메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 26, Issue 4, 1998, Pages 514-535

Hegel on justified disobedience

(1)  Tunick, Mark a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0032368540     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591798026004004     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (11)

References (87)
  • 1
    • 85033882989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This question is distinct from the question, not addressed here, of whether disobedience of a particular unjust law that is part of an otherwise just constitutional system is ever justified.
  • 2
    • 0007181471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Formulation of principles for right conduct characterizes much contemporary political philosophy, as is apparent by consulting the journals Ethics and Philosophy and Public Affairs and the work of philosophers such as John Rawls, R. M. Hare, Thomas Scanlon, and Joel Feinberg. For a discussion of principled approaches to political theory that emphasizes the ways in which principles are constrained by social practices, norms, and shared understandings, see Mark Tunick, Practices and Principles: Approaches to Ethical and Legal Judgment (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998).
    • (1998) Practices and Principles: Approaches to Ethical and Legal Judgment
    • Tunick, M.1
  • 3
    • 84881118659 scopus 로고
    • Fragment on government
    • ed. John Bowring Edinburgh: William Tait, chap. 1, sec. 43
    • Jeremy Bentham, "Fragment on Government," in Works of Jeremy Bentham, ed. John Bowring (Edinburgh: William Tait, 1838), chap. 1, sec. 43.
    • (1838) Works of Jeremy Bentham
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 4
    • 84928460327 scopus 로고
    • Presumptive benefit, fairness, and political obligation
    • summer
    • George Klosko, "Presumptive Benefit, Fairness, and Political Obligation," Philosophy and Public Affairs 16, no. 3 (summer 1987): 241-59; cf. H.L.A. Hart, "Are There Any Natural Rights?" Philosophical Review 64, no. 2 (April 1955): 175-91; and John Rawls, "Legal Obligation and the Duty of Fair Play," in Law and Philosophy, ed. Sidney Hook (New York: New York University Press, 1964), 9-10.
    • (1987) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.16 , Issue.3 , pp. 241-259
    • Klosko, G.1
  • 5
    • 0000982081 scopus 로고
    • Are there any natural rights?
    • April
    • George Klosko, "Presumptive Benefit, Fairness, and Political Obligation," Philosophy and Public Affairs 16, no. 3 (summer 1987): 241-59; cf. H.L.A. Hart, "Are There Any Natural Rights?" Philosophical Review 64, no. 2 (April 1955): 175-91; and John Rawls, "Legal Obligation and the Duty of Fair Play," in Law and Philosophy, ed. Sidney Hook (New York: New York University Press, 1964), 9-10.
    • (1955) Philosophical Review , vol.64 , Issue.2 , pp. 175-191
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 6
    • 0003294352 scopus 로고
    • Legal obligation and the duty of fair play
    • ed. Sidney Hook New York: New York University Press
    • George Klosko, "Presumptive Benefit, Fairness, and Political Obligation," Philosophy and Public Affairs 16, no. 3 (summer 1987): 241-59; cf. H.L.A. Hart, "Are There Any Natural Rights?" Philosophical Review 64, no. 2 (April 1955): 175-91; and John Rawls, "Legal Obligation and the Duty of Fair Play," in Law and Philosophy, ed. Sidney Hook (New York: New York University Press, 1964), 9-10.
    • (1964) Law and Philosophy , pp. 9-10
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 7
    • 84928839818 scopus 로고
    • Political obligation and the argument from gratitude
    • summer
    • A.D.M. Walker, "Political Obligation and the Argument from Gratitude," Philosophy and Public Affairs 17, no. 3 (summer 1988): 192, 205, 207.
    • (1988) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.17 , Issue.3 , pp. 192
    • Walker, A.D.M.1
  • 8
    • 0039393647 scopus 로고
    • In defense of the consent theory of political obligation and authority
    • April
    • Harry Beran, "In Defense of the Consent Theory of Political Obligation and Authority," Ethics 87, no. 3 (April 1977): 261-2 . In some versions, each person must consent, in others the first generation of the political community, in still others the majority. See A. J. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligation (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979), 60. Consent theories also differ about what must be consented to - particular laws? the procedures for passing laws?
    • (1977) Ethics , vol.87 , Issue.3 , pp. 261-262
    • Beran, H.1
  • 9
    • 0003890812 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Harry Beran, "In Defense of the Consent Theory of Political Obligation and Authority," Ethics 87, no. 3 (April 1977): 261-2 . In some versions, each person must consent, in others the first generation of the political community, in still others the majority. See A. J. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligation (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979), 60. Consent theories also differ about what must be consented to - particular laws? the procedures for passing laws?
    • (1979) Moral Principles and Political Obligation , pp. 60
    • Simmons, A.J.1
  • 10
    • 84860836792 scopus 로고
    • Special ties and natural duties
    • winter
    • Jeremy Waldron, "Special Ties and Natural Duties," Philosophy and Public Affairs 22, no. 1 (winter 1993): 3. See also John Rawls, Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 113-5, 334-7. For criticism of the natural duty theory, see Mark Tunick, "The Scope of Our Natural Duties," forthcoming in Journal of Social Philosophy.
    • (1993) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.22 , Issue.1 , pp. 3
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 11
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Jeremy Waldron, "Special Ties and Natural Duties," Philosophy and Public Affairs 22, no. 1 (winter 1993): 3. See also John Rawls, Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 113-5, 334-7. For criticism of the natural duty theory, see Mark Tunick, "The Scope of Our Natural Duties," forthcoming in Journal of Social Philosophy.
    • (1971) Theory of Justice , pp. 113-115
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 12
    • 85033896643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The scope of our natural duties
    • forthcoming in
    • Jeremy Waldron, "Special Ties and Natural Duties," Philosophy and Public Affairs 22, no. 1 (winter 1993): 3. See also John Rawls, Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 113-5, 334-7. For criticism of the natural duty theory, see Mark Tunick, "The Scope of Our Natural Duties," forthcoming in Journal of Social Philosophy.
    • Journal of Social Philosophy
    • Tunick, M.1
  • 13
    • 0002521640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Book of fallacies
    • ed. Bowring
    • Jeremy Bentham, Book of Fallacies, in Works, ed. Bowring, 392, 398, 459.
    • Works , pp. 392
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 14
    • 0004260323 scopus 로고
    • ed. Allen Wood, trans. H. B. Nisbet Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • G.W.F. Hegel, Philosophy of Right, ed. Allen Wood, trans. H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992). I refer to this work as PR and cite paragraph numbers and, where paragraphs are lengthy, page numbers. "Rem" refers to Remarks, and "Z," to an Addition (Zusatz). I also make reference to lecture notes taken by students of Hegel's course on the philosophy of right. In doing so, I use the following abbreviations: "Rph III": G.W.F. Hegel, Philosophie des Rechts: Die Vorlesung von 1819/20, ed. Dieter Henrich (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1983); "Rph V": G.W.F. Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie (1818-1831) [Lectures on the Philosophy of Right], 4 vols., ed. Karl-Heinz Ilting (Stuttgart-Bad-Canstatt: Friedrich Fromann, 1973), vol. 3; "Rph VI": Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie, vol. 4; "Rph VII": Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie, vol. 4. When citing from the lecture notes, references are to volume, page, and line when needed.
    • (1992) Philosophy of Right
    • Hegel, G.W.F.1
  • 15
    • 22144497496 scopus 로고
    • ed. Dieter Henrich Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp
    • G.W.F. Hegel, Philosophy of Right, ed. Allen Wood, trans. H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992). I refer to this work as PR and cite paragraph numbers and, where paragraphs are lengthy, page numbers. "Rem" refers to Remarks, and "Z," to an Addition (Zusatz). I also make reference to lecture notes taken by students of Hegel's course on the philosophy of right. In doing so, I use the following abbreviations: "Rph III": G.W.F. Hegel, Philosophie des Rechts: Die Vorlesung von 1819/20, ed. Dieter Henrich (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1983); "Rph V": G.W.F. Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie (1818-1831) [Lectures on the Philosophy of Right], 4 vols., ed. Karl-Heinz Ilting (Stuttgart-Bad-Canstatt: Friedrich Fromann, 1973), vol. 3; "Rph VI": Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie, vol. 4; "Rph VII": Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie, vol. 4. When citing from the lecture notes, references are to volume, page, and line when needed.
    • (1983) Philosophie des Rechts: Die Vorlesung von 1819/20
    • Hegel, G.W.F.1
  • 16
    • 0040859527 scopus 로고
    • Vorlesungen ueber rechtsphilosophie (1818-1831)
    • 4 vols., ed. Karl-Heinz Ilting Stuttgart-Bad-Canstatt: Friedrich Fromann
    • G.W.F. Hegel, Philosophy of Right, ed. Allen Wood, trans. H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992). I refer to this work as PR and cite paragraph numbers and, where paragraphs are lengthy, page numbers. "Rem" refers to Remarks, and "Z," to an Addition (Zusatz). I also make reference to lecture notes taken by students of Hegel's course on the philosophy of right. In doing so, I use the following abbreviations: "Rph III": G.W.F. Hegel, Philosophie des Rechts: Die Vorlesung von 1819/20, ed. Dieter Henrich (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1983); "Rph V": G.W.F. Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie (1818-1831) [Lectures on the Philosophy of Right], 4 vols., ed. Karl-Heinz Ilting (Stuttgart-Bad-Canstatt: Friedrich Fromann, 1973), vol. 3; "Rph VI": Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie, vol. 4; "Rph VII": Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie, vol. 4. When citing from the lecture notes, references are to volume, page, and line when needed.
    • (1973) Lectures on the Philosophy of Right , vol.3
    • Hegel, G.W.F.1
  • 17
    • 85033887422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • G.W.F. Hegel, Philosophy of Right, ed. Allen Wood, trans. H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992). I refer to this work as PR and cite paragraph numbers and, where paragraphs are lengthy, page numbers. "Rem" refers to Remarks, and "Z," to an Addition (Zusatz). I also make reference to lecture notes taken by students of Hegel's course on the philosophy of right. In doing so, I use the following abbreviations: "Rph III": G.W.F. Hegel, Philosophie des Rechts: Die Vorlesung von 1819/20, ed. Dieter Henrich (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1983); "Rph V": G.W.F. Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie (1818-1831) [Lectures on the Philosophy of Right], 4 vols., ed. Karl-Heinz Ilting (Stuttgart-Bad-Canstatt: Friedrich Fromann, 1973), vol. 3; "Rph VI": Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie, vol. 4; "Rph VII": Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie, vol. 4. When citing from the lecture notes, references are to volume, page, and line when needed.
    • Vorlesungen Ueber Rechtsphilosophie , vol.4
    • Hegel1
  • 18
    • 85033891799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • G.W.F. Hegel, Philosophy of Right, ed. Allen Wood, trans. H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992). I refer to this work as PR and cite paragraph numbers and, where paragraphs are lengthy, page numbers. "Rem" refers to Remarks, and "Z," to an Addition (Zusatz). I also make reference to lecture notes taken by students of Hegel's course on the philosophy of right. In doing so, I use the following abbreviations: "Rph III": G.W.F. Hegel, Philosophie des Rechts: Die Vorlesung von 1819/20, ed. Dieter Henrich (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1983); "Rph V": G.W.F. Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie (1818-1831) [Lectures on the Philosophy of Right], 4 vols., ed. Karl-Heinz Ilting (Stuttgart-Bad-Canstatt: Friedrich Fromann, 1973), vol. 3; "Rph VI": Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie, vol. 4; "Rph VII": Hegel, Vorlesungen ueber Rechtsphilosophie, vol. 4. When citing from the lecture notes, references are to volume, page, and line when needed.
    • Vorlesungen Ueber Rechtsphilosophie , vol.4
    • Hegel1
  • 19
    • 85033891955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Preface
    • See PR, Preface, pp. 20-1; PR 273 Rem; Hegel, Reason in History, trans. Robert Hartman (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1953), 37-8, 58-9.
    • PR , pp. 20-21
  • 20
    • 85033890384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rem
    • See PR, Preface, pp. 20-1; PR 273 Rem; Hegel, Reason in History, trans. Robert Hartman (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1953), 37-8, 58-9.
    • PR , vol.273
  • 21
    • 0009321781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Robert Hartman Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill
    • See PR, Preface, pp. 20-1; PR 273 Rem; Hegel, Reason in History, trans. Robert Hartman (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1953), 37-8, 58-9.
    • (1953) Reason in History , pp. 37-38
    • Hegel1
  • 22
    • 0039393702 scopus 로고
    • The actual is the rational
    • ed. David Lamb London: Croom Helm
    • See Sean Sayers, "The Actual Is the Rational," in Hegel and Modern Philosophy, ed. David Lamb (London: Croom Helm, 1987), 147-8; Andrew Arato, "A Reconstruction of Hegel's Theory of Civil Society," Cardozo Law Review 10, no. 5 (1989): 1365; Sidney Hook, "Hegel Rehabilitated?" in Encounter 24 (January 1965): 56; Ossip Flechtheim, Hegels Strafrechtstheorie [Hegel's Theory of Punishment] (Berlin :Duncker und Humblot, 1975), 16, 26, 119; Theodor Adorno, "Kritik," in Die Zeit 26 (27 June 1969); cited in Ernst Topitsch, Die Sozialphilosophie Hegels als Heilslehre und Herrschaflsideologie [Hegel's Social Philosophy as an Ideology of Mastery] (Munich: R. Piper and Co., 1981), 72; Bernard Yack, The Longing for Total Revolution (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 186-7; and the works cited in section IV.
    • (1987) Hegel and Modern Philosophy , pp. 147-148
    • Sayers, S.1
  • 23
    • 84909129098 scopus 로고
    • A reconstruction of Hegel's theory of civil society
    • See Sean Sayers, "The Actual Is the Rational," in Hegel and Modern Philosophy, ed. David Lamb (London: Croom Helm, 1987), 147-8; Andrew Arato, "A Reconstruction of Hegel's Theory of Civil Society," Cardozo Law Review 10, no. 5 (1989): 1365; Sidney Hook, "Hegel Rehabilitated?" in Encounter 24 (January 1965): 56; Ossip Flechtheim, Hegels Strafrechtstheorie [Hegel's Theory of Punishment] (Berlin :Duncker und Humblot, 1975), 16, 26, 119; Theodor Adorno, "Kritik," in Die Zeit 26 (27 June 1969); cited in Ernst Topitsch, Die Sozialphilosophie Hegels als Heilslehre und Herrschaflsideologie [Hegel's Social Philosophy as an Ideology of Mastery] (Munich: R. Piper and Co., 1981), 72; Bernard Yack, The Longing for Total Revolution (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 186-7; and the works cited in section IV.
    • (1989) Cardozo Law Review , vol.10 , Issue.5 , pp. 1365
    • Arato, A.1
  • 24
    • 85050418593 scopus 로고
    • Hegel rehabilitated?
    • January
    • See Sean Sayers, "The Actual Is the Rational," in Hegel and Modern Philosophy, ed. David Lamb (London: Croom Helm, 1987), 147-8; Andrew Arato, "A Reconstruction of Hegel's Theory of Civil Society," Cardozo Law Review 10, no. 5 (1989): 1365; Sidney Hook, "Hegel Rehabilitated?" in Encounter 24 (January 1965): 56; Ossip Flechtheim, Hegels Strafrechtstheorie [Hegel's Theory of Punishment] (Berlin :Duncker und Humblot, 1975), 16, 26, 119; Theodor Adorno, "Kritik," in Die Zeit 26 (27 June 1969); cited in Ernst Topitsch, Die Sozialphilosophie Hegels als Heilslehre und Herrschaflsideologie [Hegel's Social Philosophy as an Ideology of Mastery] (Munich: R. Piper and Co., 1981), 72; Bernard Yack, The Longing for Total Revolution (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 186-7; and the works cited in section IV.
    • (1965) Encounter , vol.24 , pp. 56
    • Hook, S.1
  • 25
    • 84926971359 scopus 로고
    • Berlin :Duncker und Humblot
    • See Sean Sayers, "The Actual Is the Rational," in Hegel and Modern Philosophy, ed. David Lamb (London: Croom Helm, 1987), 147-8; Andrew Arato, "A Reconstruction of Hegel's Theory of Civil Society," Cardozo Law Review 10, no. 5 (1989): 1365; Sidney Hook, "Hegel Rehabilitated?" in Encounter 24 (January 1965): 56; Ossip Flechtheim, Hegels Strafrechtstheorie [Hegel's Theory of Punishment] (Berlin :Duncker und Humblot, 1975), 16, 26, 119; Theodor Adorno, "Kritik," in Die Zeit 26 (27 June 1969); cited in Ernst Topitsch, Die Sozialphilosophie Hegels als Heilslehre und Herrschaflsideologie [Hegel's Social Philosophy as an Ideology of Mastery] (Munich: R. Piper and Co., 1981), 72; Bernard Yack, The Longing for Total Revolution (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 186-7; and the works cited in section IV.
    • (1975) Hegels Strafrechtstheorie [hegel's Theory of Punishment] , pp. 16
    • Flechtheim, O.1
  • 26
    • 85033898067 scopus 로고
    • Kritik
    • 27 June
    • See Sean Sayers, "The Actual Is the Rational," in Hegel and Modern Philosophy, ed. David Lamb (London: Croom Helm, 1987), 147-8; Andrew Arato, "A Reconstruction of Hegel's Theory of Civil Society," Cardozo Law Review 10, no. 5 (1989): 1365; Sidney Hook, "Hegel Rehabilitated?" in Encounter 24 (January 1965): 56; Ossip Flechtheim, Hegels Strafrechtstheorie [Hegel's Theory of Punishment] (Berlin :Duncker und Humblot, 1975), 16, 26, 119; Theodor Adorno, "Kritik," in Die Zeit 26 (27 June 1969); cited in Ernst Topitsch, Die Sozialphilosophie Hegels als Heilslehre und Herrschaflsideologie [Hegel's Social Philosophy as an Ideology of Mastery] (Munich: R. Piper and Co., 1981), 72; Bernard Yack, The Longing for Total Revolution (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 186-7; and the works cited in section IV.
    • (1969) Die Zeit , vol.26
    • Adorno, T.1
  • 27
    • 84911120913 scopus 로고
    • Munich: R. Piper and Co.
    • See Sean Sayers, "The Actual Is the Rational," in Hegel and Modern Philosophy, ed. David Lamb (London: Croom Helm, 1987), 147-8; Andrew Arato, "A Reconstruction of Hegel's Theory of Civil Society," Cardozo Law Review 10, no. 5 (1989): 1365; Sidney Hook, "Hegel Rehabilitated?" in Encounter 24 (January 1965): 56; Ossip Flechtheim, Hegels Strafrechtstheorie [Hegel's Theory of Punishment] (Berlin :Duncker und Humblot, 1975), 16, 26, 119; Theodor Adorno, "Kritik," in Die Zeit 26 (27 June 1969); cited in Ernst Topitsch, Die Sozialphilosophie Hegels als Heilslehre und Herrschaflsideologie [Hegel's Social Philosophy as an Ideology of Mastery] (Munich: R. Piper and Co., 1981), 72; Bernard Yack, The Longing for Total Revolution (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 186-7; and the works cited in section IV.
    • (1981) Die Sozialphilosophie Hegels als Heilslehre und Herrschaflsideologie [Hegel's Social Philosophy as an Ideology of Mastery] , pp. 72
    • Topitsch, E.1
  • 28
    • 0003600861 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • See Sean Sayers, "The Actual Is the Rational," in Hegel and Modern Philosophy, ed. David Lamb (London: Croom Helm, 1987), 147-8; Andrew Arato, "A Reconstruction of Hegel's Theory of Civil Society," Cardozo Law Review 10, no. 5 (1989): 1365; Sidney Hook, "Hegel Rehabilitated?" in Encounter 24 (January 1965): 56; Ossip Flechtheim, Hegels Strafrechtstheorie [Hegel's Theory of Punishment] (Berlin :Duncker und Humblot, 1975), 16, 26, 119; Theodor Adorno, "Kritik," in Die Zeit 26 (27 June 1969); cited in Ernst Topitsch, Die Sozialphilosophie Hegels als Heilslehre und Herrschaflsideologie [Hegel's Social Philosophy as an Ideology of Mastery] (Munich: R. Piper and Co., 1981), 72; Bernard Yack, The Longing for Total Revolution (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), 186-7; and the works cited in section IV.
    • (1986) The Longing for Total Revolution , pp. 186-187
    • Yack, B.1
  • 29
    • 0039985861 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
    • On one view, to say that government or authority is legitimate means simply that one has a prima facie obligation to obey it. "We have not understood what it means to be a member of political society if we suppose that political obligation is something that we might not have had and that therefore needs to be justified" (Thomas Mcpherson, Political Obligation [London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1967], 64-5; cf. Hanna Pitkin, "Obligation and Consent II," American Political Science Review 60 [1966]: 39-52, esp. 39, 48).
    • (1967) Political Obligation , pp. 64-65
    • McPherson, T.1
  • 30
    • 84971185414 scopus 로고
    • Obligation and consent II
    • On one view, to say that government or authority is legitimate means simply that one has a prima facie obligation to obey it. "We have not understood what it means to be a member of political society if we suppose that political obligation is something that we might not have had and that therefore needs to be justified" (Thomas Mcpherson, Political Obligation [London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1967], 64-5; cf. Hanna Pitkin, "Obligation and Consent II," American Political Science Review 60 [1966]: 39-52, esp. 39, 48).
    • (1966) American Political Science Review , vol.60 , pp. 39-52
    • Pitkin, H.1
  • 31
    • 85033880761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rem
    • PR 258 Rem, p. 277; Hegel adds that contract and consent are too "abstract."
    • PR , vol.258 , pp. 277
  • 32
    • 0003757613 scopus 로고
    • reprint, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Plamenatz says that consent is the "granting to another the right to act in a certain way." John Plamenatz, Consent, Freedom and Political Obligation. 2d ed. (1938; reprint, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968), 8-9.
    • (1938) Consent, Freedom and Political Obligation. 2d Ed. , pp. 8-9
    • Plamenatz, J.1
  • 33
    • 0040524013 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • See Patrick Riley, Will and Political Legitimacy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1982), 192.
    • (1982) Will and Political Legitimacy , pp. 192
    • Riley, P.1
  • 34
    • 0039985817 scopus 로고
    • Philosophy of history
    • G.W.F. Hegel [Works in Twenty Volumes], ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl Michel Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag
    • Hegel, Philosophy of History, in G.W.F. Hegel Werke in zwanzig Baenden [Works in Twenty Volumes], ed. Eva Moldenhauer and Karl Michel (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1986), vol. 12, p. 417.
    • (1986) Werke in Zwanzig Baenden , vol.12 , pp. 417
    • Hegel1
  • 35
    • 0002521640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Book of fallacies
    • ed. Bowring
    • Jeremy Bentham, Book of Fallacies, in Works, ed. Bowring, 392-3.
    • Works , pp. 392-393
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 36
    • 84880740835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hegel, Werke, vol. 7, p. 238, corresponding to PR 126.
    • Werke , vol.7 , pp. 238
    • Hegel1
  • 37
    • 85033887665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • corresponding to
    • Hegel, Werke, vol. 7, p. 238, corresponding to PR 126.
    • PR , vol.126
  • 38
    • 85033896188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rph VI: 4:338, 16-22
    • Rph VI: 4:338, 16-22. Cf. PR 280, p. 218: "Love, the ethical moment in marriage, is, as love, a feeling for actual individuals in the present, not for an abstraction."
    • PR , vol.280 , pp. 218
  • 39
    • 85033875908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See PR 151; Rph III, 124, 21-8; Mark Tunick, "Are There Natural Rights? - Hegel's Break with Kant," in Hegel on the Modern World, ed. Ardis Collins (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994); and Tunick, Practices and Principles, chap. 2.
    • PR , vol.151
  • 40
    • 85033891351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rph III, 124, 21-8
    • See PR 151; Rph III, 124, 21-8; Mark Tunick, "Are There Natural Rights? - Hegel's Break with Kant," in Hegel on the Modern World, ed. Ardis Collins (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994); and Tunick, Practices and Principles, chap. 2.
  • 41
    • 85033884064 scopus 로고
    • Are there natural rights? - Hegel's break with kant
    • ed. Ardis Collins Albany: State University of New York Press
    • See PR 151; Rph III, 124, 21-8; Mark Tunick, "Are There Natural Rights? - Hegel's Break with Kant," in Hegel on the Modern World, ed. Ardis Collins (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994); and Tunick, Practices and Principles, chap. 2.
    • (1994) Hegel on the Modern World
    • Tunick, M.1
  • 42
    • 85033875954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Tunick, Practices and Principles, chap. 2
    • See PR 151; Rph III, 124, 21-8; Mark Tunick, "Are There Natural Rights? - Hegel's Break with Kant," in Hegel on the Modern World, ed. Ardis Collins (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994); and Tunick, Practices and Principles, chap. 2.
  • 43
    • 85033888349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But not always. Hegel adheres to a principle of equality - all human beings are equally deserving of being free (as Hegel understands "free"). However, as we shall see, he opposes using the principle of equality as a basis of wealth distribution, and he does not regard all humans as having equal capacities
    • But not always. Hegel adheres to a principle of equality - all human beings are equally deserving of being free (as Hegel understands "free"). However, as we shall see, he opposes using the principle of equality as a basis of wealth distribution, and he does not regard all humans as having equal capacities.
  • 44
    • 85033874075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PR 145, p. 190. Cf. PR 3 Rem; PR 261 Rem, p. 283: "the part should be considered only with reference to the whole"; and PR 211Z, p. 243: "right . . . must be a system in itself." Cf. Michael Hardimon, "The Project of Reconciliation: Hegel's Social Philosophy," Philosophy and Public Affairs (spring 1992): 168: Hegel seeks to show that "the family, civil society, and the state formed a single coherent, intelligible system that promoted both individuality and community."
    • PR , vol.145 , pp. 190
  • 45
    • 85033902708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rem
    • PR 145, p. 190. Cf. PR 3 Rem; PR 261 Rem, p. 283: "the part should be considered only with reference to the whole"; and PR 211Z, p. 243: "right . . . must be a system in itself." Cf. Michael Hardimon, "The Project of Reconciliation: Hegel's Social Philosophy," Philosophy and Public Affairs (spring 1992): 168: Hegel seeks to show that "the family, civil society, and the state formed a single coherent, intelligible system that promoted both individuality and community."
    • PR , vol.3
  • 46
    • 85033901424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rem
    • PR 145, p. 190. Cf. PR 3 Rem; PR 261 Rem, p. 283: "the part should be considered only with reference to the whole"; and PR 211Z, p. 243: "right . . . must be a system in itself." Cf. Michael Hardimon, "The Project of Reconciliation: Hegel's Social Philosophy," Philosophy and Public Affairs (spring 1992): 168: Hegel seeks to show that "the family, civil society, and the state formed a single coherent, intelligible system that promoted both individuality and community."
    • PR , vol.261 , pp. 283
  • 47
    • 85033874084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PR 145, p. 190. Cf. PR 3 Rem; PR 261 Rem, p. 283: "the part should be considered only with reference to the whole"; and PR 211Z, p. 243: "right . . . must be a system in itself." Cf. Michael Hardimon, "The Project of Reconciliation: Hegel's Social Philosophy," Philosophy and Public Affairs (spring 1992): 168: Hegel seeks to show that "the family, civil society, and the state formed a single coherent, intelligible system that promoted both individuality and community."
    • PR , vol.211 Z , pp. 243
  • 48
    • 84933492057 scopus 로고
    • The project of reconciliation: Hegel's social philosophy
    • spring
    • PR 145, p. 190. Cf. PR 3 Rem; PR 261 Rem, p. 283: "the part should be considered only with reference to the whole"; and PR 211Z, p. 243: "right . . . must be a system in itself." Cf. Michael Hardimon, "The Project of Reconciliation: Hegel's Social Philosophy," Philosophy and Public Affairs (spring 1992): 168: Hegel seeks to show that "the family, civil society, and the state formed a single coherent, intelligible system that promoted both individuality and community."
    • (1992) Philosophy and Public Affairs , pp. 168
    • Hardimon, M.1
  • 49
    • 85033895688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PR 270Z, p. 302, my emphasis; cf. PR 272, p. 305. Also, PR, Preface, p. 11 on "enduring."
    • PR , vol.270 Z , pp. 302
  • 50
    • 85033890689 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PR 270Z, p. 302, my emphasis; cf. PR 272, p. 305. Also, PR, Preface, p. 11 on "enduring."
    • PR , vol.272 , pp. 305
  • 51
    • 85033900415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Preface
    • PR 270Z, p. 302, my emphasis; cf. PR 272, p. 305. Also, PR, Preface, p. 11 on "enduring."
    • PR , pp. 11
  • 56
    • 85033876234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rph V, 3:227, 6-11: "slavery is wrong, but necessary for certain epochs, though it is an untrue appearance"; and PR 57 Rem on slavery being "absolutely unjust."
    • See Rph V, 3:227, 6-11: "slavery is wrong, but necessary for certain epochs, though it is an untrue appearance"; and PR 57 Rem on slavery being "absolutely unjust."
  • 57
    • 85033874970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 88
    • Ibid., 88.
  • 58
    • 85033888496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I cannot take up here the highly charged controversy of whether Hegel thinks the modern state as depicted in Philosophy of Right is also the last system of ethical life we shall see, whether on his view there is an "end to history."
  • 59
    • 0007192137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, chap. 3
    • For a detailed account of Hegel's conception of freedom that fills out what can only briefly be sketched here, see Mark Tunick, Hegel's Political Philosophy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992), chap. 3.
    • (1992) Hegel's Political Philosophy
    • Tunick, M.1
  • 60
    • 84928441047 scopus 로고
    • Hegel's justification of hereditary monarchy
    • For a treatment of how Hegel develops an account of the purpose of the practice of legal punishment in order to explain certain features of the practice and criticize others, see ibid. For a discussion of his account of the institution of hereditary monarchy, see Mark Tunick, "Hegel's Justification of Hereditary Monarchy," History of Political Thought 12 (1991): 481-96.
    • (1991) History of Political Thought , vol.12 , pp. 481-496
    • Tunick, M.1
  • 62
    • 0003809273 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Examples of works that have challenged the nonliberal view of Hegel are Shlomo Avineri, Hegel's Theory of the Modern State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972); Charles Taylor, Hegel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975); Joaquim Ritter, Hegel and the French Revolution, trans. Richard Dien Winfield (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1982); and more recently, Steven B. Smith, Hegel's Critique of Liberalism: Rights in Context (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989); Alan Wood, Hegel's Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990); and Tunick, Hegel's Political Philosophy. Allen Wood does take up the question of justified disobedience briefly, and I discuss what he says below. 7
    • (1972) Hegel's Theory of the Modern State
    • Avineri, S.1
  • 63
    • 0004259337 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Examples of works that have challenged the nonliberal view of Hegel are Shlomo Avineri, Hegel's Theory of the Modern State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972); Charles Taylor, Hegel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975); Joaquim Ritter, Hegel and the French Revolution, trans. Richard Dien Winfield (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1982); and more recently, Steven B. Smith, Hegel's Critique of Liberalism: Rights in Context (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989); Alan Wood, Hegel's Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990); and Tunick, Hegel's Political Philosophy. Allen Wood does take up the question of justified disobedience briefly, and I discuss what he says below. 7
    • (1975) Hegel
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 64
    • 0039081287 scopus 로고
    • trans. Richard Dien Winfield Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • Examples of works that have challenged the nonliberal view of Hegel are Shlomo Avineri, Hegel's Theory of the Modern State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972); Charles Taylor, Hegel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975); Joaquim Ritter, Hegel and the French Revolution, trans. Richard Dien Winfield (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1982); and more recently, Steven B. Smith, Hegel's Critique of Liberalism: Rights in Context (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989); Alan Wood, Hegel's Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990); and Tunick, Hegel's Political Philosophy. Allen Wood does take up the question of justified disobedience briefly, and I discuss what he says below. 7
    • (1982) Hegel and the French Revolution
    • Ritter, J.1
  • 65
    • 0009118696 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Examples of works that have challenged the nonliberal view of Hegel are Shlomo Avineri, Hegel's Theory of the Modern State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972); Charles Taylor, Hegel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975); Joaquim Ritter, Hegel and the French Revolution, trans. Richard Dien Winfield (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1982); and more recently, Steven B. Smith, Hegel's Critique of Liberalism: Rights in Context (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989); Alan Wood, Hegel's Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990); and Tunick, Hegel's Political Philosophy. Allen Wood does take up the question of justified disobedience briefly, and I discuss what he says below. 7
    • (1989) Hegel's Critique of Liberalism: Rights in Context
    • Smith, S.B.1
  • 66
    • 0004239092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Examples of works that have challenged the nonliberal view of Hegel are Shlomo Avineri, Hegel's Theory of the Modern State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972); Charles Taylor, Hegel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975); Joaquim Ritter, Hegel and the French Revolution, trans. Richard Dien Winfield (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1982); and more recently, Steven B. Smith, Hegel's Critique of Liberalism: Rights in Context (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989); Alan Wood, Hegel's Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990); and Tunick, Hegel's Political Philosophy. Allen Wood does take up the question of justified disobedience briefly, and I discuss what he says below. 7
    • (1990) Hegel's Ethical Thought
    • Wood, A.1
  • 67
    • 0007192137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Examples of works that have challenged the nonliberal view of Hegel are Shlomo Avineri, Hegel's Theory of the Modern State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972); Charles Taylor, Hegel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975); Joaquim Ritter, Hegel and the French Revolution, trans. Richard Dien Winfield (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1982); and more recently, Steven B. Smith, Hegel's Critique of Liberalism: Rights in Context (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989); Alan Wood, Hegel's Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990); and Tunick, Hegel's Political Philosophy. Allen Wood does take up the question of justified disobedience briefly, and I discuss what he says below. 7
    • Hegel's Political Philosophy
    • Tunick1
  • 69
    • 0040524013 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Patrick Riley, Will and Political Legitimacy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982), 187.
    • (1982) Will and Political Legitimacy , pp. 187
    • Riley, P.1
  • 70
    • 0041172960 scopus 로고
    • Politics and philosophy in Kant and Hegel
    • ed. Stephen Priest Oxford: Clarendon, "to know how the citizens of a society ought to act the philosopher need do no more, in Hegel's view, than look closely at that society and the rules that govern it"
    • See also Howard Williams, "Politics and Philosophy in Kant and Hegel," in Hegel's Critique of Kant, ed. Stephen Priest (Oxford: Clarendon, 1987): "to know how the citizens of a society ought to act the philosopher need do no more, in Hegel's view, than look closely at that society and the rules that govern it" (p. 200). See also the sources referred to in note 11, above.
    • (1987) Hegel's Critique of Kant , pp. 200
    • Williams, H.1
  • 71
    • 85033896215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rem
    • PR 140 Rem, p. 175. Cf. PR 270 Rem, p. 301: "when [opinions] based on bad principles give themselves a universal existence which undermines actuality, the state must protect objective truth and the principles of ethical life."
    • PR , vol.140 , pp. 175
  • 72
    • 85033899371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rem
    • PR 140 Rem, p. 175. Cf. PR 270 Rem, p. 301: "when [opinions] based on bad principles give themselves a universal existence which undermines actuality, the state must protect objective truth and the principles of ethical life."
    • PR , vol.270 , pp. 301
  • 73
    • 85033883697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PR 215Z, p. 247; cf. Rph V, 3:414-15; PR 107, 118, 132, 260Z.
    • PR , vol.215 Z , pp. 247
  • 74
    • 85033898087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rph V, 3:414-15
    • PR 215Z, p. 247; cf. Rph V, 3:414-15; PR 107, 118, 132, 260Z.
  • 75
    • 85033878555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PR 215Z, p. 247; cf. Rph V, 3:414-15; PR 107, 118, 132, 260Z.
    • PR , vol.260 Z , pp. 107
  • 76
    • 85033879096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rph VI, 4:154, 12-21 Rem.
    • Rph VI, 4:154, 12-21. Cf. PR 270 Rem., p. 295: "A state which is strong because its organization is fully developed . . . may . . . even tolerate communities whose religion does not recognize even their direct duties towards the state (although this naturally depends on the numbers concerned)." For an extensive discussion on the reliability of the lecture notes and on Hegel's reasons for not publishing all the views he espoused in his lectures, see Tunick, Hegel's Political Philosophy, chap. 1; see also Jacques D'Hondt, Hegel in His Time, trans. John Burbridge, Nelson Roland, and Judith Levasseur (Peterboroush, Ontario: Broadview, 1988); and Karl-Heinz Ilting, "Der exoterische und der esoterische Hegel ( 1824-1831)" [The Exoteric and Esoteric Hegel], Introduction to Rph IV, pp. 45-66.
    • PR , vol.270 , pp. 295
  • 77
    • 0001715569 scopus 로고
    • trans. John Burbridge, Nelson Roland, and Judith Levasseur Peterboroush, Ontario: Broadview
    • Rph VI, 4:154, 12-21. Cf. PR 270 Rem., p. 295: "A state which is strong because its organization is fully developed . . . may . . . even tolerate communities whose religion does not recognize even their direct duties towards the state (although this naturally depends on the numbers concerned)." For an extensive discussion on the reliability of the lecture notes and on Hegel's reasons for not publishing all the views he espoused in his lectures, see Tunick, Hegel's Political Philosophy, chap. 1; see also Jacques D'Hondt, Hegel in His Time, trans. John Burbridge, Nelson Roland, and Judith Levasseur (Peterboroush, Ontario: Broadview, 1988); and Karl-Heinz Ilting, "Der exoterische und der esoterische Hegel ( 1824-1831)" [The Exoteric and Esoteric Hegel], Introduction to Rph IV, pp. 45-66.
    • (1988) Hegel in His Time
    • D'Hondt, J.1
  • 78
    • 84921908598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Der exoterische und der esoterische Hegel ( 1824-1831)
    • Introduction to Rph IV
    • Rph VI, 4:154, 12-21. Cf. PR 270 Rem., p. 295: "A state which is strong because its organization is fully developed . . . may . . . even tolerate communities whose religion does not recognize even their direct duties towards the state (although this naturally depends on the numbers concerned)." For an extensive discussion on the reliability of the lecture notes and on Hegel's reasons for not publishing all the views he espoused in his lectures, see Tunick, Hegel's Political Philosophy, chap. 1; see also Jacques D'Hondt, Hegel in His Time, trans. John Burbridge, Nelson Roland, and Judith Levasseur (Peterboroush, Ontario: Broadview, 1988); and Karl-Heinz Ilting, "Der exoterische und der esoterische Hegel ( 1824-1831)" [The Exoteric and Esoteric Hegel], Introduction to Rph IV, pp. 45-66.
    • The Exoteric and Esoteric Hegel , pp. 45-66
    • Ilting, K.-H.1
  • 79
    • 85033899192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vernunft in verwirklichung
    • Rph III
    • Dieter Henrich, "Vernunft in Verwirklichung" [The Realisation of Reason], in Rph III, p. 20. "Recht zum Aufstand" is Henrich's term; it does not appear in the lecture notes.
    • The Realisation of Reason , pp. 20
    • Henrich, D.1
  • 81
    • 85033895591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PR 265Z, p. 287.1 am reading "this satisfaction" narrowly, here, to refer to the satisfaction of welfare needs, but conceivably it can be construed more broadly.
    • PR , vol.265 Z , pp. 287
  • 82
    • 85033877599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "only in ages when the actual world is a hollow, spiritless, and unsettled existence may the individual be permitted to flee from actuality and retreat into his inner life." See also Rph V, 3:573, 27-33: where there is misery (Elend), society is in the process of breaking apart
    • Cf. PR 138Z, pp. 166-7: "only in ages when the actual world is a hollow, spiritless, and unsettled existence may the individual be permitted to flee from actuality and retreat into his inner life." See also Rph V, 3:573, 27-33: where there is misery (Elend), society is in the process of breaking apart.
    • PR , vol.138 Z , pp. 166-167
  • 83
    • 0004239092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wood, Hegel's Ethical Thought, 105. Wood notes, however, that it is "positively inconsistent with Hegel's explicit account of legal obligation to maintain that we are obligated by right to obey unjust laws." His is one of the few statements acknowledging that Hegel in principle would be open to justified disobedience.
    • Hegel's Ethical Thought , pp. 105
    • Wood1
  • 84
    • 0040578764 scopus 로고
    • Review of Hegels Heidelberger rechtsphilosophie
    • See Ludwig Siep, "Review of Hegels Heidelberger Rechtsphilosophie," Hegel-Studien 20 (1985): 291.
    • (1985) Hegel-Studien , vol.20 , pp. 291
    • Siep, L.1
  • 87
    • 0004344619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philosophical anarchists argue that "we are not specially bound to obey our laws or to support our government simply because they are ours" - Simmons, Moral Principles, 194.
    • Moral Principles , pp. 194
    • Simmons1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.