메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 19, Issue 2, 1998, Pages 142-166

Aristotle and natural law

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0032220714     PISSN: 0143781X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (23)

References (145)
  • 1
    • 0003220212 scopus 로고
    • Natural law
    • New York
    • 1 The Greek term employed by Aristotle should strictly speaking be translated into English as 'natural justice'. Leo Strauss prefers the expression 'natural right'. Cf. L. Strauss, 'Natural Law', International Encyclopedia of Social Sciences, 11 (New York, 1968), p. 81. As M. Salomon Shellens has pointed out, however, many commentators employ the phrase 'natural law' in this context. Cf. M. Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', Natural Law Forum, 72 (1959), p. 74. We shall use the terms 'natural justice' and 'natural law' interchangeably.
    • (1968) International Encyclopedia of Social Sciences , vol.11 , pp. 81
    • Strauss, L.1
  • 2
    • 84921648698 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle on natural law
    • We shall use the terms 'natural justice' and 'natural law' interchangeably
    • 1 The Greek term employed by Aristotle should strictly speaking be translated into English as 'natural justice'. Leo Strauss prefers the expression 'natural right'. Cf. L. Strauss, 'Natural Law', International Encyclopedia of Social Sciences, 11 (New York, 1968), p. 81. As M. Salomon Shellens has pointed out, however, many commentators employ the phrase 'natural law' in this context. Cf. M. Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', Natural Law Forum, 72 (1959), p. 74. We shall use the terms 'natural justice' and 'natural law' interchangeably.
    • (1959) Natural Law Forum , vol.72 , pp. 74
    • Salomon Shellens, M.1
  • 4
    • 0003687723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago, We shall focus here on the Nicomachean Ethics and ignore the Rhetoric. The value of the latter as a source for Aristotle's views on natural law is a matter of dispute
    • 3 L. Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1974), p. 156. We shall focus here on the Nicomachean Ethics and ignore the Rhetoric. The value of the latter as a source for Aristotle's views on natural law is a matter of dispute. See C.J. Friedrich, The Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective (Chicago, 1963), p. 23 n. 16; M. Hamburger, Morals and Law: The Growth of Aristotle's Legal Theory (New Haven, 1951), p. 39 n. 1 and p. 65; H. Kelsen, 'The Foundations of the Theory of Natural Law', in H. Kelsen, Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy (Dordrecht, 1973), p. 135; D.G. Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Subdivisions of Particular Justice', Classical Review, VIII (1894), pp. 185-92, esp. p. 191 n. 2; D.G. Ritchie, Natural Law and Natural Rights (London, 1895), p. 30; P.E. Sigmund, Natural Law in Political Thought (Cambridge, MA, 1971), pp. 9-10; J.W. Salmond, 'The Law of Nature', The Law Quarterly Review, 42 (1895), p. 127; F.D. Wormuth, 'Aristotle on Law', in Essays in Political Theory, ed. M.R. Konvitz and A.E. Murphy (New York, 1948).
    • (1974) Natural Right and History , pp. 156
    • Strauss, L.1
  • 5
    • 0010143436 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • 3 L. Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1974), p. 156. We shall focus here on the Nicomachean Ethics and ignore the Rhetoric. The value of the latter as a source for Aristotle's views on natural law is a matter of dispute. See C.J. Friedrich, The Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective (Chicago, 1963), p. 23 n. 16; M. Hamburger, Morals and Law: The Growth of Aristotle's Legal Theory (New Haven, 1951), p. 39 n. 1 and p. 65; H. Kelsen, 'The Foundations of the Theory of Natural Law', in H. Kelsen, Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy (Dordrecht, 1973), p. 135; D.G. Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Subdivisions of Particular Justice', Classical Review, VIII (1894), pp. 185-92, esp. p. 191 n. 2; D.G. Ritchie, Natural Law and Natural Rights (London, 1895), p. 30; P.E. Sigmund, Natural Law in Political Thought (Cambridge, MA, 1971), pp. 9-10; J.W. Salmond, 'The Law of Nature', The Law Quarterly Review, 42 (1895), p. 127; F.D. Wormuth, 'Aristotle on Law', in Essays in Political Theory, ed. M.R. Konvitz and A.E. Murphy (New York, 1948).
    • (1963) The Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective , Issue.16 , pp. 23
    • Friedrich, C.J.1
  • 6
    • 0010091596 scopus 로고
    • New Haven
    • 3 L. Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1974), p. 156. We shall focus here on the Nicomachean Ethics and ignore the Rhetoric. The value of the latter as a source for Aristotle's views on natural law is a matter of dispute. See C.J. Friedrich, The Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective (Chicago, 1963), p. 23 n. 16; M. Hamburger, Morals and Law: The Growth of Aristotle's Legal Theory (New Haven, 1951), p. 39 n. 1 and p. 65; H. Kelsen, 'The Foundations of the Theory of Natural Law', in H. Kelsen, Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy (Dordrecht, 1973), p. 135; D.G. Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Subdivisions of Particular Justice', Classical Review, VIII (1894), pp. 185-92, esp. p. 191 n. 2; D.G. Ritchie, Natural Law and Natural Rights (London, 1895), p. 30; P.E. Sigmund, Natural Law in Political Thought (Cambridge, MA, 1971), pp. 9-10; J.W. Salmond, 'The Law of Nature', The Law Quarterly Review, 42 (1895), p. 127; F.D. Wormuth, 'Aristotle on Law', in Essays in Political Theory, ed. M.R. Konvitz and A.E. Murphy (New York, 1948).
    • (1951) Morals and Law: The Growth of Aristotle's Legal Theory , Issue.1 , pp. 39
    • Hamburger, M.1
  • 7
    • 0003330106 scopus 로고
    • The foundations of the theory of natural law
    • H. Kelsen, Dordrecht
    • 3 L. Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1974), p. 156. We shall focus here on the Nicomachean Ethics and ignore the Rhetoric. The value of the latter as a source for Aristotle's views on natural law is a matter of dispute. See C.J. Friedrich, The Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective (Chicago, 1963), p. 23 n. 16; M. Hamburger, Morals and Law: The Growth of Aristotle's Legal Theory (New Haven, 1951), p. 39 n. 1 and p. 65; H. Kelsen, 'The Foundations of the Theory of Natural Law', in H. Kelsen, Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy (Dordrecht, 1973), p. 135; D.G. Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Subdivisions of Particular Justice', Classical Review, VIII (1894), pp. 185-92, esp. p. 191 n. 2; D.G. Ritchie, Natural Law and Natural Rights (London, 1895), p. 30; P.E. Sigmund, Natural Law in Political Thought (Cambridge, MA, 1971), pp. 9-10; J.W. Salmond, 'The Law of Nature', The Law Quarterly Review, 42 (1895), p. 127; F.D. Wormuth, 'Aristotle on Law', in Essays in Political Theory, ed. M.R. Konvitz and A.E. Murphy (New York, 1948).
    • (1973) Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy , pp. 135
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 8
    • 84894346289 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's subdivisions of particular justice
    • 3 L. Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1974), p. 156. We shall focus here on the Nicomachean Ethics and ignore the Rhetoric. The value of the latter as a source for Aristotle's views on natural law is a matter of dispute. See C.J. Friedrich, The Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective (Chicago, 1963), p. 23 n. 16; M. Hamburger, Morals and Law: The Growth of Aristotle's Legal Theory (New Haven, 1951), p. 39 n. 1 and p. 65; H. Kelsen, 'The Foundations of the Theory of Natural Law', in H. Kelsen, Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy (Dordrecht, 1973), p. 135; D.G. Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Subdivisions of Particular Justice', Classical Review, VIII (1894), pp. 185-92, esp. p. 191 n. 2; D.G. Ritchie, Natural Law and Natural Rights (London, 1895), p. 30; P.E. Sigmund, Natural Law in Political Thought (Cambridge, MA, 1971), pp. 9-10; J.W. Salmond, 'The Law of Nature', The Law Quarterly Review, 42 (1895), p. 127; F.D. Wormuth, 'Aristotle on Law', in Essays in Political Theory, ed. M.R. Konvitz and A.E. Murphy (New York, 1948).
    • (1894) Classical Review , vol.8 , Issue.2 , pp. 185-192
    • Ritchie, D.G.1
  • 9
    • 0010192044 scopus 로고
    • London
    • 3 L. Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1974), p. 156. We shall focus here on the Nicomachean Ethics and ignore the Rhetoric. The value of the latter as a source for Aristotle's views on natural law is a matter of dispute. See C.J. Friedrich, The Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective (Chicago, 1963), p. 23 n. 16; M. Hamburger, Morals and Law: The Growth of Aristotle's Legal Theory (New Haven, 1951), p. 39 n. 1 and p. 65; H. Kelsen, 'The Foundations of the Theory of Natural Law', in H. Kelsen, Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy (Dordrecht, 1973), p. 135; D.G. Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Subdivisions of Particular Justice', Classical Review, VIII (1894), pp. 185-92, esp. p. 191 n. 2; D.G. Ritchie, Natural Law and Natural Rights (London, 1895), p. 30; P.E. Sigmund, Natural Law in Political Thought (Cambridge, MA, 1971), pp. 9-10; J.W. Salmond, 'The Law of Nature', The Law Quarterly Review, 42 (1895), p. 127; F.D. Wormuth, 'Aristotle on Law', in Essays in Political Theory, ed. M.R. Konvitz and A.E. Murphy (New York, 1948).
    • (1895) Natural Law and Natural Rights , pp. 30
    • Ritchie, D.G.1
  • 10
    • 0003941001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA
    • 3 L. Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1974), p. 156. We shall focus here on the Nicomachean Ethics and ignore the Rhetoric. The value of the latter as a source for Aristotle's views on natural law is a matter of dispute. See C.J. Friedrich, The Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective (Chicago, 1963), p. 23 n. 16; M. Hamburger, Morals and Law: The Growth of Aristotle's Legal Theory (New Haven, 1951), p. 39 n. 1 and p. 65; H. Kelsen, 'The Foundations of the Theory of Natural Law', in H. Kelsen, Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy (Dordrecht, 1973), p. 135; D.G. Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Subdivisions of Particular Justice', Classical Review, VIII (1894), pp. 185-92, esp. p. 191 n. 2; D.G. Ritchie, Natural Law and Natural Rights (London, 1895), p. 30; P.E. Sigmund, Natural Law in Political Thought (Cambridge, MA, 1971), pp. 9-10; J.W. Salmond, 'The Law of Nature', The Law Quarterly Review, 42 (1895), p. 127; F.D. Wormuth, 'Aristotle on Law', in Essays in Political Theory, ed. M.R. Konvitz and A.E. Murphy (New York, 1948).
    • (1971) Natural Law in Political Thought , pp. 9-10
    • Sigmund, P.E.1
  • 11
    • 0003357729 scopus 로고
    • The law of nature
    • 3 L. Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1974), p. 156. We shall focus here on the Nicomachean Ethics and ignore the Rhetoric. The value of the latter as a source for Aristotle's views on natural law is a matter of dispute. See C.J. Friedrich, The Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective (Chicago, 1963), p. 23 n. 16; M. Hamburger, Morals and Law: The Growth of Aristotle's Legal Theory (New Haven, 1951), p. 39 n. 1 and p. 65; H. Kelsen, 'The Foundations of the Theory of Natural Law', in H. Kelsen, Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy (Dordrecht, 1973), p. 135; D.G. Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Subdivisions of Particular Justice', Classical Review, VIII (1894), pp. 185-92, esp. p. 191 n. 2; D.G. Ritchie, Natural Law and Natural Rights (London, 1895), p. 30; P.E. Sigmund, Natural Law in Political Thought (Cambridge, MA, 1971), pp. 9-10; J.W. Salmond, 'The Law of Nature', The Law Quarterly Review, 42 (1895), p. 127; F.D. Wormuth, 'Aristotle on Law', in Essays in Political Theory, ed. M.R. Konvitz and A.E. Murphy (New York, 1948).
    • (1895) The Law Quarterly Review , vol.42 , pp. 127
    • Salmond, J.W.1
  • 12
    • 0003349717 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle on law
    • ed. M.R. Konvitz and A.E. Murphy New York
    • 3 L. Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago, 1974), p. 156. We shall focus here on the Nicomachean Ethics and ignore the Rhetoric. The value of the latter as a source for Aristotle's views on natural law is a matter of dispute. See C.J. Friedrich, The Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective (Chicago, 1963), p. 23 n. 16; M. Hamburger, Morals and Law: The Growth of Aristotle's Legal Theory (New Haven, 1951), p. 39 n. 1 and p. 65; H. Kelsen, 'The Foundations of the Theory of Natural Law', in H. Kelsen, Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy (Dordrecht, 1973), p. 135; D.G. Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Subdivisions of Particular Justice', Classical Review, VIII (1894), pp. 185-92, esp. p. 191 n. 2; D.G. Ritchie, Natural Law and Natural Rights (London, 1895), p. 30; P.E. Sigmund, Natural Law in Political Thought (Cambridge, MA, 1971), pp. 9-10; J.W. Salmond, 'The Law of Nature', The Law Quarterly Review, 42 (1895), p. 127; F.D. Wormuth, 'Aristotle on Law', in Essays in Political Theory, ed. M.R. Konvitz and A.E. Murphy (New York, 1948).
    • (1948) Essays in Political Theory
    • Wormuth, F.D.1
  • 16
    • 4243454704 scopus 로고
    • trans. W.D. Ross Oxford, Book V, ch. 7
    • 7 Aristotle, Ethica Nicomachea, trans. W.D. Ross (Oxford, 1925), Book V, ch. 7, 1134b-1135a.
    • (1925) Ethica Nicomachea
    • Aristotle1
  • 17
    • 0003612184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Avebury
    • 8 The account presented here is based on an earlier discussion of Aristotle's views in Tony Burns, Natural Law and Political Ideology in the Philosophy of Hegel (Avebury, 1996), pp. 3, 14, 67-8. See also A.P. d'Entrèves, Natural Law (London, 2nd edn., 1974), pp. 174-5; H. Rommen, The Natural Law (New York, 1979), p. 247.
    • (1996) Natural Law and Political Ideology in the Philosophy of Hegel , pp. 3
    • Burns, T.1
  • 18
    • 0004323605 scopus 로고
    • London, 2nd edn.
    • 8 The account presented here is based on an earlier discussion of Aristotle's views in Tony Burns, Natural Law and Political Ideology in the Philosophy of Hegel (Avebury, 1996), pp. 3, 14, 67-8. See also A.P. d'Entrèves, Natural Law (London, 2nd edn., 1974), pp. 174-5; H. Rommen, The Natural Law (New York, 1979), p. 247.
    • (1974) Natural Law , pp. 174-175
    • D'Entrèves, A.P.1
  • 19
    • 0003682732 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • 8 The account presented here is based on an earlier discussion of Aristotle's views in Tony Burns, Natural Law and Political Ideology in the Philosophy of Hegel (Avebury, 1996), pp. 3, 14, 67-8. See also A.P. d'Entrèves, Natural Law (London, 2nd edn., 1974), pp. 174-5; H. Rommen, The Natural Law (New York, 1979), p. 247.
    • (1979) The Natural Law , pp. 247
    • Rommen, H.1
  • 20
    • 84972592548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Natural right and Aristotle's understanding of justice
    • 9 See B. Yack, 'Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice, Political Theory, 18(2) (1990), p. 219; also M. Salomon, 'Le droit natural chez Aristote', Archives de philosophie de droit et de sociologie juridique, 7 (1937), pp. 120-7; Salmond, 'The Law of Nature', p. 127 n. 2.
    • (1990) Political Theory , vol.18 , Issue.2 , pp. 219
    • Yack, B.1
  • 21
    • 84972592548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Le droit natural chez Aristote
    • 9 See B. Yack, 'Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice, Political Theory, 18(2) (1990), p. 219; also M. Salomon, 'Le droit natural chez Aristote', Archives de philosophie de droit et de sociologie juridique, 7 (1937), pp. 120-7; Salmond, 'The Law of Nature', p. 127 n. 2.
    • (1937) Archives de Philosophie de Droit et de Sociologie Juridique , vol.7 , pp. 120-127
    • Salomon, M.1
  • 22
    • 84972592548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 9 See B. Yack, 'Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice, Political Theory, 18(2) (1990), p. 219; also M. Salomon, 'Le droit natural chez Aristote', Archives de philosophie de droit et de sociologie juridique, 7 (1937), pp. 120-7; Salmond, 'The Law of Nature', p. 127 n. 2.
    • The Law of Nature , Issue.2 , pp. 127
    • Salmond1
  • 23
    • 0010186866 scopus 로고
    • The terms lus Positivism and Signum Positivum in twelfth century scholasticism
    • 10 The term 'positive law' (or its equivalent) actually comes into use for the first time in the medieval period. See D. van den Eynde, 'The Terms lus Positivism and Signum Positivum in Twelfth Century Scholasticism', Franciscan Studies, 9 (1949), pp. 41-9; S. Kuttner, 'Sur les origines du terme droit positif', Revue historique de droit français et étranger, 15 (1936), pp. 728 ff.; W. Ullmann, Law and Politics in the Middle Ages (London, 1975), p. 62. Most commentators acknowledge that the features which at this time come to be associated with positive law are those which Aristotle associates with legal or conventional justice.
    • (1949) Franciscan Studies , vol.9 , pp. 41-49
    • Van Den Eynde, D.1
  • 24
    • 0010153103 scopus 로고
    • Sur les origines du terme droit positif
    • 10 The term 'positive law' (or its equivalent) actually comes into use for the first time in the medieval period. See D. van den Eynde, 'The Terms lus Positivism and Signum Positivum in Twelfth Century Scholasticism', Franciscan Studies, 9 (1949), pp. 41-9; S. Kuttner, 'Sur les origines du terme droit positif', Revue historique de droit français et étranger, 15 (1936), pp. 728 ff.; W. Ullmann, Law and Politics in the Middle Ages (London, 1975), p. 62. Most commentators acknowledge that the features which at this time come to be associated with positive law are those which Aristotle associates with legal or conventional justice.
    • (1936) Revue Historique de Droit Français et Étranger , vol.15 , pp. 728
    • Kuttner, S.1
  • 25
    • 0010205834 scopus 로고
    • London
    • 10 The term 'positive law' (or its equivalent) actually comes into use for the first time in the medieval period. See D. van den Eynde, 'The Terms lus Positivism and Signum Positivum in Twelfth Century Scholasticism', Franciscan Studies, 9 (1949), pp. 41-9; S. Kuttner, 'Sur les origines du terme droit positif', Revue historique de droit français et étranger, 15 (1936), pp. 728 ff.; W. Ullmann, Law and Politics in the Middle Ages (London, 1975), p. 62. Most commentators acknowledge that the features which at this time come to be associated with positive law are those which Aristotle associates with legal or conventional justice.
    • (1975) Law and Politics in the Middle Ages , pp. 62
    • Ullmann, W.1
  • 27
    • 0010153104 scopus 로고
    • ed. Sir Ernest Barker Oxford, Appendix II
    • 12 As Ernest Barker points out, Aristotle employs the terms 'justice' and 'injustice' in a sense which is as much 'moral' or 'ethical' as it is 'legal'. See Aristotle, The Politics of Aristotle, ed. Sir Ernest Barker (Oxford, 1946), Appendix II, p. 362.
    • (1946) The Politics of Aristotle , pp. 362
    • Aristotle1
  • 29
    • 0003402357 scopus 로고
    • London
    • 14 See for example J.M. Brennan, The Open Texture of Moral Concepts (London, 1977), pp. 36, 41, 44-57, 64-5, 119; J. Kovesi, Moral Notions (London, 1967), pp. 26, 32, 109; and L.A. Jost, 'A Descriptivist Reading of Aristotle's Treatment of Virtue Terms', Apeiron, 13 (1979), pp. 41-8.
    • (1977) The Open Texture of Moral Concepts , pp. 36
    • Brennan, J.M.1
  • 30
    • 0010089297 scopus 로고
    • London
    • 14 See for example J.M. Brennan, The Open Texture of Moral Concepts (London, 1977), pp. 36, 41, 44-57, 64-5, 119; J. Kovesi, Moral Notions (London, 1967), pp. 26, 32, 109; and L.A. Jost, 'A Descriptivist Reading of Aristotle's Treatment of Virtue Terms', Apeiron, 13 (1979), pp. 41-8.
    • (1967) Moral Notions , pp. 26
    • Kovesi, J.1
  • 31
    • 0010148296 scopus 로고
    • A descriptivist reading of Aristotle's treatment of virtue terms
    • 14 See for example J.M. Brennan, The Open Texture of Moral Concepts (London, 1977), pp. 36, 41, 44-57, 64-5, 119; J. Kovesi, Moral Notions (London, 1967), pp. 26, 32, 109; and L.A. Jost, 'A Descriptivist Reading of Aristotle's Treatment of Virtue Terms', Apeiron, 13 (1979), pp. 41-8.
    • (1979) Apeiron , vol.13 , pp. 41-48
    • Jost, L.A.1
  • 35
    • 0010097018 scopus 로고
    • ed. H. Jackson Cambridge
    • 18 Aristotle, IIEPI ΔIKAIOΣΥTNHΣ: The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, ed. H. Jackson (Cambridge, 1879), p. 39. Similar translations are offered by Chase, in Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, ed. D.P. Chase (London, n.d.), p. 145, and by Thompson in Aristotle, The Ethics of Aristotle, ed. J.A.K. Thompson (Harmondsworth, 1965), p. 157, although Thompson refers to two 'forms' of political justice rather than two 'kinds'. See also Yack, 'Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice', p. 220.
    • (1879) IIEPI ΔIKAIOΣΥTNHΣ: The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle , pp. 39
    • Aristotle1
  • 36
    • 0010192046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. D.P. Chase (London, n.d.)
    • 18 Aristotle, IIEPI ΔIKAIOΣΥTNHΣ: The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, ed. H. Jackson (Cambridge, 1879), p. 39. Similar translations are offered by Chase, in Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, ed. D.P. Chase (London, n.d.), p. 145, and by Thompson in Aristotle, The Ethics of Aristotle, ed. J.A.K. Thompson (Harmondsworth, 1965), p. 157, although Thompson refers to two 'forms' of political justice rather than two 'kinds'. See also Yack, 'Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice', p. 220.
    • The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle , pp. 145
    • Aristotle1
  • 37
    • 0010196196 scopus 로고
    • ed. J.A.K. Thompson Harmondsworth, although Thompson refers to two 'forms' of political justice rather than two 'kinds'
    • 18 Aristotle, IIEPI ΔIKAIOΣΥTNHΣ: The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, ed. H. Jackson (Cambridge, 1879), p. 39. Similar translations are offered by Chase, in Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, ed. D.P. Chase (London, n.d.), p. 145, and by Thompson in Aristotle, The Ethics of Aristotle, ed. J.A.K. Thompson (Harmondsworth, 1965), p. 157, although Thompson refers to two 'forms' of political justice rather than two 'kinds'. See also Yack, 'Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice', p. 220.
    • (1965) The Ethics of Aristotle , pp. 157
    • Aristotle1
  • 38
    • 0004336682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 18 Aristotle, IIEPI ΔIKAIOΣΥTNHΣ: The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, ed. H. Jackson (Cambridge, 1879), p. 39. Similar translations are offered by Chase, in Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, ed. D.P. Chase (London, n.d.), p. 145, and by Thompson in Aristotle, The Ethics of Aristotle, ed. J.A.K. Thompson (Harmondsworth, 1965), p. 157, although Thompson refers to two 'forms' of political justice rather than two 'kinds'. See also Yack, 'Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice', p. 220.
    • Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice , pp. 220
    • Yack1
  • 39
    • 0010100356 scopus 로고
    • ed. Sir Alexander Grant 2 vols., London, 4th edn.
    • 19 A similar translation to that of Ross is provided by both Grant, in Aristotle, The Ethics of Aristotle: Illustrated with Essays and Notes, ed. Sir Alexander Grant (2 vols., London, 4th edn., 1885), Vol. II, p. 126, and by Stewart, in J.A. Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle (2 vols., Oxford, 1892), p. 492, although Grant and Stewart employ the word 'element' rather than the word 'part'.
    • (1885) The Ethics of Aristotle: Illustrated with Essays and Notes , vol.2 , pp. 126
    • Aristotle1
  • 40
    • 0010099764 scopus 로고
    • 2 vols., Oxford, although Grant and Stewart employ the word 'element' rather than the word 'part'
    • 19 A similar translation to that of Ross is provided by both Grant, in Aristotle, The Ethics of Aristotle: Illustrated with Essays and Notes, ed. Sir Alexander Grant (2 vols., London, 4th edn., 1885), Vol. II, p. 126, and by Stewart, in J.A. Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle (2 vols., Oxford, 1892), p. 492, although Grant and Stewart employ the word 'element' rather than the word 'part'.
    • (1892) Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle , pp. 492
    • Stewart, J.A.1
  • 42
    • 0003410276 scopus 로고
    • London
    • 21 Aristotle does not make any explicit distinction between legal or conventional justice which is customary and legal or conventional justice which is enacted. It would, however, be a mistake to assume automatically, as W.A. Robson appears to do, that he must have had customary law in mind here. Cf. W.A. Robson, Civilisation and the Growth of Law (London, 1935), pp. 243-5. As G.R. Morrow has pointed out, the idea of 'legislation' is evidently by no means alien either to Greek political experience or to Greek political thought at this time. Cf. G.R. Morrow, 'Plato and the Law of Nature', in Essays in Political Theory, ed. Konvitz and Murphy, pp. 38 ff. This is, indeed, evident from what Aristotle himself has to say about such matters in Chapter 9 of Book 10 of the Ethics.
    • (1935) Civilisation and the Growth of Law , pp. 243-245
    • Robson, W.A.1
  • 43
    • 70450071138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plato and the law of nature
    • ed. Konvitz and Murphy, This is, indeed, evident from what Aristotle himself has to say about such matters in Chapter 9 of Book 10 of the Ethics
    • 21 Aristotle does not make any explicit distinction between legal or conventional justice which is customary and legal or conventional justice which is enacted. It would, however, be a mistake to assume automatically, as W.A. Robson appears to do, that he must have had customary law in mind here. Cf. W.A. Robson, Civilisation and the Growth of Law (London, 1935), pp. 243-5. As G.R. Morrow has pointed out, the idea of 'legislation' is evidently by no means alien either to Greek political experience or to Greek political thought at this time. Cf. G.R. Morrow, 'Plato and the Law of Nature', in Essays in Political Theory, ed. Konvitz and Murphy, pp. 38 ff. This is, indeed, evident from what Aristotle himself has to say about such matters in Chapter 9 of Book 10 of the Ethics.
    • Essays in Political Theory , pp. 38
    • Morrow, G.R.1
  • 46
    • 4243461874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 24 Aristotle, Ethics, V, 1, 1129a, 34-43.
    • Ethics , vol.5 , Issue.1
    • Aristotle1
  • 47
    • 0009139466 scopus 로고
    • Equality
    • 25 Modern discussion of the concept of justice has been greatly influenced by what Aristotle has to say about the subject. See, for example, I. Berlin, 'Equality', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56 (1955-6); W.T. Blackstone, 'On the Meaning and Justification of the Equality Principle', Ethics (1967); M. Ginsberg, 'The Concept of Justice', in On Justice in Society (Harmondsworth, 1971); H. Kelsen, What is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1957); H. Kelsen, A General Theory of Law and the State (New York, 1961); D. Lloyd, The Idea of Law (Harmondsworth, 1972); Ch. Perelman, The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument (London, 1963); Ch. Perelman, Justice, Law and Argument: Essays on Legal and Moral Reasoning (Dordrecht, 1980); D.D. Raphael, Problems of Political Philosophy (London, 1970); A. Ross, 'The Idea of Justice', in On Law and Justice (London, 1958); B. Williams, 'The Idea of Equality', in Philosophy, Politics and Society, ed. P. Laslett and W.G. Runciman, second series (1967).
    • (1955) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.56
    • Berlin, I.1
  • 48
    • 71149095963 scopus 로고
    • On the meaning and justification of the equality principle
    • 25 Modern discussion of the concept of justice has been greatly influenced by what Aristotle has to say about the subject. See, for example, I. Berlin, 'Equality', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56 (1955-6); W.T. Blackstone, 'On the Meaning and Justification of the Equality Principle', Ethics (1967); M. Ginsberg, 'The Concept of Justice', in On Justice in Society (Harmondsworth, 1971); H. Kelsen, What is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1957); H. Kelsen, A General Theory of Law and the State (New York, 1961); D. Lloyd, The Idea of Law (Harmondsworth, 1972); Ch. Perelman, The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument (London, 1963); Ch. Perelman, Justice, Law and Argument: Essays on Legal and Moral Reasoning (Dordrecht, 1980); D.D. Raphael, Problems of Political Philosophy (London, 1970); A. Ross, 'The Idea of Justice', in On Law and Justice (London, 1958); B. Williams, 'The Idea of Equality', in Philosophy, Politics and Society, ed. P. Laslett and W.G. Runciman, second series (1967).
    • (1967) Ethics
    • Blackstone, W.T.1
  • 49
    • 0010186867 scopus 로고
    • The concept of justice
    • Harmondsworth
    • 25 Modern discussion of the concept of justice has been greatly influenced by what Aristotle has to say about the subject. See, for example, I. Berlin, 'Equality', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56 (1955-6); W.T. Blackstone, 'On the Meaning and Justification of the Equality Principle', Ethics (1967); M. Ginsberg, 'The Concept of Justice', in On Justice in Society (Harmondsworth, 1971); H. Kelsen, What is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1957); H. Kelsen, A General Theory of Law and the State (New York, 1961); D. Lloyd, The Idea of Law (Harmondsworth, 1972); Ch. Perelman, The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument (London, 1963); Ch. Perelman, Justice, Law and Argument: Essays on Legal and Moral Reasoning (Dordrecht, 1980); D.D. Raphael, Problems of Political Philosophy (London, 1970); A. Ross, 'The Idea of Justice', in On Law and Justice (London, 1958); B. Williams, 'The Idea of Equality', in Philosophy, Politics and Society, ed. P. Laslett and W.G. Runciman, second series (1967).
    • (1971) On Justice in Society
    • Ginsberg, M.1
  • 50
    • 0003835486 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley and Los Angeles
    • 25 Modern discussion of the concept of justice has been greatly influenced by what Aristotle has to say about the subject. See, for example, I. Berlin, 'Equality', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56 (1955-6); W.T. Blackstone, 'On the Meaning and Justification of the Equality Principle', Ethics (1967); M. Ginsberg, 'The Concept of Justice', in On Justice in Society (Harmondsworth, 1971); H. Kelsen, What is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1957); H. Kelsen, A General Theory of Law and the State (New York, 1961); D. Lloyd, The Idea of Law (Harmondsworth, 1972); Ch. Perelman, The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument (London, 1963); Ch. Perelman, Justice, Law and Argument: Essays on Legal and Moral Reasoning (Dordrecht, 1980); D.D. Raphael, Problems of Political Philosophy (London, 1970); A. Ross, 'The Idea of Justice', in On Law and Justice (London, 1958); B. Williams, 'The Idea of Equality', in Philosophy, Politics and Society, ed. P. Laslett and W.G. Runciman, second series (1967).
    • (1957) What Is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 51
    • 0003516637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York
    • 25 Modern discussion of the concept of justice has been greatly influenced by what Aristotle has to say about the subject. See, for example, I. Berlin, 'Equality', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56 (1955-6); W.T. Blackstone, 'On the Meaning and Justification of the Equality Principle', Ethics (1967); M. Ginsberg, 'The Concept of Justice', in On Justice in Society (Harmondsworth, 1971); H. Kelsen, What is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1957); H. Kelsen, A General Theory of Law and the State (New York, 1961); D. Lloyd, The Idea of Law (Harmondsworth, 1972); Ch. Perelman, The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument (London, 1963); Ch. Perelman, Justice, Law and Argument: Essays on Legal and Moral Reasoning (Dordrecht, 1980); D.D. Raphael, Problems of Political Philosophy (London, 1970); A. Ross, 'The Idea of Justice', in On Law and Justice (London, 1958); B. Williams, 'The Idea of Equality', in Philosophy, Politics and Society, ed. P. Laslett and W.G. Runciman, second series (1967).
    • (1961) A General Theory of Law and the State
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 52
    • 0005702394 scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth
    • 25 Modern discussion of the concept of justice has been greatly influenced by what Aristotle has to say about the subject. See, for example, I. Berlin, 'Equality', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56 (1955-6); W.T. Blackstone, 'On the Meaning and Justification of the Equality Principle', Ethics (1967); M. Ginsberg, 'The Concept of Justice', in On Justice in Society (Harmondsworth, 1971); H. Kelsen, What is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1957); H. Kelsen, A General Theory of Law and the State (New York, 1961); D. Lloyd, The Idea of Law (Harmondsworth, 1972); Ch. Perelman, The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument (London, 1963); Ch. Perelman, Justice, Law and Argument: Essays on Legal and Moral Reasoning (Dordrecht, 1980); D.D. Raphael, Problems of Political Philosophy (London, 1970); A. Ross, 'The Idea of Justice', in On Law and Justice (London, 1958); B. Williams, 'The Idea of Equality', in Philosophy, Politics and Society, ed. P. Laslett and W.G. Runciman, second series (1967).
    • (1972) The Idea of Law
    • Lloyd, D.1
  • 53
    • 0003441856 scopus 로고
    • London
    • 25 Modern discussion of the concept of justice has been greatly influenced by what Aristotle has to say about the subject. See, for example, I. Berlin, 'Equality', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56 (1955-6); W.T. Blackstone, 'On the Meaning and Justification of the Equality Principle', Ethics (1967); M. Ginsberg, 'The Concept of Justice', in On Justice in Society (Harmondsworth, 1971); H. Kelsen, What is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1957); H. Kelsen, A General Theory of Law and the State (New York, 1961); D. Lloyd, The Idea of Law (Harmondsworth, 1972); Ch. Perelman, The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument (London, 1963); Ch. Perelman, Justice, Law and Argument: Essays on Legal and Moral Reasoning (Dordrecht, 1980); D.D. Raphael, Problems of Political Philosophy (London, 1970); A. Ross, 'The Idea of Justice', in On Law and Justice (London, 1958); B. Williams, 'The Idea of Equality', in Philosophy, Politics and Society, ed. P. Laslett and W.G. Runciman, second series (1967).
    • (1963) The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument
    • Perelman, Ch.1
  • 54
    • 0003572303 scopus 로고
    • Dordrecht
    • 25 Modern discussion of the concept of justice has been greatly influenced by what Aristotle has to say about the subject. See, for example, I. Berlin, 'Equality', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56 (1955-6); W.T. Blackstone, 'On the Meaning and Justification of the Equality Principle', Ethics (1967); M. Ginsberg, 'The Concept of Justice', in On Justice in Society (Harmondsworth, 1971); H. Kelsen, What is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1957); H. Kelsen, A General Theory of Law and the State (New York, 1961); D. Lloyd, The Idea of Law (Harmondsworth, 1972); Ch. Perelman, The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument (London, 1963); Ch. Perelman, Justice, Law and Argument: Essays on Legal and Moral Reasoning (Dordrecht, 1980); D.D. Raphael, Problems of Political Philosophy (London, 1970); A. Ross, 'The Idea of Justice', in On Law and Justice (London, 1958); B. Williams, 'The Idea of Equality', in Philosophy, Politics and Society, ed. P. Laslett and W.G. Runciman, second series (1967).
    • (1980) Justice, Law and Argument: Essays on Legal and Moral Reasoning
    • Perelman, Ch.1
  • 55
    • 0002325079 scopus 로고
    • London
    • 25 Modern discussion of the concept of justice has been greatly influenced by what Aristotle has to say about the subject. See, for example, I. Berlin, 'Equality', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56 (1955-6); W.T. Blackstone, 'On the Meaning and Justification of the Equality Principle', Ethics (1967); M. Ginsberg, 'The Concept of Justice', in On Justice in Society (Harmondsworth, 1971); H. Kelsen, What is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1957); H. Kelsen, A General Theory of Law and the State (New York, 1961); D. Lloyd, The Idea of Law (Harmondsworth, 1972); Ch. Perelman, The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument (London, 1963); Ch. Perelman, Justice, Law and Argument: Essays on Legal and Moral Reasoning (Dordrecht, 1980); D.D. Raphael, Problems of Political Philosophy (London, 1970); A. Ross, 'The Idea of Justice', in On Law and Justice (London, 1958); B. Williams, 'The Idea of Equality', in Philosophy, Politics and Society, ed. P. Laslett and W.G. Runciman, second series (1967).
    • (1970) Problems of Political Philosophy
    • Raphael, D.D.1
  • 56
    • 0010151436 scopus 로고
    • The idea of justice
    • London
    • 25 Modern discussion of the concept of justice has been greatly influenced by what Aristotle has to say about the subject. See, for example, I. Berlin, 'Equality', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56 (1955-6); W.T. Blackstone, 'On the Meaning and Justification of the Equality Principle', Ethics (1967); M. Ginsberg, 'The Concept of Justice', in On Justice in Society (Harmondsworth, 1971); H. Kelsen, What is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1957); H. Kelsen, A General Theory of Law and the State (New York, 1961); D. Lloyd, The Idea of Law (Harmondsworth, 1972); Ch. Perelman, The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument (London, 1963); Ch. Perelman, Justice, Law and Argument: Essays on Legal and Moral Reasoning (Dordrecht, 1980); D.D. Raphael, Problems of Political Philosophy (London, 1970); A. Ross, 'The Idea of Justice', in On Law and Justice (London, 1958); B. Williams, 'The Idea of Equality', in Philosophy, Politics and Society, ed. P. Laslett and W.G. Runciman, second series (1967).
    • (1958) On Law and Justice
    • Ross, A.1
  • 57
    • 0003337617 scopus 로고
    • The idea of equality
    • ed. P. Laslett and W.G. Runciman, second series
    • 25 Modern discussion of the concept of justice has been greatly influenced by what Aristotle has to say about the subject. See, for example, I. Berlin, 'Equality', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56 (1955-6); W.T. Blackstone, 'On the Meaning and Justification of the Equality Principle', Ethics (1967); M. Ginsberg, 'The Concept of Justice', in On Justice in Society (Harmondsworth, 1971); H. Kelsen, What is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays by Hans Kelsen (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1957); H. Kelsen, A General Theory of Law and the State (New York, 1961); D. Lloyd, The Idea of Law (Harmondsworth, 1972); Ch. Perelman, The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument (London, 1963); Ch. Perelman, Justice, Law and Argument: Essays on Legal and Moral Reasoning (Dordrecht, 1980); D.D. Raphael, Problems of Political Philosophy (London, 1970); A. Ross, 'The Idea of Justice', in On Law and Justice (London, 1958); B. Williams, 'The Idea of Equality', in Philosophy, Politics and Society, ed. P. Laslett and W.G. Runciman, second series (1967).
    • (1967) Philosophy, Politics and Society
    • Williams, B.1
  • 58
    • 0010192048 scopus 로고
    • A conspectus of the meaning of 'epieikeia' and 'aequitas' in history
    • Washington
    • 26 That the English term 'equity' is derived ultimately (via the Latin aequitas) from the Greek το ιοον has been maintained by a number of commentators. See for example, J. Riley, 'A Conspectus of the Meaning of 'Epieikeia' and 'Aequitas' in History', in The History, Nature and Uses of Epieikeia in Moral Theology (Washington, 1948), pp. 10-18. For a different view see H. Maine, Ancient Law, ed. J.H. Morgan (London, 1965), p. 34. It is important to note that the English word 'equity' used in this more general sense must be distinguished from the same term when it is used to translate the Greek word επιεικεια (epieikeia). Aristotle discusses επιεικεια in Book V, Chapter 10 of the Ethics. Equity in this more technical sense is a legal principle which is supposed to deal with 'problem cases' which call for 'a correction of the law where it is defective owing to its universality' (Aristotle, Ethics, V, 10, 1137b, 25-30).
    • (1948) The History, Nature and Uses of Epieikeia in Moral Theology , pp. 10-18
    • Riley, J.1
  • 59
    • 0010179030 scopus 로고
    • ed. J.H. Morgan London
    • 26 That the English term 'equity' is derived ultimately (via the Latin aequitas) from the Greek το ιοον has been maintained by a number of commentators. See for example, J. Riley, 'A Conspectus of the Meaning of 'Epieikeia' and 'Aequitas' in History', in The History, Nature and Uses of Epieikeia in Moral Theology (Washington, 1948), pp. 10-18. For a different view see H. Maine, Ancient Law, ed. J.H. Morgan (London, 1965), p. 34. It is important to note that the English word 'equity' used in this more general sense must be distinguished from the same term when it is used to translate the Greek word επιεικεια (epieikeia). Aristotle discusses επιεικεια in Book V, Chapter 10 of the Ethics. Equity in this more technical sense is a legal principle which is supposed to deal with 'problem cases' which call for 'a correction of the law where it is defective owing to its universality' (Aristotle, Ethics, V, 10, 1137b, 25-30).
    • (1965) Ancient Law , pp. 34
    • Maine, H.1
  • 60
    • 4243452264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 26 That the English term 'equity' is derived ultimately (via the Latin aequitas) from the Greek το ιοον has been maintained by a number of commentators. See for example, J. Riley, 'A Conspectus of the Meaning of 'Epieikeia' and 'Aequitas' in History', in The History, Nature and Uses of Epieikeia in Moral Theology (Washington, 1948), pp. 10-18. For a different view see H. Maine, Ancient Law, ed. J.H. Morgan (London, 1965), p. 34. It is important to note that the English word 'equity' used in this more general sense must be distinguished from the same term when it is used to translate the Greek word επιεικεια (epieikeia). Aristotle discusses επιεικεια in Book V, Chapter 10 of the Ethics. Equity in this more technical sense is a legal principle which is supposed to deal with 'problem cases' which call for 'a correction of the law where it is defective owing to its universality' (Aristotle, Ethics, V, 10, 1137b, 25-30).
    • Ethics , vol.5 , Issue.10
    • Aristotle1
  • 61
    • 0010153106 scopus 로고
    • ed. A.H. Campbell Edinburgh
    • 27 G. del Vecchio, Justice, ed. A.H. Campbell (Edinburgh, 1952), pp. 84, 187-8. For additional references to Aristotle and the Golden Rule see: Hamburger, Morals and Law, p. 52; W.A. Spooner, 'Golden Rule', in The Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics, ed. G. Hastings (New York, 1914), Vol. 6, p. 311; J.O. Hertzler, 'On Golden Rules', International Journal of Ethics, 44 (1934), p. 423.
    • (1952) Justice , pp. 84
    • Del Vecchio, G.1
  • 62
    • 0010212383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 27 G. del Vecchio, Justice, ed. A.H. Campbell (Edinburgh, 1952), pp. 84, 187-8. For additional references to Aristotle and the Golden Rule see: Hamburger, Morals and Law, p. 52; W.A. Spooner, 'Golden Rule', in The Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics, ed. G. Hastings (New York, 1914), Vol. 6, p. 311; J.O. Hertzler, 'On Golden Rules', International Journal of Ethics, 44 (1934), p. 423.
    • Morals and Law , pp. 52
    • Hamburger1
  • 63
    • 0010157597 scopus 로고
    • Golden rule
    • ed. G. Hastings New York
    • 27 G. del Vecchio, Justice, ed. A.H. Campbell (Edinburgh, 1952), pp. 84, 187-8. For additional references to Aristotle and the Golden Rule see: Hamburger, Morals and Law, p. 52; W.A. Spooner, 'Golden Rule', in The Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics, ed. G. Hastings (New York, 1914), Vol. 6, p. 311; J.O. Hertzler, 'On Golden Rules', International Journal of Ethics, 44 (1934), p. 423.
    • (1914) The Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics , vol.6 , pp. 311
    • Spooner, W.A.1
  • 64
    • 60950511544 scopus 로고
    • On golden rules
    • 27 G. del Vecchio, Justice, ed. A.H. Campbell (Edinburgh, 1952), pp. 84, 187-8. For additional references to Aristotle and the Golden Rule see: Hamburger, Morals and Law, p. 52; W.A. Spooner, 'Golden Rule', in The Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics, ed. G. Hastings (New York, 1914), Vol. 6, p. 311; J.O. Hertzler, 'On Golden Rules', International Journal of Ethics, 44 (1934), p. 423.
    • (1934) International Journal of Ethics , vol.44 , pp. 423
    • Hertzler, J.O.1
  • 68
    • 0010203449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 31 See also Snyder, 'Natural Law and Equity', pp. 33-43; Ch. Perelman, 'Equity and the Rule of Justice', in Justice, Law and Argument, pp. 34-43; D.D. Raphael, 'Equality and Equity', Philosophy, 21 (1946); F. W. Maitland, Equity: A Course of Lectures (New York, 1936); H. Maine, 'Law of Nature and Equity', in Ancient Law; C.K. Allen, 'Equity', in Law in the Making (Oxford, 1951); P. Vinogradoff, Historical Jurisprudence (Oxford, 1923), Vol. 2, ch. III, s. 5; P. Vinogradoff, Common Sense in Law (London, 1943), Chs. VIII and IX.
    • Natural Law and Equity , pp. 33-43
    • Snyder1
  • 69
    • 0010155627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Equity and the rule of justice
    • 31 See also Snyder, 'Natural Law and Equity', pp. 33-43; Ch. Perelman, 'Equity and the Rule of Justice', in Justice, Law and Argument, pp. 34-43; D.D. Raphael, 'Equality and Equity', Philosophy, 21 (1946); F. W. Maitland, Equity: A Course of Lectures (New York, 1936); H. Maine, 'Law of Nature and Equity', in Ancient Law; C.K. Allen, 'Equity', in Law in the Making (Oxford, 1951); P. Vinogradoff, Historical Jurisprudence (Oxford, 1923), Vol. 2, ch. III, s. 5; P. Vinogradoff, Common Sense in Law (London, 1943), Chs. VIII and IX.
    • Justice, Law and Argument , pp. 34-43
    • Perelman, Ch.1
  • 70
    • 0010186868 scopus 로고
    • Equality and equity
    • 31 See also Snyder, 'Natural Law and Equity', pp. 33-43; Ch. Perelman, 'Equity and the Rule of Justice', in Justice, Law and Argument, pp. 34-43; D.D. Raphael, 'Equality and Equity', Philosophy, 21 (1946); F. W. Maitland, Equity: A Course of Lectures (New York, 1936); H. Maine, 'Law of Nature and Equity', in Ancient Law; C.K. Allen, 'Equity', in Law in the Making (Oxford, 1951); P. Vinogradoff, Historical Jurisprudence (Oxford, 1923), Vol. 2, ch. III, s. 5; P. Vinogradoff, Common Sense in Law (London, 1943), Chs. VIII and IX.
    • (1946) Philosophy , vol.21
    • Raphael, D.D.1
  • 71
    • 0010203450 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • 31 See also Snyder, 'Natural Law and Equity', pp. 33-43; Ch. Perelman, 'Equity and the Rule of Justice', in Justice, Law and Argument, pp. 34-43; D.D. Raphael, 'Equality and Equity', Philosophy, 21 (1946); F. W. Maitland, Equity: A Course of Lectures (New York, 1936); H. Maine, 'Law of Nature and Equity', in Ancient Law; C.K. Allen, 'Equity', in Law in the Making (Oxford, 1951); P. Vinogradoff, Historical Jurisprudence (Oxford, 1923), Vol. 2, ch. III, s. 5; P. Vinogradoff, Common Sense in Law (London, 1943), Chs. VIII and IX.
    • (1936) Equity: A Course of Lectures
    • Maitland, F.W.1
  • 72
    • 0010186869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law of nature and equity
    • 31 See also Snyder, 'Natural Law and Equity', pp. 33-43; Ch. Perelman, 'Equity and the Rule of Justice', in Justice, Law and Argument, pp. 34-43; D.D. Raphael, 'Equality and Equity', Philosophy, 21 (1946); F. W. Maitland, Equity: A Course of Lectures (New York, 1936); H. Maine, 'Law of Nature and Equity', in Ancient Law; C.K. Allen, 'Equity', in Law in the Making (Oxford, 1951); P. Vinogradoff, Historical Jurisprudence (Oxford, 1923), Vol. 2, ch. III, s. 5; P. Vinogradoff, Common Sense in Law (London, 1943), Chs. VIII and IX.
    • Ancient Law
    • Maine, H.1
  • 73
    • 0010143441 scopus 로고
    • Equity
    • Oxford
    • 31 See also Snyder, 'Natural Law and Equity', pp. 33-43; Ch. Perelman, 'Equity and the Rule of Justice', in Justice, Law and Argument, pp. 34-43; D.D. Raphael, 'Equality and Equity', Philosophy, 21 (1946); F. W. Maitland, Equity: A Course of Lectures (New York, 1936); H. Maine, 'Law of Nature and Equity', in Ancient Law; C.K. Allen, 'Equity', in Law in the Making (Oxford, 1951); P. Vinogradoff, Historical Jurisprudence (Oxford, 1923), Vol. 2, ch. III, s. 5; P. Vinogradoff, Common Sense in Law (London, 1943), Chs. VIII and IX.
    • (1951) Law in the Making
    • Allen, C.K.1
  • 74
    • 0010092922 scopus 로고
    • Oxford, ch. III
    • 31 See also Snyder, 'Natural Law and Equity', pp. 33-43; Ch. Perelman, 'Equity and the Rule of Justice', in Justice, Law and Argument, pp. 34-43; D.D. Raphael, 'Equality and Equity', Philosophy, 21 (1946); F. W. Maitland, Equity: A Course of Lectures (New York, 1936); H. Maine, 'Law of Nature and Equity', in Ancient Law; C.K. Allen, 'Equity', in Law in the Making (Oxford, 1951); P. Vinogradoff, Historical Jurisprudence (Oxford, 1923), Vol. 2, ch. III, s. 5; P. Vinogradoff, Common Sense in Law (London, 1943), Chs. VIII and IX.
    • (1923) Historical Jurisprudence , vol.2 , pp. 5
    • Vinogradoff, P.1
  • 75
    • 84909089807 scopus 로고
    • London, Chs. VIII and IX
    • 31 See also Snyder, 'Natural Law and Equity', pp. 33-43; Ch. Perelman, 'Equity and the Rule of Justice', in Justice, Law and Argument, pp. 34-43; D.D. Raphael, 'Equality and Equity', Philosophy, 21 (1946); F. W. Maitland, Equity: A Course of Lectures (New York, 1936); H. Maine, 'Law of Nature and Equity', in Ancient Law; C.K. Allen, 'Equity', in Law in the Making (Oxford, 1951); P. Vinogradoff, Historical Jurisprudence (Oxford, 1923), Vol. 2, ch. III, s. 5; P. Vinogradoff, Common Sense in Law (London, 1943), Chs. VIII and IX.
    • (1943) Common Sense in Law
    • Vinogradoff, P.1
  • 78
    • 0004306795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 34 In the terminology of the Hegelian philosophy, a precept of natural justice is an 'essence'. This principle manifests itself, or 'appears', in a particular society at a particular time, as a principle of positive law or 'political justice'. To see a principle of positive law as a 'synthesis' of an 'essence' with an 'appearance' is to see it in its 'actuality'. See Burns, Natural Law and Political Ideology, pp. 66-74.
    • Natural Law and Political Ideology , pp. 66-74
    • Burns1
  • 79
    • 0003553021 scopus 로고
    • New York. This Aristotelian insight is preserved in the philosophy of Hegel, who states that although natural law 'is distinct from positive law', nevertheless to 'pervert their difference into an opposition and a contradiction would be a gross misunderstanding'
    • 35 E. Barker, The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle (New York, 1959), p. 327. This Aristotelian insight is preserved in the philosophy of Hegel, who states that although natural law 'is distinct from positive law', nevertheless to 'pervert their difference into an opposition and a contradiction would be a gross misunderstanding'. Cf. G.W.F. Hegel, Philosophy of Right, ed. T.M. Knox (Oxford, 1979), Para. 3, p. 16.
    • (1959) The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle , pp. 327
    • Barker, E.1
  • 80
    • 0004260323 scopus 로고
    • ed. T.M. Knox Oxford, Para. 3
    • 35 E. Barker, The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle (New York, 1959), p. 327. This Aristotelian insight is preserved in the philosophy of Hegel, who states that although natural law 'is distinct from positive law', nevertheless to 'pervert their difference into an opposition and a contradiction would be a gross misunderstanding'. Cf. G.W.F. Hegel, Philosophy of Right, ed. T.M. Knox (Oxford, 1979), Para. 3, p. 16.
    • (1979) Philosophy of Right , pp. 16
    • Hegel, G.W.F.1
  • 81
    • 0004306795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 36 See Burns, Natural Law and Political Ideology, pp. 18-19; also J. Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford, 1980), pp. 28, 281; Kelsen, General Theory of Law and the State, p. 416.
    • Natural Law and Political Ideology , pp. 18-19
    • Burns1
  • 82
    • 0003529325 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • 36 See Burns, Natural Law and Political Ideology, pp. 18-19; also J. Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford, 1980), pp. 28, 281; Kelsen, General Theory of Law and the State, p. 416.
    • (1980) Natural Law and Natural Rights , pp. 28
    • Finnis, J.1
  • 83
    • 0003516637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 36 See Burns, Natural Law and Political Ideology, pp. 18-19; also J. Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford, 1980), pp. 28, 281; Kelsen, General Theory of Law and the State, p. 416.
    • General Theory of Law and the State , pp. 416
    • Kelsen1
  • 84
    • 0010143442 scopus 로고
    • ed. J.H. Burns and H.L.A. Hart London
    • 37 Bentham would insist that it is logically impossible for a positive law to permit the act of murder. See J. Bentham, A Comment on the Commentaries, ed. J.H. Burns and H.L.A. Hart (London, 1977), pp. 42-3. See also Burns, Natural Law and Political Ideology, pp. 36-7.
    • (1977) A Comment on the Commentaries , pp. 42-43
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 85
    • 0004306795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 37 Bentham would insist that it is logically impossible for a positive law to permit the act of murder. See J. Bentham, A Comment on the Commentaries, ed. J.H. Burns and H.L.A. Hart (London, 1977), pp. 42-3. See also Burns, Natural Law and Political Ideology, pp. 36-7.
    • Natural Law and Political Ideology , pp. 36-37
    • Burns1
  • 86
    • 4243408174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 38 Aristotle, Ethics, X, 9, 1180b, 10-25; Aristotle, Analytica Posteriora ed. G.R.G. Mure (Oxford, 1926), I, 4, 73b, 25-30; ibid., I, 33, 88b, 30-35.
    • Ethics , vol.10 , Issue.9
    • Aristotle1
  • 87
    • 4243455382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. G.R.G. Mure Oxford
    • 38 Aristotle, Ethics, X, 9, 1180b, 10-25; Aristotle, Analytica Posteriora ed. G.R.G. Mure (Oxford, 1926), I, 4, 73b, 25-30; ibid., I, 33, 88b, 30-35.
    • (1926) Analytica Posteriora , vol.1 , Issue.4
    • Aristotle1
  • 88
    • 4243444721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 38 Aristotle, Ethics, X, 9, 1180b, 10-25; Aristotle, Analytica Posteriora ed. G.R.G. Mure (Oxford, 1926), I, 4, 73b, 25-30; ibid., I, 33, 88b, 30-35.
    • Analytica Posteriora , vol.1 , Issue.33
  • 90
    • 0003426112 scopus 로고
    • Washington
    • 40 For this interpretation of the notion of 'changeability' in relation to natural law see R.F. Begin, Natural Law and Positive Law (Washington, 1959), p. 88; J. Maritain, Man and the State (Chicago, 1958), pp. 84-94; Strauss, Natural Right and History, pp. 9, 97-8.
    • (1959) Natural Law and Positive Law , pp. 88
    • Begin, R.F.1
  • 91
    • 0004232462 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • 40 For this interpretation of the notion of 'changeability' in relation to natural law see R.F. Begin, Natural Law and Positive Law (Washington, 1959), p. 88; J. Maritain, Man and the State (Chicago, 1958), pp. 84-94; Strauss, Natural Right and History, pp. 9, 97-8.
    • (1958) Man and the State , pp. 84-94
    • Maritain, J.1
  • 92
    • 0003687723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 40 For this interpretation of the notion of 'changeability' in relation to natural law see R.F. Begin, Natural Law and Positive Law (Washington, 1959), p. 88; J. Maritain, Man and the State (Chicago, 1958), pp. 84-94; Strauss, Natural Right and History, pp. 9, 97-8.
    • Natural Right and History , pp. 9
    • Strauss1
  • 93
    • 4243454214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 41 Aristotle, Ethics, I, 4, 1095b, 1-5.
    • Ethics , vol.1 , Issue.4
    • Aristotle1
  • 94
    • 79959088390 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 42 Aristotle, Ethics, VI, 3, 1139b, 15-25; also VI, 5, 1140a, 30-5; VI, 6, 1140b, 30-5.
    • Ethics , vol.6 , Issue.3
    • Aristotle1
  • 95
    • 4243413562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 42 Aristotle, Ethics, VI, 3, 1139b, 15-25; also VI, 5, 1140a, 30-5; VI, 6, 1140b, 30-5.
    • Ethics , vol.6 , Issue.5
  • 96
    • 4243413562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 42 Aristotle, Ethics, VI, 3, 1139b, 15-25; also VI, 5, 1140a, 30-5; VI, 6, 1140b, 30-5.
    • Ethics , vol.6 , Issue.6
  • 97
    • 4243408174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 43 Aristotle, Ethics, X, 9, 1180b, 10-25; Aristotle, Analytica Posteriora, ed. Mure, I, 33, 88b, 30-5.
    • Ethics , vol.10 , Issue.9
    • Aristotle1
  • 98
    • 4243444721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Mure
    • 43 Aristotle, Ethics, X, 9, 1180b, 10-25; Aristotle, Analytica Posteriora, ed. Mure, I, 33, 88b, 30-5.
    • Analytica Posteriora , vol.1 , Issue.33
    • Aristotle1
  • 101
    • 4243452224 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 46 Aristotle, Ethics, I, 3, 1094b, 10-30; II, 2, 1103b, 25-1104a, 10.
    • Ethics , vol.1 , Issue.3
    • Aristotle1
  • 102
    • 4243452261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 46 Aristotle, Ethics, I, 3, 1094b, 10-30; II, 2, 1103b, 25-1104a, 10.
    • Ethics , vol.2 , Issue.2
  • 103
    • 4243452224 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 47 Ibid., I, 3, 1094b, 10-20; II, 2, 1103b, 25-1104a, 5.
    • Ethics , vol.1 , Issue.3
  • 104
    • 4243452261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 47 Ibid., I, 3, 1094b, 10-20; II, 2, 1103b, 25-1104a, 5.
    • Ethics , vol.2 , Issue.2
  • 105
    • 4243413561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 48 Ibid., X, 9, 1181a, 25-1181b, 1.
    • Ethics , vol.10 , Issue.9
  • 106
    • 4243413562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 49 Ibid., VI, 5, 1140a, 25-1140b, 30.
    • Ethics , vol.6 , Issue.5
  • 107
    • 4243408204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 50 Ibid., VI, 7, 1141b, 15-20.
    • Ethics , vol.6 , Issue.7
  • 108
    • 0004349725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 51 Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 72. See also Crowe, The Changing Profile of Natural Law, p. 19; W. Friedmann, Legal Theory (London, 5th edn., 1967), p. 10; Friedrich, Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective, pp. 22-3.
    • Aristotle on Natural Law , pp. 72
    • Shellens, S.1
  • 109
    • 0004338003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 51 Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 72. See also Crowe, The Changing Profile of Natural Law, p. 19; W. Friedmann, Legal Theory (London, 5th edn., 1967), p. 10; Friedrich, Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective, pp. 22-3.
    • The Changing Profile of Natural Law , pp. 19
    • Crowe1
  • 110
    • 0010089298 scopus 로고
    • London, 5th edn.
    • 51 Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 72. See also Crowe, The Changing Profile of Natural Law, p. 19; W. Friedmann, Legal Theory (London, 5th edn., 1967), p. 10; Friedrich, Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective, pp. 22-3.
    • (1967) Legal Theory , pp. 10
    • Friedmann, W.1
  • 111
    • 0002183924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 51 Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 72. See also Crowe, The Changing Profile of Natural Law, p. 19; W. Friedmann, Legal Theory (London, 5th edn., 1967), p. 10; Friedrich, Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective, pp. 22-3.
    • Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective , pp. 22-23
    • Friedrich1
  • 112
    • 0004334097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 52 Kelsen, 'The Foundation of the Theory of Natural Law', pp. 122-36; H. Kelsen, 'Aristotle's Doctrine of Justice', in What is Justice?, pp. 125-36; Yack, 'Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice', p. 216.
    • The Foundation of the Theory of Natural Law , pp. 122-136
    • Kelsen1
  • 113
    • 84923714720 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's doctrine of justice
    • 52 Kelsen, 'The Foundation of the Theory of Natural Law', pp. 122-36; H. Kelsen, 'Aristotle's Doctrine of Justice', in What is Justice?, pp. 125-36; Yack, 'Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice', p. 216.
    • What Is Justice? , pp. 125-136
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 114
    • 0004336682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 52 Kelsen, 'The Foundation of the Theory of Natural Law', pp. 122-36; H. Kelsen, 'Aristotle's Doctrine of Justice', in What is Justice?, pp. 125-36; Yack, 'Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice', p. 216.
    • Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice , pp. 216
    • Yack1
  • 116
    • 0004348585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 54 Kelsen, 'Aristotle's Doctrine of Justice', p. 133. See also, H. Kelsen, 'Natural Law Doctrine and Legal Positivism', in A General Theory of Law and the State, pp. 439-40.
    • Aristotle's Doctrine of Justice , pp. 133
    • Kelsen1
  • 117
    • 0042081941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Natural law doctrine and legal positivism
    • 54 Kelsen, 'Aristotle's Doctrine of Justice', p. 133. See also, H. Kelsen, 'Natural Law Doctrine and Legal Positivism', in A General Theory of Law and the State, pp. 439-40.
    • A General Theory of Law and the State , pp. 439-440
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 124
    • 0010099173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 60 Wormuth, 'Aristotle on Law', p. 59; also pp. 46, 54-8 . The view of Kelsen and Wormuth is shared by Yack, 'Natural Right and Aristotle's Understanding of Justice', pp. 220, 234.
    • Aristotle on Law , pp. 59
    • Wormuth1
  • 126
    • 84979121616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hegel and natural law theory
    • 61 I have discussed the role that the Aristotelian conception of natural law has to play in Hegel's political thought, briefly, in Tony Burns, 'Hegel and Natural Law Theory', Politics, 15(1) (1995), pp. 27-32, and at greater length in Burns, Natural Law and Political Ideology, Chs. 2 and 4.
    • (1995) Politics , vol.15 , Issue.1 , pp. 27-32
    • Burns, T.1
  • 127
    • 84979121616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chs. 2 and 4
    • 61 I have discussed the role that the Aristotelian conception of natural law has to play in Hegel's political thought, briefly, in Tony Burns, 'Hegel and Natural Law Theory', Politics, 15(1) (1995), pp. 27-32, and at greater length in Burns, Natural Law and Political Ideology, Chs. 2 and 4.
    • Natural Law and Political Ideology
    • Burns1
  • 128
    • 0010157602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 62 In our view, Aristotle's principal task throughout Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics is to define the concept of justice - which he does by relating this concept to that of equity. Book V, therefore, as del Vecchio has put it, contains Aristotle's understanding of the concept of justice, as it is 'genetically understood'. That is to say, it contains an account of the concept of justice understood in its strictest sense, or 'without qualification' (απλως δικαιον, haplos dikaion). For this reading of Aristotle's intentions see del Vecchio, Justice, p. 23; Gauthier and Jolif, in Aristotle, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, ed. R.A. Gauthier and J.Y. Jolif (4 vols., Louvain-Paris, 2nd edn., 1970), Vol. III, p. 385; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 100-4; W.L. Newman in Aristotle: The Politics, ed. W.L. Newman (4 vols., Oxford, 1881-1902), Vol. III, p. 192; Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 89. Such a reading of Aristotle's intentions implies that, although it may not appear so on the surface, Book V does actually possess, at least implicitly, some sort of underlying, coherent structure. For this hotly debated issue see Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, pp. 213, 217-24; del Vecchio, Justice, pp. 53, 68; Grant, The Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. II, pp. 108-12; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 76, 82-3 and 100-4; Gauthier and Jolif, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, Vol. III, pp. 369-73, 385; Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Sub-Divisions of Particular Justice', p. 185; W.D. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1964), p. 212; Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics, I, pp. 431-2.
    • Justice , pp. 23
    • Del Vecchio1
  • 129
    • 0010212384 scopus 로고
    • ed. R.A. Gauthier and J.Y. Jolif 4 vols., Louvain-Paris, 2nd edn.
    • 62 In our view, Aristotle's principal task throughout Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics is to define the concept of justice - which he does by relating this concept to that of equity. Book V, therefore, as del Vecchio has put it, contains Aristotle's understanding of the concept of justice, as it is 'genetically understood'. That is to say, it contains an account of the concept of justice understood in its strictest sense, or 'without qualification' (απλως δικαιον, haplos dikaion). For this reading of Aristotle's intentions see del Vecchio, Justice, p. 23; Gauthier and Jolif, in Aristotle, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, ed. R.A. Gauthier and J.Y. Jolif (4 vols., Louvain-Paris, 2nd edn., 1970), Vol. III, p. 385; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 100-4; W.L. Newman in Aristotle: The Politics, ed. W.L. Newman (4 vols., Oxford, 1881-1902), Vol. III, p. 192; Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 89. Such a reading of Aristotle's intentions implies that, although it may not appear so on the surface, Book V does actually possess, at least implicitly, some sort of underlying, coherent structure. For this hotly debated issue see Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, pp. 213, 217-24; del Vecchio, Justice, pp. 53, 68; Grant, The Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. II, pp. 108-12; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 76, 82-3 and 100-4; Gauthier and Jolif, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, Vol. III, pp. 369-73, 385; Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Sub-Divisions of Particular Justice', p. 185; W.D. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1964), p. 212; Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics, I, pp. 431-2.
    • (1970) L'Éthique à Nicomaque , vol.3 , pp. 385
    • Aristotle1
  • 130
    • 0010157603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 62 In our view, Aristotle's principal task throughout Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics is to define the concept of justice - which he does by relating this concept to that of equity. Book V, therefore, as del Vecchio has put it, contains Aristotle's understanding of the concept of justice, as it is 'genetically understood'. That is to say, it contains an account of the concept
    • The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics , pp. 20
    • Jackson1
  • 131
    • 0010099174 scopus 로고
    • ed. W.L. Newman 4 vols., Oxford
    • 62 In our view, Aristotle's principal task throughout Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics is to define the concept of justice - which he does by relating this concept to that of equity. Book V, therefore, as del Vecchio has put it, contains Aristotle's understanding of the concept of justice, as it is 'genetically understood'. That is to say, it contains an account of the concept of justice understood in its strictest sense, or 'without qualification' (απλως δικαιον, haplos dikaion). For this reading of Aristotle's intentions see del Vecchio, Justice, p. 23; Gauthier and Jolif, in Aristotle, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, ed. R.A. Gauthier and J.Y. Jolif (4 vols., Louvain-Paris, 2nd edn., 1970), Vol. III, p. 385; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 100-4; W.L. Newman in Aristotle: The Politics, ed. W.L. Newman (4 vols., Oxford, 1881-1902), Vol. III, p. 192; Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 89. Such a reading of Aristotle's intentions implies that, although it may not appear so on the surface, Book V does actually possess, at least implicitly, some sort of underlying, coherent structure. For this hotly debated issue see Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, pp. 213, 217-24; del Vecchio, Justice, pp. 53, 68; Grant, The Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. II, pp. 108-12; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 76, 82-3 and 100-4; Gauthier and Jolif, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, Vol. III, pp. 369-73, 385; Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Sub-Divisions of Particular Justice', p. 185; W.D. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1964), p. 212; Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics, I, pp. 431-2.
    • (1881) Aristotle: The Politics , vol.3 , pp. 192
    • Newman, W.L.1
  • 132
    • 0004349725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such a reading of Aristotle's intentions implies that, although it may not appear so on the surface, Book V does actually possess, at least implicitly, some sort of underlying, coherent structure
    • 62 In our view, Aristotle's principal task throughout Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics is to define the concept of justice - which he does by relating this concept to that of equity. Book V, therefore, as del Vecchio has put it, contains Aristotle's understanding of the concept of justice, as it is 'genetically understood'. That is to say, it contains an account of the concept of justice understood in its strictest sense, or 'without qualification' (απλως δικαιον, haplos dikaion). For this reading of Aristotle's intentions see del Vecchio, Justice, p. 23; Gauthier and Jolif, in Aristotle, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, ed. R.A. Gauthier and J.Y. Jolif (4 vols., Louvain-Paris, 2nd edn., 1970), Vol. III, p. 385; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 100-4; W.L. Newman in Aristotle: The Politics, ed. W.L. Newman (4 vols., Oxford, 1881-1902), Vol. III, p. 192; Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 89. Such a reading of Aristotle's intentions implies that, although it may not appear so on the surface, Book V does actually possess, at least implicitly, some sort of underlying, coherent structure. For this hotly debated issue see Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, pp. 213, 217-24; del Vecchio, Justice, pp. 53, 68; Grant, The Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. II, pp. 108-12; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 76, 82-3 and 100-4; Gauthier and Jolif, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, Vol. III, pp. 369-73, 385; Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Sub-Divisions of Particular Justice', p. 185; W.D. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1964), p. 212; Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics, I, pp. 431-2.
    • Aristotle on Natural Law , pp. 89
    • Shellens, S.1
  • 133
    • 0010156680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 62 In our view, Aristotle's principal task throughout Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics is to define the concept of justice - which he does by relating this concept to that of equity. Book V, therefore, as del Vecchio has put it, contains Aristotle's understanding of the concept of justice, as it is 'genetically understood'. That is to say, it contains an account of the concept of justice understood in its strictest sense, or 'without qualification' (απλως δικαιον, haplos dikaion). For this reading of Aristotle's intentions see del Vecchio, Justice, p. 23; Gauthier and Jolif, in Aristotle, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, ed. R.A. Gauthier and J.Y. Jolif (4 vols., Louvain-Paris, 2nd edn., 1970), Vol. III, p. 385; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 100-4; W.L. Newman in Aristotle: The Politics, ed. W.L. Newman (4 vols., Oxford, 1881-1902), Vol. III, p. 192; Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 89. Such a reading of Aristotle's intentions implies that, although it may not appear so on the surface, Book V does actually possess, at least implicitly, some sort of underlying, coherent structure. For this hotly debated issue see Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, pp. 213, 217-24; del Vecchio, Justice, pp. 53, 68; Grant, The Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. II, pp. 108-12; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 76, 82-3 and 100-4; Gauthier and Jolif, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, Vol. III, pp. 369-73, 385; Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Sub-Divisions of Particular Justice', p. 185; W.D. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1964), p. 212; Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics, I, pp. 431-2.
    • The Ethics of Aristotle , pp. 213
    • Burnet1
  • 134
    • 0010157602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 62 In our view, Aristotle's principal task throughout Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics is to define the concept of justice - which he does by relating this concept to that of equity. Book V, therefore, as del Vecchio has put it, contains Aristotle's understanding of the concept of justice, as it is 'genetically understood'. That is to say, it contains an account of the concept of justice understood in its strictest sense, or 'without qualification' (απλως δικαιον, haplos dikaion). For this reading of Aristotle's intentions see del Vecchio, Justice, p. 23; Gauthier and Jolif, in Aristotle, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, ed. R.A. Gauthier and J.Y. Jolif (4 vols., Louvain-Paris, 2nd edn., 1970), Vol. III, p. 385; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 100-4; W.L. Newman in Aristotle: The Politics, ed. W.L. Newman (4 vols., Oxford, 1881-1902), Vol. III, p. 192; Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 89. Such a reading of Aristotle's intentions implies that, although it may not appear so on the surface, Book V does actually possess, at least implicitly, some sort of underlying, coherent structure. For this hotly debated issue see Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, pp. 213, 217-24; del Vecchio, Justice, pp. 53, 68; Grant, The Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. II, pp. 108-12; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 76, 82-3 and 100-4; Gauthier and Jolif, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, Vol. III, pp. 369-73, 385; Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Sub-Divisions of Particular Justice', p. 185; W.D. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1964), p. 212; Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics, I, pp. 431-2.
    • Justice , pp. 53
    • Del Vecchio1
  • 135
    • 0010198545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 62 In our view, Aristotle's principal task throughout Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics is to define the concept of justice - which he does by relating this concept to that of equity. Book V, therefore, as del Vecchio has put it, contains Aristotle's understanding of the concept of justice, as it is 'genetically understood'. That is to say, it contains an account of the concept of justice understood in its strictest sense, or 'without qualification' (απλως δικαιον, haplos dikaion). For this reading of Aristotle's intentions see del Vecchio, Justice, p. 23; Gauthier and Jolif, in Aristotle, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, ed. R.A. Gauthier and J.Y. Jolif (4 vols., Louvain-Paris, 2nd edn., 1970), Vol. III, p. 385; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 100-4; W.L. Newman in Aristotle: The Politics, ed. W.L. Newman (4 vols., Oxford, 1881-1902), Vol. III, p. 192; Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 89. Such a reading of Aristotle's intentions implies that, although it may not appear so on the surface, Book V does actually possess, at least implicitly, some sort of underlying, coherent structure. For this hotly debated issue see Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, pp. 213, 217-24; del Vecchio, Justice, pp. 53, 68; Grant, The Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. II, pp. 108-12; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 76, 82-3 and 100-4; Gauthier and Jolif, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, Vol. III, pp. 369-73, 385; Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Sub-Divisions of Particular Justice', p. 185; W.D. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1964), p. 212; Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics, I, pp. 431-2.
    • The Ethics of Aristotle , vol.2 , pp. 108-112
    • Grant1
  • 136
    • 0010157603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 62 In our view, Aristotle's principal task throughout Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics is to define the concept of justice - which he does by relating this concept to that of equity. Book V, therefore, as del Vecchio has put it, contains Aristotle's understanding of the concept of justice, as it is 'genetically understood'. That is to say, it contains an account of the concept of justice understood in its strictest sense, or 'without qualification' (απλως δικαιον, haplos dikaion). For this reading of Aristotle's intentions see del Vecchio, Justice, p. 23; Gauthier and Jolif, in Aristotle, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, ed. R.A. Gauthier and J.Y. Jolif (4 vols., Louvain-Paris, 2nd edn., 1970), Vol. III, p. 385; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 100-4; W.L. Newman in Aristotle: The Politics, ed. W.L. Newman (4 vols., Oxford, 1881-1902), Vol. III, p. 192; Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 89. Such a reading of Aristotle's intentions implies that, although it may not appear so on the surface, Book V does actually possess, at least implicitly, some sort of underlying, coherent structure. For this hotly debated issue see Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, pp. 213, 217-24; del Vecchio, Justice, pp. 53, 68; Grant, The Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. II, pp. 108-12; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 76, 82-3 and 100-4; Gauthier and Jolif, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, Vol. III, pp. 369-73, 385; Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Sub-Divisions of Particular Justice', p. 185; W.D. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1964), p. 212; Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics, I, pp. 431-2.
    • The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics , pp. 20
    • Jackson1
  • 137
    • 0010205838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 62 In our view, Aristotle's principal task throughout Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics is to define the concept of justice - which he does by relating this concept to that of equity. Book V, therefore, as del Vecchio has put it, contains Aristotle's understanding of the concept of justice, as it is 'genetically understood'. That is to say, it contains an account of the concept of justice understood in its strictest sense, or 'without qualification' (απλως δικαιον, haplos dikaion). For this reading of Aristotle's intentions see del Vecchio, Justice, p. 23; Gauthier and Jolif, in Aristotle, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, ed. R.A. Gauthier and J.Y. Jolif (4 vols., Louvain-Paris, 2nd edn., 1970), Vol. III, p. 385; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 100-4; W.L. Newman in Aristotle: The Politics, ed. W.L. Newman (4 vols., Oxford, 1881-1902), Vol. III, p. 192; Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 89. Such a reading of Aristotle's intentions implies that, although it may not appear so on the surface, Book V does actually possess, at least implicitly, some sort of underlying, coherent structure. For this hotly debated issue see Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, pp. 213, 217-24; del Vecchio, Justice, pp. 53, 68; Grant, The Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. II, pp. 108-12; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 76, 82-3 and 100-4; Gauthier and Jolif, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, Vol. III, pp. 369-73, 385; Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Sub-Divisions of Particular Justice', p. 185; W.D. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1964), p. 212; Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics, I, pp. 431-2.
    • L'Éthique à Nicomaque , vol.3 , pp. 369-373
    • Gauthier1    Jolif2
  • 138
    • 0010212386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 62 In our view, Aristotle's principal task throughout Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics is to define the concept of justice - which he does by relating this concept to that of equity. Book V, therefore, as del Vecchio has put it, contains Aristotle's understanding of the concept of justice, as it is 'genetically understood'. That is to say, it contains an account of the concept of justice understood in its strictest sense, or 'without qualification' (απλως δικαιον, haplos dikaion). For this reading of Aristotle's intentions see del Vecchio, Justice, p. 23; Gauthier and Jolif, in Aristotle, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, ed. R.A. Gauthier and J.Y. Jolif (4 vols., Louvain-Paris, 2nd edn., 1970), Vol. III, p. 385; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 100-4; W.L. Newman in Aristotle: The Politics, ed. W.L. Newman (4 vols., Oxford, 1881-1902), Vol. III, p. 192; Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 89. Such a reading of Aristotle's intentions implies that, although it may not appear so on the surface, Book V does actually possess, at least implicitly, some sort of underlying, coherent structure. For this hotly debated issue see Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, pp. 213, 217-24; del Vecchio, Justice, pp. 53, 68; Grant, The Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. II, pp. 108-12; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 76, 82-3 and 100-4; Gauthier and Jolif, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, Vol. III, pp. 369-73, 385; Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Sub-Divisions of Particular Justice', p. 185; W.D. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1964), p. 212; Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics, I, pp. 431-2.
    • Aristotle's Sub-Divisions of Particular Justice , pp. 185
    • Ritchie1
  • 139
    • 61049348448 scopus 로고
    • London
    • 62 In our view, Aristotle's principal task throughout Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics is to define the concept of justice - which he does by relating this concept to that of equity. Book V, therefore, as del Vecchio has put it, contains Aristotle's understanding of the concept of justice, as it is 'genetically understood'. That is to say, it contains an account of the concept of justice understood in its strictest sense, or 'without qualification' (απλως δικαιον, haplos dikaion). For this reading of Aristotle's intentions see del Vecchio, Justice, p. 23; Gauthier and Jolif, in Aristotle, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, ed. R.A. Gauthier and J.Y. Jolif (4 vols., Louvain-Paris, 2nd edn., 1970), Vol. III, p. 385; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 100-4; W.L. Newman in Aristotle: The Politics, ed. W.L. Newman (4 vols., Oxford, 1881-1902), Vol. III, p. 192; Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 89. Such a reading of Aristotle's intentions implies that, although it may not appear so on the surface, Book V does actually possess, at least implicitly, some sort of underlying, coherent structure. For this hotly debated issue see Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, pp. 213, 217-24; del Vecchio, Justice, pp. 53, 68; Grant, The Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. II, pp. 108-12; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 76, 82-3 and 100-4; Gauthier and Jolif, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, Vol. III, pp. 369-73, 385; Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Sub-Divisions of Particular Justice', p. 185; W.D. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1964), p. 212; Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics, I, pp. 431-2.
    • (1964) Aristotle , pp. 212
    • Ross, W.D.1
  • 140
    • 0010101910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 62 In our view, Aristotle's principal task throughout Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics is to define the concept of justice - which he does by relating this concept to that of equity. Book V, therefore, as del Vecchio has put it, contains Aristotle's understanding of the concept of justice, as it is 'genetically understood'. That is to say, it contains an account of the concept of justice understood in its strictest sense, or 'without qualification' (απλως δικαιον, haplos dikaion). For this reading of Aristotle's intentions see del Vecchio, Justice, p. 23; Gauthier and Jolif, in Aristotle, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, ed. R.A. Gauthier and J.Y. Jolif (4 vols., Louvain-Paris, 2nd edn., 1970), Vol. III, p. 385; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 100-4; W.L. Newman in Aristotle: The Politics, ed. W.L. Newman (4 vols., Oxford, 1881-1902), Vol. III, p. 192; Salomon Shellens, 'Aristotle on Natural Law', p. 89. Such a reading of Aristotle's intentions implies that, although it may not appear so on the surface, Book V does actually possess, at least implicitly, some sort of underlying, coherent structure. For this hotly debated issue see Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, pp. 213, 217-24; del Vecchio, Justice, pp. 53, 68; Grant, The Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. II, pp. 108-12; Jackson, The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics, pp. xx, 76, 82-3 and 100-4; Gauthier and Jolif, L'Éthique à Nicomaque, Vol. III, pp. 369-73, 385; Ritchie, 'Aristotle's Sub-Divisions of Particular Justice', p. 185; W.D. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1964), p. 212; Stewart, Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics, I, pp. 431-2.
    • Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics , vol.1 , pp. 431-432
    • Stewart1
  • 141
    • 4243454846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Barker
    • 63 cf. Aristotle, Politics, ed. Barker, III, IX, 3, 1280a, p. 136; III, XII, 1, 1282b, p. 151.
    • Politics , vol.3-9 , Issue.3-1280 A , pp. 136
    • Aristotle1
  • 142
    • 4243452260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 63 cf. Aristotle, Politics, ed. Barker, III, IX, 3, 1280a, p. 136; III, XII, 1, 1282b, p. 151.
    • Politics , vol.3-12 , Issue.1-1282 B , pp. 151


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.