메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 17, Issue 5-6, 1998, Pages 481-507

The purposiveness of law: Two concepts of representation in the European Union

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0032277784     PISSN: 01675249     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/3505186     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (14)

References (34)
  • 1
    • 84882554388 scopus 로고
    • Sovereignty, Democracy, Subsidiarity
    • Neil MacCormick, "Sovereignty, Democracy, Subsidiarity", Rechtstheorie 25 (1994), p. 290.
    • (1994) Rechtstheorie , vol.25 , pp. 290
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 2
    • 0031488661 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democracy, Subsidiarity and Citizenship in the 'European Commonwealth'
    • N. MacCormick, "Democracy, Subsidiarity and Citizenship in the 'European Commonwealth' ", Law and Philosophy 16 (1997), p. 339.
    • (1997) Law and Philosophy , vol.16 , pp. 339
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 4
    • 84979126215 scopus 로고
    • Beyond the Sovereign State
    • N. MacCormick, "Beyond the Sovereign State", The Modern Law Review 56 (1993) 1, p. 12.
    • (1993) The Modern Law Review , vol.56 , Issue.1 , pp. 12
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 6
    • 0004281766 scopus 로고
    • trans. and ed. Julian H. Franklin Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Jean Bodin, On Sovereignty, trans. and ed. Julian H. Franklin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), p. 4.
    • (1992) On Sovereignty , pp. 4
    • Bodin, J.1
  • 7
    • 0003458347 scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, As this definition makes clear, Parliament's "sovereignty" is conferred or conditioned by the constitution
    • This contradiction is already present in Dicey. According to classical British constitutional doctrine, "The principle of Parliamentary sovereignty means neither more nor less than this, namely, that Parliament . . . has, under the English constitution, the right to make or unmake any law whatever; and, further, that no person or body is recognised by the law of England as having a right to override or set aside the legislation of Parliament" (A.C. Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1982), p. 3). As this definition makes clear, Parliament's "sovereignty" is conferred or conditioned by the constitution.
    • (1982) Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution , pp. 3
    • Dicey, A.C.1
  • 8
    • 0042842998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Both Hart and Kelsen are wary of discussing the concept of law in terms of the relation between a manifold of norms and a purpose. In Kelsen's case, this move is explicitly motivated by the desire to avoid any form of legal foundationalism; despite significant differences between Kelsen's "basic norm" and Hart's "rule of recognition", the same motivation seems to govern Hart's analysis of the concept of law. The problem with this approach is, first, that law is a purposive order and, second, that the concept of legitimate power is conceptually bound up with the purposiveness of law. Rather than sidestepping this issue, a principal task for legal philosophy consists in giving a non-foundationalist account of legitimate power and of the law's purposiveness. Such, precisely, is the aim of this paper.
  • 9
    • 0042342078 scopus 로고
    • v. The European Union Treaty"
    • Extracts from "Brunner et al. v. The European Union Treaty", Common Market Law Review 31 (1994), p. 252. The complete translation of the decision is in CMLR 1 (1994), pp. 57 ff.
    • (1994) Common Market Law Review , vol.31 , pp. 252
    • Brunner1
  • 10
    • 33746340010 scopus 로고
    • Extracts from "Brunner et al. v. The European Union Treaty", Common Market Law Review 31 (1994), p. 252. The complete translation of the decision is in CMLR 1 (1994), pp. 57 ff.
    • (1994) CMLR , vol.1
  • 11
    • 0042342102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The English version inaccurately translates this expression as "principle of accountability." I shall not discuss here the similarities and differences between the Court's and Kelsen's employment of the term "imputation"
    • Ibid., p. 256. The English version inaccurately translates this expression as "principle of accountability." I shall not discuss here the similarities and differences between the Court's and Kelsen's employment of the term "imputation."
    • CMLR , pp. 256
  • 12
    • 0042842981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The English version incorrectly translates Staatenverbund as "federation of states." The inimitable German reads: ". . . keinen sich auf einer europäisches Staatsvolk stützenden Staat"
    • Ibid., p. 258. The English version incorrectly translates Staatenverbund as "federation of states." The inimitable German reads: ". . . keinen sich auf einer europäisches Staatsvolk stützenden Staat."
    • CMLR , pp. 258
  • 16
    • 0041840893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • choice of the term "function" is unfortunate, as the contemporary reader is tempted to equate it with "functionalism" or "instrumentalism." This equation is mistaken, for Cassirer conceives the term function as being synonymous with relation. Significantly, Part I of Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbegriff, the work in which he introduces this term, is titled
    • Retrospectively, Cassirer's choice of the term "function" is unfortunate, as the contemporary reader is tempted to equate it with "functionalism" or "instrumentalism." This equation is mistaken, for Cassirer conceives the term function as being synonymous with relation. Significantly, Part I of Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbegriff, the work in which he introduces this term, is titled "Thing-Concepts and Relation-Concepts."
    • Thing-Concepts and Relation-Concepts
    • Cassirer1
  • 18
    • 0041840922 scopus 로고
    • puts it, "the difficulty arises in these cases through mixing up 'is' and 'is called'." trans. by G.E.M. Anscombe, ed. by G. H. von Wright, R. Rhees and G.E.M. Anscombe Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • As Wittgenstein puts it, "the difficulty arises in these cases through mixing up 'is' and 'is called'." (Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, trans. by G.E.M. Anscombe, ed. by G. H. von Wright, R. Rhees and G.E.M. Anscombe (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1978), p. 88.) Wittgenstein's views on rule-following and Cassirer's analysis of functions coincide in decisive aspects. In Het verdwijnpunt van de wet. Een essay over de symboolwerking van wetgeving (Zwolle, The Netherlands: Tjeenk Willink, 1997), Bert van Roermund has linked Wittgenstein's analyses of rule-following to Erwin Panofsky's studies on the "point of view" in art, which build on Cassirer's concept of functional representation.
    • (1978) Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics , pp. 88
    • Wittgenstein1
  • 19
    • 0042342091 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • views on rule-following and Cassirer's analysis of functions coincide in decisive aspects. Zwolle, The Netherlands: Tjeenk Willink, Bert van Roermund has linked Wittgenstein's analyses of rule-following to Erwin Panofsky's studies on the "point of view" in art, which build on Cassirer's concept of functional representation
    • As Wittgenstein puts it, "the difficulty arises in these cases through mixing up 'is' and 'is called'." (Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, trans. by G.E.M. Anscombe, ed. by G. H. von Wright, R. Rhees and G.E.M. Anscombe (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1978), p. 88.) Wittgenstein's views on rule-following and Cassirer's analysis of functions coincide in decisive aspects. In Het verdwijnpunt van de wet. Een essay over de symboolwerking van wetgeving (Zwolle, The Netherlands: Tjeenk Willink, 1997), Bert van Roermund has linked Wittgenstein's analyses of rule-following to Erwin Panofsky's studies on the "point of view" in art, which build on Cassirer's concept of functional representation.
    • (1997) Het Verdwijnpunt Van de Wet. een Essay over de Symboolwerking Van Wetgeving
    • Wittgenstein1
  • 22
    • 0041840912 scopus 로고
    • Die Sprache und der Aufbau der Gegenstandswelt
    • E.W. Orth and J.M. Krois (eds.), Hamburg: Felix Meiner
    • E. Cassirer, "Die Sprache und der Aufbau der Gegenstandswelt", in E.W. Orth and J.M. Krois (eds.), Symbol, Technik, Sprache (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1995), p. 122.
    • (1995) Symbol, Technik, Sprache , pp. 122
    • Cassirer, E.1
  • 25
    • 0042842996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As will be clear from the following discussion, reifying the general also implies reifying the particular
    • Cassirer, Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbegriff, p. 34. As will be clear from the following discussion, reifying the general also implies reifying the particular.
    • Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbegriff , pp. 34
    • Cassirer1
  • 28
    • 0010346622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sovereignty and Symbolization
    • to appear in
    • See my "Sovereignty and Symbolization", to appear in Rechtstheorie 28 (1997), p. 3.
    • (1997) Rechtstheorie , vol.28 , pp. 3
  • 29
    • 0041840920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Case 294/83, ECR (1986), p. 1365
    • Case 294/83, ECR (1986), p. 1365.
  • 30
    • 0041340254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for example, remark that the autonomy of European law "does not rest on determinate metajuridical conceptions about European unity, federal structures or something of the sort. On the contrary, the ECJ conceives its mandate as a call to interpret Community law in view of the far-reaching integration objectives set out in articles 2 and 3 of the Community Treaty" Alphen aan den Rijn, The Netherlands: Samsom H.D. Tjeenk Willink
    • R. Barents and L.J. Brinkhorst, for example, remark that the autonomy of European law "does not rest on determinate metajuridical conceptions about European unity, federal structures or something of the sort. On the contrary, the ECJ conceives its mandate as a call to interpret Community law in view of the far-reaching integration objectives set out in articles 2 and 3 of the Community Treaty" (Grondlijnen van Europees recht (Alphen aan den Rijn, The Netherlands: Samsom H.D. Tjeenk Willink, 1996), p. 242).
    • (1996) Grondlijnen Van Europees Recht , pp. 242
    • Barents, R.1    Brinkhorst, L.J.2
  • 31
    • 0042842995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Case 26/62, ECR (1963), p. 12. Significantly, the Van Gend & Loos decision unfolds the two-way dynamic of representation: the Court derives its decision from the EC Treaty and it also ascribes a specific meaning to the Treaty
    • Case 26/62, ECR (1963), p. 12. Significantly, the Van Gend & Loos decision unfolds the two-way dynamic of representation: the Court derives its decision from the EC Treaty and it also ascribes a specific meaning to the Treaty.
  • 33
    • 84982531124 scopus 로고
    • The Maastricht-Urteil: Sovereignty Now
    • N. MacCormick, "The Maastricht-Urteil: Sovereignty Now", European Law Journal 1 (3) (1995), p. 265.
    • (1995) European Law Journal , vol.1 , Issue.3 , pp. 265
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 34
    • 0009137576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aldershot: Avebury Press, Although they understand such normative orders as incompatible with the idea of sovereignty, the coexistence in identical space of different normative orders presupposes the different viewpoints assured by sovereignty
    • This, I think, is what Bankowski and Scott call "overlapping normative orders" in "The European Union?" in R. Bellamy (ed.), Constitutionalism, Democracy and Sovereignty: American and European Perspectives (Aldershot: Avebury Press, 1996). Although they understand such normative orders as incompatible with the idea of sovereignty, the coexistence in identical space of different normative orders presupposes the different viewpoints assured by sovereignty.
    • (1996) Constitutionalism, Democracy and Sovereignty: American and European Perspectives
    • Bellamy, R.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.