메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 19, Issue 2, 1998, Pages 265-292

James and the early Laski: The ambiguous legacy of pragmatism

(1)  Pemberton, Jo Anne Claire a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0032093302     PISSN: 0143781X     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (6)

References (421)
  • 1
    • 84929863311 scopus 로고
    • Holmes-Cohen correspondence
    • 1 Justice Holmes made this claim in a letter to the philosopher Morris R. Cohen (21 July 1920). See the 'Holmes-Cohen Correspondence', Journal of the History of Ideas, IX (1948), edited with a Foreword by Felix S. Cohen, pp. 3-52, p. 19. Cf. Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy: II', The New Republic (1 October 1919), pp. 255-27, p. 255. Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy: III', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 82. W.Y. Elliott, 'The Pragmatic Politics of Mr. H.J. Laski', The American Political Science Review, XVIII (1924), pp. 251-75, p. 252. Horace Meyer Kallen, William James and Henri Bergson (Chicago, 1915), pp. 10 f., 105. The Letters of William, James, ed. Henry James (2 vols., Boston, 1920), Vol. II, p. 271.
    • (1948) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.9 , pp. 3-52
    • Cohen, F.S.1
  • 2
    • 0010089313 scopus 로고
    • On American philosophy: II
    • 1 October
    • 1 Justice Holmes made this claim in a letter to the philosopher Morris R. Cohen (21 July 1920). See the 'Holmes-Cohen Correspondence', Journal of the History of Ideas, IX (1948), edited with a Foreword by Felix S. Cohen, pp. 3-52, p. 19. Cf. Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy: II', The New Republic (1 October 1919), pp. 255-27, p. 255. Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy: III', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 82. W.Y. Elliott, 'The Pragmatic Politics of Mr. H.J. Laski', The American Political Science Review, XVIII (1924), pp. 251-75, p. 252. Horace Meyer Kallen, William James and Henri Bergson (Chicago, 1915), pp. 10 f., 105. The Letters of William, James, ed. Henry James (2 vols., Boston, 1920), Vol. II, p. 271.
    • (1919) The New Republic , pp. 255-327
    • Cohen, M.R.1
  • 3
    • 0002774492 scopus 로고
    • On American philosophy: III
    • 17 March
    • 1 Justice Holmes made this claim in a letter to the philosopher Morris R. Cohen (21 July 1920). See the 'Holmes-Cohen Correspondence', Journal of the History of Ideas, IX (1948), edited with a Foreword by Felix S. Cohen, pp. 3-52, p. 19. Cf. Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy: II', The New Republic (1 October 1919), pp. 255-27, p. 255. Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy: III', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 82. W.Y. Elliott, 'The Pragmatic Politics of Mr. H.J. Laski', The American Political Science Review, XVIII (1924), pp. 251-75, p. 252. Horace Meyer Kallen, William James and Henri Bergson (Chicago, 1915), pp. 10 f., 105. The Letters of William, James, ed. Henry James (2 vols., Boston, 1920), Vol. II, p. 271.
    • (1920) The New Republic , pp. 82-86
    • Cohen, M.R.1
  • 4
    • 0001290517 scopus 로고
    • The pragmatic politics of Mr. H.J. Laski
    • 1 Justice Holmes made this claim in a letter to the philosopher Morris R. Cohen (21 July 1920). See the 'Holmes-Cohen Correspondence', Journal of the History of Ideas, IX (1948), edited with a Foreword by Felix S. Cohen, pp. 3-52, p. 19. Cf. Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy: II', The New Republic (1 October 1919), pp. 255-27, p. 255. Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy: III', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 82. W.Y. Elliott, 'The Pragmatic Politics of Mr. H.J. Laski', The American Political Science Review, XVIII (1924), pp. 251-75, p. 252. Horace Meyer Kallen, William James and Henri Bergson (Chicago, 1915), pp. 10 f., 105. The Letters of William, James, ed. Henry James (2 vols., Boston, 1920), Vol. II, p. 271.
    • (1924) The American Political Science Review , vol.18 , pp. 251-275
    • Elliott, W.Y.1
  • 5
    • 0010947425 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • 1 Justice Holmes made this claim in a letter to the philosopher Morris R. Cohen (21 July 1920). See the 'Holmes-Cohen Correspondence', Journal of the History of Ideas, IX (1948), edited with a Foreword by Felix S. Cohen, pp. 3-52, p. 19. Cf. Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy: II', The New Republic (1 October 1919), pp. 255-27, p. 255. Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy: III', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 82. W.Y. Elliott, 'The Pragmatic Politics of Mr. H.J. Laski', The American Political Science Review, XVIII (1924), pp. 251-75, p. 252. Horace Meyer Kallen, William James and Henri Bergson (Chicago, 1915), pp. 10 f., 105. The Letters of William, James, ed. Henry James (2 vols., Boston, 1920), Vol. II, p. 271.
    • (1915) William James and Henri Bergson
    • Kallen, H.M.1
  • 6
    • 0010131138 scopus 로고
    • 2 vols., Boston
    • 1 Justice Holmes made this claim in a letter to the philosopher Morris R. Cohen (21 July 1920). See the 'Holmes-Cohen Correspondence', Journal of the History of Ideas, IX (1948), edited with a Foreword by Felix S. Cohen, pp. 3-52, p. 19. Cf. Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy: II', The New Republic (1 October 1919), pp. 255-27, p. 255. Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy: III', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 82. W.Y. Elliott, 'The Pragmatic Politics of Mr. H.J. Laski', The American Political Science Review, XVIII (1924), pp. 251-75, p. 252. Horace Meyer Kallen, William James and Henri Bergson (Chicago, 1915), pp. 10 f., 105. The Letters of William, James, ed. Henry James (2 vols., Boston, 1920), Vol. II, p. 271.
    • (1920) The Letters of William, James , vol.2 , pp. 271
    • James, H.1
  • 7
    • 0010186881 scopus 로고
    • 2 vols., London, (hereafter Letters), 13 December 1923
    • 2 Holmes-Laski Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski 1916-1935, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe, Foreword by Felix Frankfurter (2 vols., London, 1953) (hereafter Letters), Vol. I, p. 571 (13 December 1923); see also ibid. (10 February 1918). Laski declared himself to be 'all for the aperçu'. See H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of the State', The Nation (22 July 1915), pp. 115-17, p. 116. H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', Harvard Law Review, XXIX (1916), pp. 404-26, p. 425. Reprinted in H.J. Laski, The Foundations of Sovereignty and other Essays (New York, 1938; 1st published 1921) (hereafter Foundations). H.J. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', New Republic (22 July 1919), pp. 302-4, pp. 303-4. H.J. Laski, Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty (London, 1968) (hereafter Studies), pp. 10, 23, 18. H.J. Laski, Authority in the Modern State (Hamden, Connecticut, 1968) (hereafter Authority), p. 313. H.J. Laski, A Grammar of Politics (London, 1925) (hereafter Grammar), pp. 23, 261, 400, 544. H.J. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 267, 294.
    • (1953) Holmes-Laski Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski 1916-1935 , vol.1 , pp. 571
    • DeWolfe Howe, M.1    Frankfurter, F.2
  • 8
    • 0010196216 scopus 로고
    • 10 February
    • 2 Holmes-Laski Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski 1916-1935, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe, Foreword by Felix Frankfurter (2 vols., London, 1953) (hereafter Letters), Vol. I, p. 571 (13 December 1923); see also ibid. (10 February 1918). Laski declared himself to be 'all for the aperçu'. See H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of the State', The Nation (22 July 1915), pp. 115-17, p. 116. H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', Harvard Law Review, XXIX (1916), pp. 404-26, p. 425. Reprinted in H.J. Laski, The Foundations of Sovereignty and other Essays (New York, 1938; 1st published 1921) (hereafter Foundations). H.J. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', New Republic (22 July 1919), pp. 302-4, pp. 303-4. H.J. Laski, Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty (London, 1968) (hereafter Studies), pp. 10, 23, 18. H.J. Laski, Authority in the Modern State (Hamden, Connecticut, 1968) (hereafter Authority), p. 313. H.J. Laski, A Grammar of Politics (London, 1925) (hereafter Grammar), pp. 23, 261, 400, 544. H.J. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 267, 294.
    • (1918) Holmes-Laski Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski 1916-1935
  • 9
    • 0010157623 scopus 로고
    • The personality of the state
    • 22 July
    • 2 Holmes-Laski Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski 1916-1935, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe, Foreword by Felix Frankfurter (2 vols., London, 1953) (hereafter Letters), Vol. I, p. 571 (13 December 1923); see also ibid. (10 February 1918). Laski declared himself to be 'all for the aperçu'. See H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of the State', The Nation (22 July 1915), pp. 115-17, p. 116. H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', Harvard Law Review, XXIX (1916), pp. 404-26, p. 425. Reprinted in H.J. Laski, The Foundations of Sovereignty and other Essays (New York, 1938; 1st published 1921) (hereafter Foundations). H.J. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', New Republic (22 July 1919), pp. 302-4, pp. 303-4. H.J. Laski, Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty (London, 1968) (hereafter Studies), pp. 10, 23, 18. H.J. Laski, Authority in the Modern State (Hamden, Connecticut, 1968) (hereafter Authority), p. 313. H.J. Laski, A Grammar of Politics (London, 1925) (hereafter Grammar), pp. 23, 261, 400, 544. H.J. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 267, 294.
    • (1915) The Nation , pp. 115-117
    • Laski, H.J.1
  • 10
    • 0010212407 scopus 로고
    • The personality of associations
    • 2 Holmes-Laski Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski 1916-1935, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe, Foreword by Felix Frankfurter (2 vols., London, 1953) (hereafter Letters), Vol. I, p. 571 (13 December 1923); see also ibid. (10 February 1918). Laski declared himself to be 'all for the aperçu'. See H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of the State', The Nation (22 July 1915), pp. 115-17, p. 116. H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', Harvard Law Review, XXIX (1916), pp. 404-26, p. 425. Reprinted in H.J. Laski, The Foundations of Sovereignty and other Essays (New York, 1938; 1st published 1921) (hereafter Foundations). H.J. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', New Republic (22 July 1919), pp. 302-4, pp. 303-4. H.J. Laski, Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty (London, 1968) (hereafter Studies), pp. 10, 23, 18. H.J. Laski, Authority in the Modern State (Hamden, Connecticut, 1968) (hereafter Authority), p. 313. H.J. Laski, A Grammar of Politics (London, 1925) (hereafter Grammar), pp. 23, 261, 400, 544. H.J. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 267, 294.
    • (1916) Harvard Law Review , vol.29 , pp. 404-426
    • Laski, H.J.1
  • 11
    • 0010156693 scopus 로고
    • (New York, 1938; 1st published 1921) (hereafter Foundations)
    • 2 Holmes-Laski Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski 1916-1935, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe, Foreword by Felix Frankfurter (2 vols., London, 1953) (hereafter Letters), Vol. I, p. 571 (13 December 1923); see also ibid. (10 February 1918). Laski declared himself to be 'all for the aperçu'. See H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of the State', The Nation (22 July 1915), pp. 115-17, p. 116. H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', Harvard Law Review, XXIX (1916), pp. 404-26, p. 425. Reprinted in H.J. Laski, The Foundations of Sovereignty and other Essays (New York, 1938; 1st published 1921) (hereafter Foundations). H.J. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', New Republic (22 July 1919), pp. 302-4, pp. 303-4. H.J. Laski, Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty (London, 1968) (hereafter Studies), pp. 10, 23, 18. H.J. Laski, Authority in the Modern State (Hamden, Connecticut, 1968) (hereafter Authority), p. 313. H.J. Laski, A Grammar of Politics (London, 1925) (hereafter Grammar), pp. 23, 261, 400, 544. H.J. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 267, 294.
    • (1938) The Foundations of Sovereignty and Other Essays
    • Laski, H.J.1
  • 12
    • 0039086100 scopus 로고
    • The apotheosis of the state
    • 22 July
    • 2 Holmes-Laski Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski 1916-1935, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe, Foreword by Felix Frankfurter (2 vols., London, 1953) (hereafter Letters), Vol. I, p. 571 (13 December 1923); see also ibid. (10 February 1918). Laski declared himself to be 'all for the aperçu'. See H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of the State', The Nation (22 July 1915), pp. 115-17, p. 116. H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', Harvard Law Review, XXIX (1916), pp. 404-26, p. 425. Reprinted in H.J. Laski, The Foundations of Sovereignty and other Essays (New York, 1938; 1st published 1921) (hereafter Foundations). H.J. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', New Republic (22 July 1919), pp. 302-4, pp. 303-4. H.J. Laski, Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty (London, 1968) (hereafter Studies), pp. 10, 23, 18. H.J. Laski, Authority in the Modern State (Hamden, Connecticut, 1968) (hereafter Authority), p. 313. H.J. Laski, A Grammar of Politics (London, 1925) (hereafter Grammar), pp. 23, 261, 400, 544. H.J. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 267, 294.
    • (1919) New Republic , pp. 302-304
    • Laski, H.J.1
  • 13
    • 0004178961 scopus 로고
    • London, (hereafter Studies)
    • 2 Holmes-Laski Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski 1916-1935, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe, Foreword by Felix Frankfurter (2 vols., London, 1953) (hereafter Letters), Vol. I, p. 571 (13 December 1923); see also ibid. (10 February 1918). Laski declared himself to be 'all for the aperçu'. See H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of the State', The Nation (22 July 1915), pp. 115-17, p. 116. H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', Harvard Law Review, XXIX (1916), pp. 404-26, p. 425. Reprinted in H.J. Laski, The Foundations of Sovereignty and other Essays (New York, 1938; 1st published 1921) (hereafter Foundations). H.J. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', New Republic (22 July 1919), pp. 302-4, pp. 303-4. H.J. Laski, Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty (London, 1968) (hereafter Studies), pp. 10, 23, 18. H.J. Laski, Authority in the Modern State (Hamden, Connecticut, 1968) (hereafter Authority), p. 313. H.J. Laski, A Grammar of Politics (London, 1925) (hereafter Grammar), pp. 23, 261, 400, 544. H.J. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 267, 294.
    • (1968) Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty , pp. 10
    • Laski, H.J.1
  • 14
    • 0003985532 scopus 로고
    • Hamden, Connecticut, (hereafter Authority)
    • 2 Holmes-Laski Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski 1916-1935, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe, Foreword by Felix Frankfurter (2 vols., London, 1953) (hereafter Letters), Vol. I, p. 571 (13 December 1923); see also ibid. (10 February 1918). Laski declared himself to be 'all for the aperçu'. See H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of the State', The Nation (22 July 1915), pp. 115-17, p. 116. H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', Harvard Law Review, XXIX (1916), pp. 404-26, p. 425. Reprinted in H.J. Laski, The Foundations of Sovereignty and other Essays (New York, 1938; 1st published 1921) (hereafter Foundations). H.J. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', New Republic (22 July 1919), pp. 302-4, pp. 303-4. H.J. Laski, Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty (London, 1968) (hereafter Studies), pp. 10, 23, 18. H.J. Laski, Authority in the Modern State (Hamden, Connecticut, 1968) (hereafter Authority), p. 313. H.J. Laski, A Grammar of Politics (London, 1925) (hereafter Grammar), pp. 23, 261, 400, 544. H.J. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 267, 294.
    • (1968) Authority in the Modern State , pp. 313
    • Laski, H.J.1
  • 15
    • 0004205482 scopus 로고
    • London, (hereafter Grammar)
    • 2 Holmes-Laski Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski 1916-1935, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe, Foreword by Felix Frankfurter (2 vols., London, 1953) (hereafter Letters), Vol. I, p. 571 (13 December 1923); see also ibid. (10 February 1918). Laski declared himself to be 'all for the aperçu'. See H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of the State', The Nation (22 July 1915), pp. 115-17, p. 116. H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', Harvard Law Review, XXIX (1916), pp. 404-26, p. 425. Reprinted in H.J. Laski, The Foundations of Sovereignty and other Essays (New York, 1938; 1st published 1921) (hereafter Foundations). H.J. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', New Republic (22 July 1919), pp. 302-4, pp. 303-4. H.J. Laski, Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty (London, 1968) (hereafter Studies), pp. 10, 23, 18. H.J. Laski, Authority in the Modern State (Hamden, Connecticut, 1968) (hereafter Authority), p. 313. H.J. Laski, A Grammar of Politics (London, 1925) (hereafter Grammar), pp. 23, 261, 400, 544. H.J. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 267, 294.
    • (1925) A Grammar of Politics , pp. 23
    • Laski, H.J.1
  • 16
    • 0001231526 scopus 로고
    • Law and the state
    • 2 Holmes-Laski Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski 1916-1935, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe, Foreword by Felix Frankfurter (2 vols., London, 1953) (hereafter Letters), Vol. I, p. 571 (13 December 1923); see also ibid. (10 February 1918). Laski declared himself to be 'all for the aperçu'. See H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of the State', The Nation (22 July 1915), pp. 115-17, p. 116. H.J. Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', Harvard Law Review, XXIX (1916), pp. 404-26, p. 425. Reprinted in H.J. Laski, The Foundations of Sovereignty and other Essays (New York, 1938; 1st published 1921) (hereafter Foundations). H.J. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', New Republic (22 July 1919), pp. 302-4, pp. 303-4. H.J. Laski, Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty (London, 1968) (hereafter Studies), pp. 10, 23, 18. H.J. Laski, Authority in the Modern State (Hamden, Connecticut, 1968) (hereafter Authority), p. 313. H.J. Laski, A Grammar of Politics (London, 1925) (hereafter Grammar), pp. 23, 261, 400, 544. H.J. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 267, 294.
    • (1929) Economica , vol.27 , pp. 267-295
    • Laski, H.J.1
  • 18
    • 0010156694 scopus 로고
    • The personality of associations
    • 10 February
    • 4 Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 425 n. Letters, Vol. I, p. 135 (10 February 1918). Cf. William James, Pragmatism (London, 1907), pp. 6-8. See also Laski's allusion to James's description of philosophy as our 'individual way of just seeing and feeling the total push and pressure of the cosmos', Grammar, p. 544. See James, Pragmatism, p. 4. On the matter of James's projection of experience onto the cosmos see Ralph Barton Perry, In the Spirit of William James, Vol. II (Boston, 1958), pp. 75-80. Charles Morris also commented on the relation between James's empiricism and his metaphysics: 'The cosmos as a whole became simply the totality of "pure experience" ', C. Morris, The Pragmatic Movement in American Philosophy (New York, 1970), pp. 112-13.
    • (1918) N. Letters , vol.1 , pp. 135
    • Laski1
  • 19
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London
    • 4 Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 425 n. Letters, Vol. I, p. 135 (10 February 1918). Cf. William James, Pragmatism (London, 1907), pp. 6-8. See also Laski's allusion to James's description of philosophy as our 'individual way of just seeing and feeling the total push and pressure of the cosmos', Grammar, p. 544. See James, Pragmatism, p. 4. On the matter of James's projection of experience onto the cosmos see Ralph Barton Perry, In the Spirit of William James, Vol. II (Boston, 1958), pp. 75-80. Charles Morris also commented on the relation between James's empiricism and his metaphysics: 'The cosmos as a whole became simply the totality of "pure experience" ', C. Morris, The Pragmatic Movement in American Philosophy (New York, 1970), pp. 112-13.
    • (1907) Pragmatism , pp. 6-8
    • James, W.1
  • 20
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 4 Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 425 n. Letters, Vol. I, p. 135 (10 February 1918). Cf. William James, Pragmatism (London, 1907), pp. 6-8. See also Laski's allusion to James's description of philosophy as our 'individual way of just seeing and feeling the total push and pressure of the cosmos', Grammar, p. 544. See James, Pragmatism, p. 4. On the matter of James's projection of experience onto the cosmos see Ralph Barton Perry, In the Spirit of William James, Vol. II (Boston, 1958), pp. 75-80. Charles Morris also commented on the relation between James's empiricism and his metaphysics: 'The cosmos as a whole became simply the totality of "pure experience" ', C. Morris, The Pragmatic Movement in American Philosophy (New York, 1970), pp. 112-13.
    • Grammar , pp. 544
  • 21
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 4 Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 425 n. Letters, Vol. I, p. 135 (10 February 1918). Cf. William James, Pragmatism (London, 1907), pp. 6-8. See also Laski's allusion to James's description of philosophy as our 'individual way of just seeing and feeling the total push and pressure of the cosmos', Grammar, p. 544. See James, Pragmatism, p. 4. On the matter of James's projection of experience onto the cosmos see Ralph Barton Perry, In the Spirit of William James, Vol. II (Boston, 1958), pp. 75-80. Charles Morris also commented on the relation between James's empiricism and his metaphysics: 'The cosmos as a whole became simply the totality of "pure experience" ', C. Morris, The Pragmatic Movement in American Philosophy (New York, 1970), pp. 112-13.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 4
    • James1
  • 22
    • 0010186882 scopus 로고
    • Boston
    • 4 Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 425 n. Letters, Vol. I, p. 135 (10 February 1918). Cf. William James, Pragmatism (London, 1907), pp. 6-8. See also Laski's allusion to James's description of philosophy as our 'individual way of just seeing and feeling the total push and pressure of the cosmos', Grammar, p. 544. See James, Pragmatism, p. 4. On the matter of James's projection of experience onto the cosmos see Ralph Barton Perry, In the Spirit of William James, Vol. II (Boston, 1958), pp. 75-80. Charles Morris also commented on the relation between James's empiricism and his metaphysics: 'The cosmos as a whole became simply the totality of "pure experience" ', C. Morris, The Pragmatic Movement in American Philosophy (New York, 1970), pp. 112-13.
    • (1958) The Spirit of William James , vol.2 , pp. 75-80
    • Perry, R.B.1
  • 23
    • 0010143459 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • 4 Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 425 n. Letters, Vol. I, p. 135 (10 February 1918). Cf. William James, Pragmatism (London, 1907), pp. 6-8. See also Laski's allusion to James's description of philosophy as our 'individual way of just seeing and feeling the total push and pressure of the cosmos', Grammar, p. 544. See James, Pragmatism, p. 4. On the matter of James's projection of experience onto the cosmos see Ralph Barton Perry, In the Spirit of William James, Vol. II (Boston, 1958), pp. 75-80. Charles Morris also commented on the relation between James's empiricism and his metaphysics: 'The cosmos as a whole became simply the totality of "pure experience" ', C. Morris, The Pragmatic Movement in American Philosophy (New York, 1970), pp. 112-13.
    • (1970) The Pragmatic Movement in American Philosophy , pp. 112-113
    • Morris, C.1
  • 24
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 5 James, Pragmatism, p. 191. On the three main stages of James's philosophical development see Perry, Spirit of William James, p. 77.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 191
    • James1
  • 25
    • 0004343904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 5 James, Pragmatism, p. 191. On the three main stages of James's philosophical development see Perry, Spirit of William James, p. 77.
    • Spirit of William James , pp. 77
    • Perry1
  • 26
    • 0004018040 scopus 로고
    • New York, (hereafter Essays)
    • 6 On James's use of fluid imagery see William James, Essays in Radical Empiricism (New York, 1912) (hereafter Essays); and William James, A Pluralistic Universe, ed. Ralph Barton Perry with an introduction by Richard J. Bernstein (New York, 1971), pp. 50, 71, 237. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 254, 255, 260, 277.
    • (1912) Essays in Radical Empiricism
    • James, W.1
  • 27
    • 0010097953 scopus 로고
    • ed. Ralph Barton Perry with an introduction by Richard J. Bernstein New York
    • 6 On James's use of fluid imagery see William James, Essays in Radical Empiricism (New York, 1912) (hereafter Essays); and William James, A Pluralistic Universe, ed. Ralph Barton Perry with an introduction by Richard J. Bernstein (New York, 1971), pp. 50, 71, 237. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 254, 255, 260, 277.
    • (1971) A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 50
    • James, W.1
  • 28
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6 On James's use of fluid imagery see William James, Essays in Radical Empiricism (New York, 1912) (hereafter Essays); and William James, A Pluralistic Universe, ed. Ralph Barton Perry with an introduction by Richard J. Bernstein (New York, 1971), pp. 50, 71, 237. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 254, 255, 260, 277.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 254
    • James1
  • 29
    • 0010102419 scopus 로고
    • 2 vols., Chicago, (hereafter Principles)
    • 7 William James, Principles of Psychology (2 vols., Chicago, 1952) (hereafter Principles), Vol. I, p. 239. See also James, Pragmatism, pp. 53, 214.
    • (1952) Principles of Psychology , vol.1 , pp. 239
    • James, W.1
  • 30
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7 William James, Principles of Psychology (2 vols., Chicago, 1952) (hereafter Principles), Vol. I, p. 239. See also James, Pragmatism, pp. 53, 214.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 53
    • James1
  • 31
    • 0010098574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 8 Principles, I, pp. 237-9, cf. p. 276. At this stage of his career, James believed that higher states of consciousness were distinct psychic units which grew out of, but did not 'contain', lower states of consciousness. James, cited in Ralph Barton Perry, The Thought and Character of William James (2 vols., Boston, 1935), Vol. II, p. 588.
    • Principles , vol.1 , pp. 237-239
  • 32
    • 0010157624 scopus 로고
    • cited in Ralph Barton Perry, 2 vols., Boston
    • 8 Principles, I, pp. 237-9, cf. p. 276. At this stage of his career, James believed that higher states of consciousness were distinct psychic units which grew out of, but did not 'contain', lower states of consciousness. James, cited in Ralph Barton Perry, The Thought and Character of William James (2 vols., Boston, 1935), Vol. II, p. 588.
    • (1935) The Thought and Character of William James , vol.2 , pp. 588
    • James1
  • 33
    • 0010192068 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 9 Principles, I, p. 245. On James's focus on the transitive aspect of thought see also Perry, Spirit of William James, p. 81.
    • Principles , vol.1 , pp. 245
  • 34
    • 0004343904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 9 Principles, I, p. 245. On James's focus on the transitive aspect of thought see also Perry, Spirit of William James, p. 81.
    • Spirit of William James , pp. 81
    • Perry1
  • 35
    • 0010140391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 10 Principles, I, p. 226.
    • Principles , vol.1 , pp. 226
  • 38
  • 39
    • 84879965266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 14 Ibid., pp. 296-301; pp. 291-4.
    • Principles , pp. 296-301
  • 40
    • 84879965266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 15 Ibid., p. 289, cf. p. 284.
    • Principles , pp. 289
  • 41
    • 84879965266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 16 Ibid., pp. 239, 288.
    • Principles , pp. 239
  • 42
    • 84879965266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 17 Ibid., p. 285, cf. p. 289.
    • Principles , pp. 285
  • 44
    • 0010091094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 18 Perry, Spirit of William James, pp. 76, 88; cf. Essays, p. 57.
    • Essays , pp. 57
  • 45
    • 0010194665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 19 Essays, p. 50; cf. pp. 17, 22. See also Perry, Spirit of William James, pp. 92 ff.
    • Essays , pp. 50
  • 47
    • 0010203462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 20 Essays, pp. 4-8, 11, 13. James wrote that pure experience, like the physical reality he described in his Principles, is undifferentiated. It is neither thought nor thing but an 'instant field of the present . . . only virtually classifiable as objective fact or someone's opinion about the fact'. Essays, pp. 40-1. See also James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 274.
    • Essays , pp. 4-8
  • 48
    • 0010192070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 20 Essays, pp. 4-8, 11, 13. James wrote that pure experience, like the physical reality he described in his Principles, is undifferentiated. It is neither thought nor thing but an 'instant field of the present . . . only virtually classifiable as objective fact or someone's opinion about the fact'. Essays, pp. 40-1. See also James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 274.
    • Essays , pp. 40-41
  • 49
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 20 Essays, pp. 4-8, 11, 13. James wrote that pure experience, like the physical reality he described in his Principles, is undifferentiated. It is neither thought nor thing but an 'instant field of the present . . . only virtually classifiable as objective fact or someone's opinion about the fact'. Essays, pp. 40-1. See also James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 274.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 274
    • James1
  • 50
    • 0010158736 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 21 Essays, p. 48 and James, Pragmatism, p. 131.
    • Essays , pp. 48
  • 51
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 21 Essays, p. 48 and James, Pragmatism, p. 131.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 131
    • James1
  • 52
    • 0010179050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 22 On this point see Essays, pp. 25, 26, 46, 50; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 276. Morris wrote that of all the pragmatists James was closest to the British empiricists; but he also differed from them because he saw in experience a 'much wider range of the contents' such that experience included 'relations as well as the particulars which are related, and continuities as well as discontinuities'. Morris, Pragmatic Movement, pp. 112-13.
    • Essays , pp. 25
  • 53
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 22 On this point see Essays, pp. 25, 26, 46, 50; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 276. Morris wrote that of all the pragmatists James was closest to the British empiricists; but he also differed from them because he saw in experience a 'much wider range of the contents' such that experience included 'relations as well as the particulars which are related, and continuities as well as discontinuities'. Morris, Pragmatic Movement, pp. 112-13.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 276
    • James1
  • 54
    • 0010155642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 22 On this point see Essays, pp. 25, 26, 46, 50; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 276. Morris wrote that of all the pragmatists James was closest to the British empiricists; but he also differed from them because he saw in experience a 'much wider range of the contents' such that experience included 'relations as well as the particulars which are related, and continuities as well as discontinuities'. Morris, Pragmatic Movement, pp. 112-13.
    • Pragmatic Movement , pp. 112-113
    • Morris1
  • 55
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 23 James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 258-9; cf. p. 276. These points of connection are represented linguistically in the form of those prepositions, copulas and conjunctions which 'flower out of the stream of pure experience'. Essays, pp. 26-8, 42-3, 46, 51. Cf. Principles, I, p. 258.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 258-259
    • James1
  • 56
    • 0010153118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 23 James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 258-9; cf. p. 276. These points of connection are represented linguistically in the form of those prepositions, copulas and conjunctions which 'flower out of the stream of pure experience'. Essays, pp. 26-8, 42-3, 46, 51. Cf. Principles, I, p. 258.
    • Essays , pp. 26-28
  • 57
    • 0010158737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 23 James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 258-9; cf. p. 276. These points of connection are represented linguistically in the form of those prepositions, copulas and conjunctions which 'flower out of the stream of pure experience'. Essays, pp. 26-8, 42-3, 46, 51. Cf. Principles, I, p. 258.
    • Principles , vol.1 , pp. 258
  • 58
    • 0010097954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 24 Principles, I, p. 289.
    • Principles , vol.1 , pp. 289
  • 59
    • 0010179051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 25 Essays, pp. 24-6.
    • Essays , pp. 24-26
  • 60
    • 0010179052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 26 Ibid., p. 102.
    • Essays , pp. 102
  • 61
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 27 James, Pragmatism, p. 57. For an account of Mach's views see Mach, 'The Analysis of Sensations: Anti-Metaphysical', Monist, 1 (1890-1), pp. 48-68. For Pearson's views on the meaning of empiricism see Karl Pearson, A Grammar of Science (London, 1937), pp. 18 f. See also Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 463.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 57
    • James1
  • 62
    • 0002282709 scopus 로고
    • The analysis of sensations: Anti-metaphysical
    • 27 James, Pragmatism, p. 57. For an account of Mach's views see Mach, 'The Analysis of Sensations: Anti-Metaphysical', Monist, 1 (1890-1), pp. 48-68. For Pearson's views on the meaning of empiricism see Karl Pearson, A Grammar of Science (London, 1937), pp. 18 f. See also Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 463.
    • (1890) Monist , vol.1 , pp. 48-68
    • Mach1
  • 63
    • 0003806983 scopus 로고
    • London
    • 27 James, Pragmatism, p. 57. For an account of Mach's views see Mach, 'The Analysis of Sensations: Anti-Metaphysical', Monist, 1 (1890-1), pp. 48-68. For Pearson's views on the meaning of empiricism see Karl Pearson, A Grammar of Science (London, 1937), pp. 18 f. See also Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 463.
    • (1937) A Grammar of Science
    • Pearson, K.1
  • 64
    • 0010097955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 27 James, Pragmatism, p. 57. For an account of Mach's views see Mach, 'The Analysis of Sensations: Anti-Metaphysical', Monist, 1 (1890-1), pp. 48-68. For Pearson's views on the meaning of empiricism see Karl Pearson, A Grammar of Science (London, 1937), pp. 18 f. See also Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 463.
    • Thought and Character , vol.2 , pp. 463
    • Perry1
  • 65
    • 0004202418 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • 28 John Dewey also was concerned about the 'currency of subjectivist interpretations'. J. Dewey, Essays in Experimental Logic (New York, 1953). For a discussion of the solipsistic implications of the empiricism of James see Charles W. Morris, 'Pragmatism and Metaphysics', Philosophical Review, XLIII (1934), pp. 549-64, p. 563. John E. Russell 'Pragmatism and Radical Empiricism', Philosophical Review, XV (1906), pp. 406-13, pp. 406 ff; John E. Russell, 'Solipsism: The Logical Issue of Radical Empiricism', Philosophical Review, XV (1906), pp. 606-13, pp. 606 ff. Cf. V.I. Lenin, Materialism and Empirio-Criticism (Peking, 1972). Lenin attacks the 'subjective idealism' of Mach and Pearson because of the implications this had for the materialist interpretation of history (pp. 99-103).
    • (1953) Essays in Experimental Logic
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 66
    • 0010100367 scopus 로고
    • Pragmatism and metaphysics
    • 28 John Dewey also was concerned about the 'currency of subjectivist interpretations'. J. Dewey, Essays in Experimental Logic (New York, 1953). For a discussion of the solipsistic implications of the empiricism of James see Charles W. Morris, 'Pragmatism and Metaphysics', Philosophical Review, XLIII (1934), pp. 549-64, p. 563. John E. Russell 'Pragmatism and Radical Empiricism', Philosophical Review, XV (1906), pp. 406-13, pp. 406 ff; John E. Russell, 'Solipsism: The Logical Issue of Radical Empiricism', Philosophical Review, XV (1906), pp. 606-13, pp. 606 ff. Cf. V.I. Lenin, Materialism and Empirio-Criticism (Peking, 1972). Lenin attacks the 'subjective idealism' of Mach and Pearson because of the implications this had for the materialist interpretation of history (pp. 99-103).
    • (1934) Philosophical Review , vol.43 , pp. 549-564
    • Morris, C.W.1
  • 67
    • 0010196217 scopus 로고
    • Pragmatism and radical empiricism
    • 28 John Dewey also was concerned about the 'currency of subjectivist interpretations'. J. Dewey, Essays in Experimental Logic (New York, 1953). For a discussion of the solipsistic implications of the empiricism of James see Charles W. Morris, 'Pragmatism and Metaphysics', Philosophical Review, XLIII (1934), pp. 549-64, p. 563. John E. Russell 'Pragmatism and Radical Empiricism', Philosophical Review, XV (1906), pp. 406-13, pp. 406 ff; John E. Russell, 'Solipsism: The Logical Issue of Radical Empiricism', Philosophical Review, XV (1906), pp. 606-13, pp. 606 ff. Cf. V.I. Lenin, Materialism and Empirio-Criticism (Peking, 1972). Lenin attacks the 'subjective idealism' of Mach and Pearson because of the implications this had for the materialist interpretation of history (pp. 99-103).
    • (1906) Philosophical Review , vol.15 , pp. 406-413
    • Russell, J.E.1
  • 68
    • 0010194666 scopus 로고
    • Solipsism: The logical issue of radical empiricism
    • 28 John Dewey also was concerned about the 'currency of subjectivist interpretations'. J. Dewey, Essays in Experimental Logic (New York, 1953). For a discussion of the solipsistic implications of the empiricism of James see Charles W. Morris, 'Pragmatism and Metaphysics', Philosophical Review, XLIII (1934), pp. 549-64, p. 563. John E. Russell 'Pragmatism and Radical Empiricism', Philosophical Review, XV (1906), pp. 406-13, pp. 406 ff; John E. Russell, 'Solipsism: The Logical Issue of Radical Empiricism', Philosophical Review, XV (1906), pp. 606-13, pp. 606 ff. Cf. V.I. Lenin, Materialism and Empirio-Criticism (Peking, 1972). Lenin attacks the 'subjective idealism' of Mach and Pearson because of the implications this had for the materialist interpretation of history (pp. 99-103).
    • (1906) Philosophical Review , vol.15 , pp. 606-613
    • Russell, J.E.1
  • 69
    • 0004179486 scopus 로고
    • Peking. Lenin attacks the 'subjective idealism' of Mach and Pearson because of the implications this had for the materialist interpretation of history
    • 28 John Dewey also was concerned about the 'currency of subjectivist interpretations'. J. Dewey, Essays in Experimental Logic (New York, 1953). For a discussion of the solipsistic implications of the empiricism of James see Charles W. Morris, 'Pragmatism and Metaphysics', Philosophical Review, XLIII (1934), pp. 549-64, p. 563. John E. Russell 'Pragmatism and Radical Empiricism', Philosophical Review, XV (1906), pp. 406-13, pp. 406 ff; John E. Russell, 'Solipsism: The Logical Issue of Radical Empiricism', Philosophical Review, XV (1906), pp. 606-13, pp. 606 ff. Cf. V.I. Lenin, Materialism and Empirio-Criticism (Peking, 1972). Lenin attacks the 'subjective idealism' of Mach and Pearson because of the implications this had for the materialist interpretation of history (pp. 99-103).
    • (1972) Materialism and Empirio-criticism , pp. 99-103
    • Lenin, V.I.1
  • 70
    • 0010158738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 29 Essays, pp. 24, 42.
    • Essays , pp. 24
  • 72
    • 0010205846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 31 Essays, p. 43.
    • Essays , pp. 43
  • 73
    • 0010213099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 32 Ibid., p. 23.
    • Essays , pp. 23
  • 74
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 33 James expressed concern that neo-Hegelian thought was on the ascendant at both Oxford and Harvard. James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 133; cf. p. 172. 'Unstiffen' was a word James borrowed from his follower, the Italian pragmatist Giovanni Papini. James, Pragmatism, pp. 79, 54. Cf. G. Papini, 'What Pragmatism is Like', trans. Katherine Royce, Popular Science Monthly, 71 (1907-8), pp. 351-8.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 133
    • James1
  • 75
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 33 James expressed concern that neo-Hegelian thought was on the ascendant at both Oxford and Harvard. James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 133; cf. p. 172. 'Unstiffen' was a word James borrowed from his follower, the Italian pragmatist Giovanni Papini. James, Pragmatism, pp. 79, 54. Cf. G. Papini, 'What Pragmatism is Like', trans. Katherine Royce, Popular Science Monthly, 71 (1907-8), pp. 351-8.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 79
    • James1
  • 76
    • 0010196218 scopus 로고
    • What pragmatism is like
    • trans. Katherine Royce
    • 33 James expressed concern that neo-Hegelian thought was on the ascendant at both Oxford and Harvard. James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 133; cf. p. 172. 'Unstiffen' was a word James borrowed from his follower, the Italian pragmatist Giovanni Papini. James, Pragmatism, pp. 79, 54. Cf. G. Papini, 'What Pragmatism is Like', trans. Katherine Royce, Popular Science Monthly, 71 (1907-8), pp. 351-8.
    • (1907) Popular Science Monthly , vol.71 , pp. 351-358
    • Papini, G.1
  • 81
    • 0010192072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 37 Ibid., pp. 222-4 ; cf. Essays, pp. 42-3.
    • Essays , pp. 42-43
  • 82
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 38 James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 258-64, 276. Cf. Kung Chuan Hsiao, Political Pluralism: A Study in Contemporary Thought (London, 1927), pp. 200-1.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 258-264
    • James1
  • 84
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 39 James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 247, 263, 274-6, 283. This description of mental states is cited in Perry, Thought and Character, p. 589. See also James, Pragmatism, p. 156, where he wrote that the '. . . world is One just so far as its parts hang together by any definite connexion. It is many just so far as any definite connexion fails to obtain'. Cf. ibid., pp. 79, 136-7. James also discusses the notion of manyness in oneness in Essays, pp. 50, 56-7. On the finitude of James's higher being also see Essays, p. 102.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 247
    • James1
  • 85
    • 0004351457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 39 James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 247, 263, 274-6, 283. This description of mental states is cited in Perry, Thought and Character, p. 58. See also James, Pragmatism, p. 156, where he wrote that the '. . . world is One just so far as its parts hang together by any definite connexion. It is many just so far as any definite connexion fails to obtain'. Cf. ibid., pp. 79, 136-7. James also discusses the notion of manyness in oneness in Essays, pp. 50, 56-7. On the finitude of James's higher being also see Essays, p. 102.
    • Thought and Character , pp. 589
    • Perry1
  • 86
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • where he wrote that the '. . . world is One just so far as its parts hang together by any definite connexion. It is many just so far as any definite connexion fails to obtain'.
    • 39 James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 247, 263, 274-6, 283. This description of mental states is cited in Perry, Thought and Character, p. 589. See also James, Pragmatism, p. 156, where he wrote that the '. . . world is One just so far as its parts hang together by any definite connexion. It is many just so far as any definite connexion fails to obtain'. Cf. ibid., pp. 79, 136-7. James also discusses the notion of manyness in oneness in Essays, pp. 50, 56-7. On the finitude of James's higher being also see Essays, p. 102.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 156
    • James1
  • 87
    • 84952490828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 39 James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 247, 263, 274-6, 283. This description of mental states is cited in Perry, Thought and Character, p. 589. See also James, Pragmatism, p. 156, where he wrote that the '. . . world is One just so far as its parts hang together by any definite connexion. It is many just so far as any definite connexion fails to obtain'. Cf. ibid., pp. 79, 136-7. James also discusses the notion of manyness in oneness in Essays, pp. 50, 56-7. On the finitude of James's higher being also see Essays, p. 102.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 79
  • 88
    • 84888687717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 39 James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 247, 263, 274-6, 283. This description of mental states is cited in Perry, Thought and Character, p. 589. See also James, Pragmatism, p. 156, where he wrote that the '. . . world is One just so far as its parts hang together by any definite connexion. It is many just so far as any definite connexion fails to obtain'. Cf. ibid., pp. 79, 136-7. James also discusses the notion of manyness in oneness in Essays, pp. 50, 56-7. On the finitude of James's higher being also see Essays, p. 102.
    • Essays , pp. 50
    • James1
  • 89
    • 0010140393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 39 James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 247, 263, 274-6, 283. This description of mental states is cited in Perry, Thought and Character, p. 589. See also James, Pragmatism, p. 156, where he wrote that the '. . . world is One just so far as its parts hang together by any definite connexion. It is many just so far as any definite connexion fails to obtain'. Cf. ibid., pp. 79, 136-7. James also discusses the notion of manyness in oneness in Essays, pp. 50, 56-7. On the finitude of James's higher being also see Essays, p. 102.
    • Essays , pp. 102
  • 90
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 40 James, Pragmatism, pp. 250, 255-7, 286. See also Henri Bergson, Creative Evolution, authorized trans. Arthur Mitchell (Lanham, 1983), pp. 53-4. Cf. Kallen, James and Bergson, pp. 63, 241 ; and Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 602.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 250
    • James1
  • 91
    • 0003452297 scopus 로고
    • authorized trans. Arthur Mitchell Lanham
    • 40 James, Pragmatism, pp. 250, 255-7, 286. See also Henri Bergson, Creative Evolution, authorized trans. Arthur Mitchell (Lanham, 1983), pp. 53-4. Cf. Kallen, James and Bergson, pp. 63, 241 ; and Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 602.
    • (1983) Creative Evolution , pp. 53-54
    • Bergson, H.1
  • 92
    • 0010097957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 40 James, Pragmatism, pp. 250, 255-7, 286. See also Henri Bergson, Creative Evolution, authorized trans. Arthur Mitchell (Lanham, 1983), pp. 53-4. Cf. Kallen, James and Bergson, pp. 63, 241 ; and Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 602.
    • James and Bergson , pp. 63
    • Kallen1
  • 93
    • 0010192074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 40 James, Pragmatism, pp. 250, 255-7, 286. See also Henri Bergson, Creative Evolution, authorized trans. Arthur Mitchell (Lanham, 1983), pp. 53-4. Cf. Kallen, James and Bergson, pp. 63, 241 ; and Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 602.
    • Thought and Character , vol.2 , pp. 602
    • Perry1
  • 94
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 41 James, Pragmatism, p. 136. James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 276, 283. See also Letters of William James, II, p. 292. cf. Perry, Thought and Character, Vol. II, pp. 373, 383 and James, Pragmatism, pp. 158-9, where James does hold up the logical possibility of a complete unity evolving in the universe.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 136
    • James1
  • 95
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 41 James, Pragmatism, p. 136. James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 276, 283. See also Letters of William James, II, p. 292. cf. Perry, Thought and Character, Vol. II, pp. 373, 383 and James, Pragmatism, pp. 158-9, where James does hold up the logical possibility of a complete unity evolving in the universe.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 276
    • James1
  • 96
    • 0010102422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 41 James, Pragmatism, p. 136. James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 276, 283. See also Letters of William James, II, p. 292. cf. Perry, Thought and Character, Vol. II, pp. 373, 383 and James, Pragmatism, pp. 158-9, where James does hold up the logical possibility of a complete unity evolving in the universe.
    • Letters of William James , vol.2 , pp. 292
  • 97
    • 85095462137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 41 James, Pragmatism, p. 136. James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 276, 283. See also Letters of William James, II, p. 292. cf. Perry, Thought and Character, Vol. II, pp. 373, 383 and James, Pragmatism, pp. 158-9, where James does hold up the logical possibility of a complete unity evolving in the universe.
    • Thought and Character , vol.2 , pp. 373
    • Perry1
  • 98
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • where James does hold up the logical possibility of a complete unity evolving in the universe
    • 41 James, Pragmatism, p. 136. James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 276, 283. See also Letters of William James, II, p. 292. cf. Perry, Thought and Character, Vol. II, pp. 373, 383 and James, Pragmatism, pp. 158-9, where James does hold up the logical possibility of a complete unity evolving in the universe.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 158-159
    • James1
  • 101
    • 0010131069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 43 Ibid., pp. 274, 277; cf. Essays, pp. 57, 138.
    • Essays , pp. 57
  • 102
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 44 James, Pragmatism, pp. ix, 45; cf. Letters of William James, II, p. 267.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 9
    • James1
  • 103
    • 0010153124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 44 James, Pragmatism, pp. ix, 45; cf. Letters of William James, II, p. 267.
    • Letters of William James , vol.2 , pp. 267
  • 104
    • 0010151460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 45 Essays, pp. 82-3. See also James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 273. Note also that in the Essays James uses the expression 'radical empiricism' to denote both an epistemology and a type of ontology. Radical empiricism implicates the flux of life. But the term empiricism also implies a certain method of approach which roughly approximates pragmatism; that being, the test of experience. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 161, 278.
    • Essays , pp. 82-83
  • 105
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 45 Essays, pp. 82-3. See also James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 273. Note also that in the Essays James uses the expression 'radical empiricism' to denote both an epistemology and a type of ontology. Radical empiricism implicates the flux of life. But the term empiricism also implies a certain method of approach which roughly approximates pragmatism; that being, the test of experience. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 161, 278.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 273
    • James1
  • 106
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 45 Essays, pp. 82-3. See also James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 273. Note also that in the Essays James uses the expression 'radical empiricism' to denote both an epistemology and a type of ontology. Radical empiricism implicates the flux of life. But the term empiricism also implies a certain method of approach which roughly approximates pragmatism; that being, the test of experience. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 161, 278.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 161
    • James1
  • 107
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 46 James, Pragmatism, p. 79; cf. James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 276. Synechism was a word which James obtained from Charles Sanders Peirce and it was a notion he also attributed to Bergson. On this point see Perry, Spirit of William James, pp. 108, 109 n. See also James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 283; and Essays, p. 26.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 79
    • James1
  • 108
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 46 James, Pragmatism, p. 79; cf. James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 276. Synechism was a word which James obtained from Charles Sanders Peirce and it was a notion he also attributed to Bergson. On this point see Perry, Spirit of William James, pp. 108, 109 n. See also James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 283; and Essays, p. 26.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 276
    • James1
  • 109
    • 0004343904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 46 James, Pragmatism, p. 79; cf. James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 276. Synechism was a word which James obtained from Charles Sanders Peirce and it was a notion he also attributed to Bergson. On this point see Perry, Spirit of William James, pp. 108, 109 n. See also James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 283; and Essays, p. 26.
    • Spirit of William James , pp. 108
    • Perry1
  • 110
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 46 James, Pragmatism, p. 79; cf. James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 276. Synechism was a word which James obtained from Charles Sanders Peirce and it was a notion he also attributed to Bergson. On this point see Perry, Spirit of William James, pp. 108, 109 n. See also James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 283; and Essays, p. 26.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 283
    • James1
  • 111
    • 0010131070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 46 James, Pragmatism, p. 79; cf. James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 276. Synechism was a word which James obtained from Charles Sanders Peirce and it was a notion he also attributed to Bergson. On this point see Perry, Spirit of William James, pp. 108, 109 n. See also James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 283; and Essays, p. 26.
    • Essays , pp. 26
  • 112
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 47 See James, Pragmatism, pp. 119, 254. James also wrote that since 'absolute monism forbids' the idea that the world is only partially unified 'pragmatism must turn its back on absolute monism, and follow pluralism's more empirical path', ibid., p. 161.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 119
    • James1
  • 113
    • 0010091611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 47 See James, Pragmatism, pp. 119, 254. James also wrote that since 'absolute monism forbids' the idea that the world is only partially unified 'pragmatism must turn its back on absolute monism, and follow pluralism's more empirical path', ibid., p. 161.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 161
  • 114
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 48 James, Pragmatism, pp. 254-5, 283. Cf. William James, The Will to Believe and other Essays in Popular Philosophy (New York, 1897), p. 177. See also Antonio Aliotta who wrote that for the pragmatist the element of plasticity in things ensures that mind can 'reorganise and reconstruct' reality. A. Aliotta, The Idealistic Reaction Against Science, trans. Agnes McCaskill (London, 1914), p. 179. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 242-3.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 254-255
    • James1
  • 115
    • 0004053759 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • 48 James, Pragmatism, pp. 254-5, 283. Cf. William James, The Will to Believe and other Essays in Popular Philosophy (New York, 1897), p. 177. See also Antonio Aliotta who wrote that for the pragmatist the element of plasticity in things ensures that mind can 'reorganise and reconstruct' reality. A. Aliotta, The Idealistic Reaction Against Science, trans. Agnes McCaskill (London, 1914), p. 179. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 242-3.
    • (1897) The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy , pp. 177
    • James, W.1
  • 116
    • 0010213102 scopus 로고
    • trans. Agnes McCaskill London
    • 48 James, Pragmatism, pp. 254-5, 283. Cf. William James, The Will to Believe and other Essays in Popular Philosophy (New York, 1897), p. 177. See also Antonio Aliotta who wrote that for the pragmatist the element of plasticity in things ensures that mind can 'reorganise and reconstruct' reality. A. Aliotta, The Idealistic Reaction Against Science, trans. Agnes McCaskill (London, 1914), p. 179. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 242-3.
    • (1914) The Idealistic Reaction Against Science , pp. 179
    • Aliotta, A.1
  • 117
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 48 James, Pragmatism, pp. 254-5, 283. Cf. William James, The Will to Believe and other Essays in Popular Philosophy (New York, 1897), p. 177. See also Antonio Aliotta who wrote that for the pragmatist the element of plasticity in things ensures that mind can 'reorganise and reconstruct' reality. A. Aliotta, The Idealistic Reaction Against Science, trans. Agnes McCaskill (London, 1914), p. 179. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 242-3.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 242-243
    • James1
  • 120
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 51 James, Pragmatism, p. 81. On the democratic character of pragmatism see A. Eustace Haydon, 'The Theological Trend of Pragmatism', The American Journal of Theology, XXIII (1919), pp. 401-16; and A.K. Rogers, English and American Philosophy since 1800: A Critical Survey (New York, 1922), p. 360. Cited in Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 176 n.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 81
    • James1
  • 121
    • 0010089315 scopus 로고
    • The theological trend of pragmatism
    • 51 James, Pragmatism, p. 81. On the democratic character of pragmatism see A. Eustace Haydon, 'The Theological Trend of Pragmatism', The American Journal of Theology, XXIII (1919), pp. 401-16; and A.K. Rogers, English and American Philosophy since 1800: A Critical Survey (New York, 1922), p. 360. Cited in Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 176 n.
    • (1919) The American Journal of Theology , vol.23 , pp. 401-416
    • Haydon, A.E.1
  • 122
    • 0010148318 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • 51 James, Pragmatism, p. 81. On the democratic character of pragmatism see A. Eustace Haydon, 'The Theological Trend of Pragmatism', The American Journal of Theology, XXIII (1919), pp. 401-16; and A.K. Rogers, English and American Philosophy since 1800: A Critical Survey (New York, 1922), p. 360. Cited in Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 176 n.
    • (1922) English and American Philosophy since 1800: A Critical Survey , pp. 360
    • Rogers, A.K.1
  • 123
    • 0004348006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 51 James, Pragmatism, p. 81. On the democratic character of pragmatism see A. Eustace Haydon, 'The Theological Trend of Pragmatism', The American Journal of Theology, XXIII (1919), pp. 401-16; and A.K. Rogers, English and American Philosophy since 1800: A Critical Survey (New York, 1922), p. 360. Cited in Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 176 n.
    • Political Pluralism
    • Hsiao1
  • 124
    • 0004295727 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • 52 James wrote: 'There is no point of view absolutely public and universal . . . The practical consequence of such a philosophy is the well-known democratic respect for the sacredness of individuality.' See James, Talks to Teachers (New York, 1899), p. v. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 265-6. See also Hsiao who wrote that the 'real motive behind James's vehement protest against the "block universe" . . . is not so much logical or metaphysical as ethical'. Hsiao argued this because, as he rightly points out, James does concede that from the point of view of logic the notion of the absolute is not objectionable. Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 187. James called his pluralism 'humanism in the widest sense', James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 272; cf. Essays, pp. 48, 100 ff.; and James, Pragmatism, pp. 239 ff.
    • (1899) Talks to Teachers , pp. 5
    • James1
  • 125
    • 0010091612 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 52 James wrote: 'There is no point of view absolutely public and universal . . . The practical consequence of such a philosophy is the well-known democratic respect for the sacredness of individuality.' See James, Talks to Teachers (New York, 1899), p. v. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 265-6. See also Hsiao who wrote that the 'real motive behind James's vehement protest against the "block universe" . . . is not so much logical or metaphysical as ethical'. Hsiao argued this because, as he rightly points out, James does concede that from the point of view of logic the notion of the absolute is not objectionable. Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 187. James called his pluralism 'humanism in the widest sense', James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 272; cf. Essays, pp. 48, 100 ff.; and James, Pragmatism, pp. 239 ff.
    • Thought and Character , vol.2 , pp. 265-266
    • Perry1
  • 126
    • 0004348006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 52 James wrote: 'There is no point of view absolutely public and universal . . . The practical consequence of such a philosophy is the well-known democratic respect for the sacredness of individuality.' See James, Talks to Teachers (New York, 1899), p. v. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 265-6. See also Hsiao who wrote that the 'real motive behind James's vehement protest against the "block universe" . . . is not so much logical or metaphysical as ethical'. Hsiao argued this because, as he rightly points out, James does concede that from the point of view of logic the notion of the absolute is not objectionable. Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 187. James called his pluralism 'humanism in the widest sense', James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 272; cf. Essays, pp. 48, 100 ff.; and James, Pragmatism, pp. 239 ff.
    • Political Pluralism , pp. 187
    • Hsiao1
  • 127
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 52 James wrote: 'There is no point of view absolutely public and universal . . . The practical consequence of such a philosophy is the well-known democratic respect for the sacredness of individuality.' See James, Talks to Teachers (New York, 1899), p. v. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 265-6. See also Hsiao who wrote that the 'real motive behind James's vehement protest against the "block universe" . . . is not so much logical or metaphysical as ethical'. Hsiao argued this because, as he rightly points out, James does concede that from the point of view of logic the notion of the absolute is not objectionable. Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 187. James called his pluralism 'humanism in the widest sense', James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 272; cf. Essays, pp. 48, 100 ff.; and James, Pragmatism, pp. 239 ff.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 272
    • James1
  • 128
    • 0010153123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 52 James wrote: 'There is no point of view absolutely public and universal . . . The practical consequence of such a philosophy is the well-known democratic respect for the sacredness of individuality.' See James, Talks to Teachers (New York, 1899), p. v. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 265-6. See also Hsiao who wrote that the 'real motive behind James's vehement protest against the "block universe" . . . is not so much logical or metaphysical as ethical'. Hsiao argued this because, as he rightly points out, James does concede that from the point of view of logic the notion of the absolute is not objectionable. Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 187. James called his pluralism 'humanism in the widest sense', James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 272; cf. Essays, pp. 48, 100 ff.; and James, Pragmatism, pp. 239 ff.
    • Essays , pp. 48
  • 129
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 52 James wrote: 'There is no point of view absolutely public and universal . . . The practical consequence of such a philosophy is the well-known democratic respect for the sacredness of individuality.' See James, Talks to Teachers (New York, 1899), p. v. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 265-6. See also Hsiao who wrote that the 'real motive behind James's vehement protest against the "block universe" . . . is not so much logical or metaphysical as ethical'. Hsiao argued this because, as he rightly points out, James does concede that from the point of view of logic the notion of the absolute is not objectionable. Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 187. James called his pluralism 'humanism in the widest sense', James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 272; cf. Essays, pp. 48, 100 ff.; and James, Pragmatism, pp. 239 ff.
    • Pragmatism
    • James1
  • 131
    • 0003172634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 54 Cited in Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 315. Perry argued that James's views on international polities reflected his individualist stance and his belief in the toleration and enjoyment of 'differences'. See also Letters of William James, II, p. 267; cf. p. 90. James wrote: 'I am against bigness and greatness in all their forms, and with the invisible molecular moral forces that work from individual to individual, stealing in through the crannies of the world like so many soft rootlets, or like the capillary oozing of water, and yet rending the hardest monuments of man's pride, if you give them time. The bigger the unit you deal with, the hollower, the more brutal, the more mendacious is the life displayed. So I am against all big organizations as such, national ones first and foremost; against all big successes and big results; and in favor of the eternal forces of truth which always work in the individual and immediately unsuccessful way, under-dogs always, till history comes, after they are long dead, and puts them on the top.'
    • Thought and Character , vol.2 , pp. 315
    • Perry1
  • 132
    • 0010153124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • James wrote: 'I am against bigness and greatness in all their forms, and with the invisible molecular moral forces that work from individual to individual, stealing in through the crannies of the world like so many soft rootlets, or like the capillary oozing of water, and yet rending the hardest monuments of man's pride, if you give them time. The bigger the unit you deal with, the hollower, the more brutal, the more mendacious is the life displayed. So I am against all big organizations as such, national ones first and foremost; against all big successes and big results; and in favor of the eternal forces of truth which always work in the individual and immediately unsuccessful way, under-dogs always, till history comes, after they are long dead, and puts them on the top.'
    • 54 Cited in Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 315. Perry argued that James's views on international polities reflected his individualist stance and his belief in the toleration and enjoyment of 'differences'. See also Letters of William James, II, p. 267; cf. p. 90. James wrote: 'I am against bigness and greatness in all their forms, and with the invisible molecular moral forces that work from individual to individual, stealing in through the crannies of the world like so many soft rootlets, or like the capillary oozing of water, and yet rending the hardest monuments of man's pride, if you give them time. The bigger the unit you deal with, the hollower, the more brutal, the more mendacious is the life displayed. So I am against all big organizations as such, national ones first and foremost; against all big successes and big results; and in favor of the eternal forces of truth which always work in the individual and immediately unsuccessful way, under-dogs always, till history comes, after they are long dead, and puts them on the top.'
    • Letters of William James , vol.2 , pp. 267
  • 133
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 55 James, Pragmatism, pp. 81, 259. See also James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 273-4.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 81
    • James1
  • 134
  • 135
    • 0010198564 scopus 로고
    • 13 March
    • 56 Letters, I, p. 321 (13 March 1921); cf. pp. 71 (24 March 1917), 75 (5 April 1917), 507 (6 June 1923), 551 (13 October 1923), 634 (15 July 1924).
    • (1921) Letters , vol.1 , pp. 321
  • 136
    • 0010203464 scopus 로고
    • 24 March
    • 56 Letters, I, p. 321 (13 March 1921); cf. pp. 71 (24 March 1917), 75 (5 April 1917), 507 (6 June 1923), 551 (13 October 1923), 634 (15 July 1924).
    • (1917) Letters , pp. 71
  • 137
    • 0010192075 scopus 로고
    • 5 April
    • 56 Letters, I, p. 321 (13 March 1921); cf. pp. 71 (24 March 1917), 75 (5 April 1917), 507 (6 June 1923), 551 (13 October 1923), 634 (15 July 1924).
    • (1917) Letters , pp. 75
  • 138
    • 0010198565 scopus 로고
    • 6 June
    • 56 Letters, I, p. 321 (13 March 1921); cf. pp. 71 (24 March 1917), 75 (5 April 1917), 507 (6 June 1923), 551 (13 October 1923), 634 (15 July 1924).
    • (1923) Letters , pp. 507
  • 139
    • 0010100370 scopus 로고
    • 13 October
    • 56 Letters, I, p. 321 (13 March 1921); cf. pp. 71 (24 March 1917), 75 (5 April 1917), 507 (6 June 1923), 551 (13 October 1923), 634 (15 July 1924).
    • (1923) Letters , pp. 551
  • 140
    • 0010131071 scopus 로고
    • 15 July
    • 56 Letters, I, p. 321 (13 March 1921); cf. pp. 71 (24 March 1917), 75 (5 April 1917), 507 (6 June 1923), 551 (13 October 1923), 634 (15 July 1924).
    • (1924) Letters , pp. 634
  • 141
    • 79958999318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 57 Authority, p. 312. On Laski's fundamental liberalism see Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 163 n. See also Max Beloff, 'The Age of Laski', The Fortnightly, CLXVII (1950), p. 380; and Carroll Hawkins, 'Harold J. Laski: A Preliminary Analysis', Political Science Quarterly, LXV (1950), pp. 376-92, p. 392.
    • Authority , pp. 312
  • 142
    • 0004348006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 57 Authority, p. 312. On Laski's fundamental liberalism see Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 163 n. See also Max Beloff, 'The Age of Laski', The Fortnightly, CLXVII (1950), p. 380; and Carroll Hawkins, 'Harold J. Laski: A Preliminary Analysis', Political Science Quarterly, LXV (1950), pp. 376-92, p. 392.
    • Political Pluralism
    • Hsiao1
  • 143
    • 84900231129 scopus 로고
    • The age of Laski
    • 57 Authority, p. 312. On Laski's fundamental liberalism see Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 163 n. See also Max Beloff, 'The Age of Laski', The Fortnightly, CLXVII (1950), p. 380; and Carroll Hawkins, 'Harold J. Laski: A Preliminary Analysis', Political Science Quarterly, LXV (1950), pp. 376-92, p. 392.
    • (1950) The Fortnightly , vol.167 , pp. 380
    • Beloff, M.1
  • 144
    • 0010143461 scopus 로고
    • Harold J. Laski: A preliminary analysis
    • 57 Authority, p. 312. On Laski's fundamental liberalism see Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 163 n. See also Max Beloff, 'The Age of Laski', The Fortnightly, CLXVII (1950), p. 380; and Carroll Hawkins, 'Harold J. Laski: A Preliminary Analysis', Political Science Quarterly, LXV (1950), pp. 376-92, p. 392.
    • (1950) Political Science Quarterly , vol.65 , pp. 376-392
    • Hawkins, C.1
  • 145
    • 0010186885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 58 Note that political monism for Laski referred, not only to theories of the general will, but also to positivistic arguments in favour of the unity of the state, Austin's theory of parliamentary sovereignty being one example. See Laski, 'The Pluralistic State', p. 563.
    • The Pluralistic State , pp. 563
    • Laski1
  • 146
    • 0010091613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 59 Studies, p. 6. Laski argued that just as Hegel led to Bismarck the absolute in metaphysics led to the absolute State in political theory. Laski wrote of the role played by a 'certain grim Hegelianism' in producing the authoritarian German state and thereby bringing about the Great War. See also Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', pp. 302-4; and Laski, 'The Personality of the State', p. 115. Laski wrote that the conception of the state as all-encompassing was highly significant: 'The result of it is the intense unity
    • Studies , pp. 6
  • 147
    • 0004348017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 59 Studies, p. 6. Laski argued that just as Hegel led to Bismarck the absolute in metaphysics led to the absolute State in political theory. Laski wrote of the role played by a 'certain grim Hegelianism' in producing the authoritarian German state and thereby bringing about the Great War. See also Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', pp. 302-4; and Laski, 'The Personality of the State', p. 115. Laski wrote that the conception of the state as all-encompassing was highly significant: 'The result of it is the intense unity of modern Germany, a unity philosophically justified by Hegel and politically exalted by Treitszchke.'
    • The Apotheosis of the State , pp. 302-304
    • Laski1
  • 148
    • 0004349810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Laski wrote that the conception of the state as all-encompassing was highly significant: 'The result of it is the intense unity of modern Germany, a unity philosophically justified by Hegel and politically exalted by Treitszchke
    • 59 Studies, p. 6. Laski argued that just as Hegel led to Bismarck the absolute in metaphysics led to the absolute State in political theory. Laski wrote of the role played by a 'certain grim Hegelianism' in producing the authoritarian German state and thereby bringing about the Great War. See also Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', pp. 302-4; and Laski, 'The Personality of the State', p. 115. Laski wrote that the conception of the state as all-encompassing was highly significant: 'The result of it is the intense unity of modern Germany, a unity philosophically justified by Hegel and politically exalted by Treitszchke.'
    • The Personality of the State , pp. 115
    • Laski1
  • 149
    • 0004324907 scopus 로고
    • New York, rev. edn.
    • 60 John Dewey, German Philosophy and Politics (New York, rev. edn., 1942). L.T. Hobhouse, The Metaphysical Theory of the State (London, 1918), pp. 134-6.
    • (1942) German Philosophy and Politics
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 151
    • 0010158741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 61 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 126, 126 n. John Dewey, cited in G.N. Sarma, 'Harold J. Laski', The Indian Journal of Political Science, XI (1950), pp. 133-44, p. 137. No reference is given for this citation. For historical and contemporary examples of the use of the terms pluralism and monism and manyness and oneness see Laski, 'The Sovereignty of the State', Journal of Philosophy, XIII (1916), pp. 85-97. Laski's article would seem to indicate that the political application of these terms was well entrenched, although George Sabine could write in 1923 as if the words monism and pluralism had only recently been injected into the area of political theory. See Sabine, 'Pluralism: A Point of View', American Political Science Review, XXIX (1923), pp. 34-50.
    • Political Pluralism , pp. 126
    • Hsiao1
  • 152
    • 0010158741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harold J. Laski
    • cited in G.N. Sarma
    • 61 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 126, 126 n. John Dewey, cited in G.N. Sarma, 'Harold J. Laski', The Indian Journal of Political Science, XI (1950), pp. 133-44, p. 137. No reference is given for this citation. For historical and contemporary examples of the use of the terms pluralism and monism and manyness and oneness see Laski, 'The Sovereignty of the State', Journal of Philosophy, XIII (1916), pp. 85-97. Laski's article would seem to indicate that the political application of these terms was well entrenched, although George Sabine could write in 1923 as if the words monism and pluralism had only recently been injected into the area of political theory. See Sabine, 'Pluralism: A Point of View', American Political Science Review, XXIX (1923), pp. 34-50.
    • (1950) The Indian Journal of Political Science , vol.11 , pp. 133-144
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 153
    • 0010158741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The sovereignty of the state
    • 61 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 126, 126 n. John Dewey, cited in G.N. Sarma, 'Harold J. Laski', The Indian Journal of Political Science, XI (1950), pp. 133-44, p. 137. No reference is given for this citation. For historical and contemporary examples of the use of the terms pluralism and monism and manyness and oneness see Laski, 'The Sovereignty of the State', Journal of Philosophy, XIII (1916), pp. 85-97. Laski's article would seem to indicate that the political application of these terms was well entrenched, although George Sabine could write in 1923 as if the words monism and pluralism had only recently been injected into the area of political theory. See Sabine, 'Pluralism: A Point of View', American Political Science Review, XXIX (1923), pp. 34-50.
    • (1916) Journal of Philosophy , vol.13 , pp. 85-97
    • Laski1
  • 154
    • 0010158741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pluralism: A point of view
    • 61 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 126, 126 n. John Dewey, cited in G.N. Sarma, 'Harold J. Laski', The Indian Journal of Political Science, XI (1950), pp. 133-44, p. 137. No reference is given for this citation. For historical and contemporary examples of the use of the terms pluralism and monism and manyness and oneness see Laski, 'The Sovereignty of the State', Journal of Philosophy, XIII (1916), pp. 85-97. Laski's article would seem to indicate that the political application of these terms was well entrenched, although George Sabine could write in 1923 as if the words monism and pluralism had only recently been injected into the area of political theory. See Sabine, 'Pluralism: A Point of View', American Political Science Review, XXIX (1923), pp. 34-50.
    • (1923) American Political Science Review , vol.29 , pp. 34-50
    • Sabine1
  • 155
    • 0010091614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cited in Perry
    • 62 Holmes cited in Perry, Thought and Character, Vol. II, pp. 457-9.
    • Thought and Character , vol.2 , pp. 457-459
    • Holmes1
  • 157
    • 0010131139 scopus 로고
    • 15 September
    • 64 Letters, I, pp. 20 (15 September 1916), 69-70 (23 March 1917). Holmes was referring to Laski's article 'The Political Theory of the Disruption', American Political Science Review, X (1916), pp. 437-64, pp. 462-4; reprinted in Studies.
    • (1916) Letters , vol.1 , pp. 20
  • 158
    • 0010100371 scopus 로고
    • 23 March
    • 64 Letters, I, pp. 20 (15 September 1916), 69-70 (23 March 1917). Holmes was referring to Laski's article 'The Political Theory of the Disruption', American Political Science Review, X (1916), pp. 437-64, pp. 462-4; reprinted in Studies.
    • (1917) Letters , pp. 69-70
  • 159
    • 84882181326 scopus 로고
    • The political theory of the disruption
    • reprinted in Studies
    • 64 Letters, I, pp. 20 (15 September 1916), 69-70 (23 March 1917). Holmes was referring to Laski's article 'The Political Theory of the Disruption', American Political Science Review, X (1916), pp. 437-64, pp. 462-4; reprinted in Studies.
    • (1916) American Political Science Review , vol.10 , pp. 437-464
    • Holmes1
  • 160
    • 0010102423 scopus 로고
    • 24 March
    • 65 Letters, p. 71 (24 March 1917).
    • (1917) Letters , pp. 71
  • 161
    • 0010091095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The division of power may connote a pluralistic world. It may throw to the winds that omnicompetent State for which Hegel in Germany and Austin in England have long and firmly stood the sponsors
    • 66 cf. Studies, p. 68. 'The division of power may connote a pluralistic world. It may throw to the winds that omnicompetent State for which Hegel in Germany and Austin in England have long and firmly stood the sponsors.'
    • Studies , pp. 68
  • 162
    • 0010198566 scopus 로고
    • 16 September
    • 67 Letters, I, p. 22 (16 September 1916). See also Laski, 'The Temper of the Present Time', The New Republic (18 February 1920), pp. 335-8, p. 336.
    • (1916) Letters , vol.1 , pp. 22
  • 163
    • 0010198567 scopus 로고
    • The temper of the present time
    • 18 February
    • 67 Letters, I, p. 22 (16 September 1916). See also Laski, 'The Temper of the Present Time', The New Republic (18 February 1920), pp. 335-8, p. 336.
    • (1920) The New Republic , pp. 335-338
    • Laski1
  • 164
    • 0010089316 scopus 로고
    • 5 April
    • 68 Letters, I, p. 75 (5 April 1917). See James, Pragmatism, p. 288-9: '. . . the only real reason I can think of why anything should ever come is that some one wishes it to he here'. Cf. James, Will to Believe, p. 59, where he wrote: '. . . often enough our faith before hand in an uncertified result is the only thing that makes the result come true'. James was aware of criticisms like those of Holmes. He noted in his Pragmatism, p. 258, that a less misleading title for his Will to Believe might be the 'right to believe'. James meant by this that as science gave only a partial account of the universe, individuals had a 'right to supplement' this knowledge with faith in an 'unseen spiritual order'. James, Will to Believe, p. 52. For an account of the misinterpretations surrounding James's will to believe see Cohen, 'on American Philosophy', II, p. 257. For Laski's comments on the notion of the will to believe see Letters, I, pp. 575 (28 July 1923), 725 (22 March 1925).
    • (1917) Letters , vol.1 , pp. 75
  • 165
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • . . . the only real reason I can think of why anything should ever come is that some one wishes it to he here
    • 68 Letters, I, p. 75 (5 April 1917). See James, Pragmatism, p. 288-9: '. . . the only real reason I can think of why anything should ever come is that some one wishes it to he here'. Cf. James, Will to Believe, p. 59, where he wrote: '. . . often enough our faith before hand in an uncertified result is the only thing that makes the result come true'. James was aware of criticisms like those of Holmes. He noted in his Pragmatism, p. 258, that a less misleading title for his Will to Believe might be the 'right to believe'. James meant by this that as science gave only a partial account of the universe, individuals had a 'right to supplement' this knowledge with faith in an 'unseen spiritual order'. James, Will to Believe, p. 52. For an account of the misinterpretations surrounding James's will to believe see Cohen, 'on American Philosophy', II, p. 257. For Laski's comments on the notion of the will to believe see Letters, I, pp. 575 (28 July 1923), 725 (22 March 1925).
    • Pragmatism , pp. 288-289
    • James1
  • 166
    • 0004346760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • where he wrote: '. . . often enough our faith before hand in an uncertified result is the only thing that makes the result come true'
    • 68 Letters, I, p. 75 (5 April 1917). See James, Pragmatism, p. 288-9: '. . . the only real reason I can think of why anything should ever come is that some one wishes it to he here'. Cf. James, Will to Believe, p. 59, where he wrote: '. . . often enough our faith before hand in an uncertified result is the only thing that makes the result come true'. James was aware of criticisms like those of Holmes. He noted in his Pragmatism, p. 258, that a less misleading title for his Will to Believe might be the 'right to believe'. James meant by this that as science gave only a partial account of the universe, individuals had a 'right to supplement' this knowledge with faith in an 'unseen spiritual order'. James, Will to Believe, p. 52. For an account of the misinterpretations surrounding James's will to believe see Cohen, 'on American Philosophy', II, p. 257. For Laski's comments on the notion of the will to believe see Letters, I, pp. 575 (28 July 1923), 725 (22 March 1925).
    • Will to Believe , pp. 59
    • James1
  • 167
    • 0010131140 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • that a less misleading title for his Will to Believe might be the 'right to believe'. James meant by this that as science gave only a partial account of the universe, individuals had a 'right to supplement' this knowledge with faith in an 'unseen spiritual order'
    • 68 Letters, I, p. 75 (5 April 1917). See James, Pragmatism, p. 288-9: '. . . the only real reason I can think of why anything should ever come is that some one wishes it to he here'. Cf. James, Will to Believe, p. 59, where he wrote: '. . . often enough our faith before hand in an uncertified result is the only thing that makes the result come true'. James was aware of criticisms like those of Holmes. He noted in his Pragmatism, p. 258, that a less misleading title for his Will to Believe might be the 'right to believe'. James meant by this that as science gave only a partial account of the universe, individuals had a 'right to supplement' this knowledge with faith in an 'unseen spiritual order'. James, Will to Believe, p. 52. For an account of the misinterpretations surrounding James's will to believe see Cohen, 'on American Philosophy', II, p. 257. For Laski's comments on the notion of the will to believe see Letters, I, pp. 575 (28 July 1923), 725 (22 March 1925).
    • Pragmatism , pp. 258
  • 168
    • 0004346760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 68 Letters, I, p. 75 (5 April 1917). See James, Pragmatism, p. 288-9: '. . . the only real reason I can think of why anything should ever come is that some one wishes it to he here'. Cf. James, Will to Believe, p. 59, where he wrote: '. . . often enough our faith before hand in an uncertified result is the only thing that makes the result come true'. James was aware of criticisms like those of Holmes. He noted in his Pragmatism, p. 258, that a less misleading title for his Will to Believe might be the 'right to believe'. James meant by this that as science gave only a partial account of the universe, individuals had a 'right to supplement' this knowledge with faith in an 'unseen spiritual order'. James, Will to Believe, p. 52. For an account of the misinterpretations surrounding James's will to believe see Cohen, 'on American Philosophy', II, p. 257. For Laski's comments on the notion of the will to believe see Letters, I, pp. 575 (28 July 1923), 725 (22 March 1925).
    • Will to Believe , pp. 52
    • James1
  • 169
    • 0010205849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 68 Letters, I, p. 75 (5 April 1917). See James, Pragmatism, p. 288-9: '. . . the only real reason I can think of why anything should ever come is that some one wishes it to he here'. Cf. James, Will to Believe, p. 59, where he wrote: '. . . often enough our faith before hand in an uncertified result is the only thing that makes the result come true', James was aware of criticisms like those of Holmes. He noted in his Pragmatism, p. 258, that a less misleading title for his Will to Believe might be the 'right to believe'. James meant by this that as science gave only a partial account of the universe, individuals had a 'right to supplement' this knowledge with faith in an 'unseen spiritual order'. James, Will to Believe, p. 52. For an account of the misinterpretations surrounding James's will to believe see Cohen, 'on American Philosophy', II, p. 257. For Laski's comments on the notion of the will to believe see Letters, I, pp. 575 (28 July 1923), 725 (22 March 1925).
    • On American Philosophy , vol.2 , pp. 257
    • Cohen1
  • 170
    • 0010148319 scopus 로고
    • 28 July
    • 68 Letters, I, p. 75 (5 April 1917). See James, Pragmatism, p. 288-9: '. . . the only real reason I can think of why anything should ever come is that some one wishes it to he here'. Cf. James, Will to Believe, p. 59, where he wrote: '. . . often enough our faith before hand in an uncertified result is the only thing that makes the result come true', James was aware of criticisms like those of Holmes. He noted in his Pragmatism, p. 258, that a less misleading title for his Will to Believe might be the 'right to believe'. James meant by this that as science gave only a partial account of the universe, individuals had a 'right to supplement' this knowledge with faith in an 'unseen spiritual order'. James, Will to Believe, p. 52. For an account of the misinterpretations surrounding James's will to believe see Cohen, 'on American Philosophy', II, p. 257. For Laski's comments on the notion of the will to believe see Letters, I, pp. 575 (28 July 1923), 725 (22 March 1925).
    • (1923) Letters , vol.1 , pp. 575
  • 171
    • 0010156697 scopus 로고
    • 22 March
    • 68 Letters, I, p. 75 (5 April 1917). See James, Pragmatism, p. 288-9: '. . . the only real reason I can think of why anything should ever come is that some one wishes it to he here'. Cf. James, Will to Believe, p. 59, where he wrote: '. . . often enough our faith before hand in an uncertified result is the only thing that makes the result come true', James was aware of criticisms like those of Holmes. He noted in his Pragmatism, p. 258, that a less misleading title for his Will to Believe might be the 'right to believe'. James meant by this that as science gave only a partial account of the universe, individuals had a 'right to supplement' this knowledge with faith in an 'unseen spiritual order'. James, Will to Believe, p. 52. For an account of the misinterpretations surrounding James's will to believe see Cohen, 'on American Philosophy', II, p. 257. For Laski's comments on the notion of the will to believe see Letters, I, pp. 575 (28 July 1923), 725 (22 March 1925).
    • (1925) Letters , pp. 725
  • 172
    • 0038977243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 69 Foundations, p. 261; cf. Studies, p. 23. See also Authority, p. 51: '. . . it is in events alone that we must search for our truths'. For James's discussion of the test of events see James, Pragmatism, p. 201; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 277.
    • Foundations , pp. 261
  • 173
    • 0010186886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 69 Foundations, p. 261; cf. Studies, p. 23. See also Authority, p. 51: '. . . it is in events alone that we must search for our truths'. For James's discussion of the test of events see James, Pragmatism, p. 201; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 277.
    • Studies , pp. 23
  • 174
    • 79958999318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • . . . it is in events alone that we must search for our truths
    • 69 Foundations, p. 261; cf. Studies, p. 23. See also Authority, p. 51: '. . . it is in events alone that we must search for our truths'. For James's discussion of the test of events see James, Pragmatism, p. 201; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 277.
    • Authority , pp. 51
  • 175
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 69 Foundations, p. 261; cf. Studies, p. 23. See also Authority, p. 51: '. . . it is in events alone that we must search for our truths'. For James's discussion of the test of events see James, Pragmatism, p. 201; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 277.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 201
    • James1
  • 176
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 69 Foundations, p. 261; cf. Studies, p. 23. See also Authority, p. 51: '. . . it is in events alone that we must search for our truths'. For James's discussion of the test of events see James, Pragmatism, p. 201; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 277.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 277
    • James1
  • 177
  • 178
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In this real world of sweat and dirt
    • 70 Laski, 'The Temper of the Present Time', p. 338. Cf. James, Pragmatism, p. 72. 'In this real world of sweat and dirt.'
    • Pragmatism , pp. 72
    • James1
  • 179
    • 0010099191 scopus 로고
    • 13 December
    • 71 There is no need to assume that Laski derived this description of the self exclusively from James. On the one hand he thought highly of James's Principles, and on rereading it thought that it was 'a great book and full of the happy guesses so characteristic of his mind', Letters, I, p. 571 (13 December 1923). Later, in the Grammar, p. 23, he cited James on the importance of instinctive propensities in order to explain social motives. Yet he also could use and adapt others to similar affect. See the social psychological studies of William McDougall, An Introduction to Social Psychology (London, 1936), pp. 7-10, 13. McDougall wanted psychologists to move beyond introspective examinations of the stream of consciousness and begin to concentrate on outward forms of social behaviour. In his reply to Lippmann, Laski adapts McDougall's argument that economic or political theories which ascribe uniform motives to men and uphold the commanding power of reason in human affairs are bound to prove inadequate. Cf. Laski, 'Note: A Reply to Walter Lippmann's Review of Laski', Authority (31 May 1919), pp. 149-50; and Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 425.
    • (1923) Letters , vol.1 , pp. 571
  • 180
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • he cited James on the importance of instinctive propensities in order to explain social motives. Yet he also could use and adapt others to similar affect
    • 71 There is no need to assume that Laski derived this description of the self exclusively from James. On the one hand he thought highly of James's Principles, and on rereading it thought that it was 'a great book and full of the happy guesses so characteristic of his mind', Letters, I, p. 571 (13 December 1923). Later, in the Grammar, p. 23, he cited James on the importance of instinctive propensities in order to explain social motives. Yet he also could use and adapt others to similar affect. See the social psychological studies of William McDougall, An Introduction to Social Psychology (London, 1936), pp. 7-10, 13. McDougall wanted psychologists to move beyond introspective examinations of the stream of consciousness and begin to concentrate on outward forms of social behaviour. In his reply to Lippmann, Laski adapts McDougall's argument that economic or political theories which ascribe uniform motives to men and uphold the commanding power of reason in human affairs are bound to prove inadequate. Cf. Laski, 'Note: A Reply to Walter Lippmann's Review of Laski', Authority (31 May 1919), pp. 149-50; and Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 425.
    • Grammar , pp. 23
  • 181
    • 0004257707 scopus 로고
    • London
    • 71 There is no need to assume that Laski derived this description of the self exclusively from James. On the one hand he thought highly of James's Principles, and on rereading it thought that it was 'a great book and full of the happy guesses so characteristic of his mind', Letters, I, p. 571 (13 December 1923). Later, in the Grammar, p. 23, he cited James on the importance of instinctive propensities in order to explain social motives. Yet he also could use and adapt others to similar affect. See the social psychological studies of William McDougall, An Introduction to Social Psychology (London, 1936), pp. 7-10, 13. McDougall wanted psychologists to move beyond introspective examinations of the stream of consciousness and begin to concentrate on outward forms of social behaviour. In his reply to Lippmann, Laski adapts McDougall's argument that economic or political theories which ascribe uniform motives to men and uphold the commanding power of reason in human affairs are bound to prove inadequate. Cf. Laski, 'Note: A Reply to Walter Lippmann's Review of Laski', Authority (31 May 1919), pp. 149-50; and Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 425.
    • (1936) An Introduction to Social Psychology , pp. 7-10
    • McDougall, W.1
  • 182
    • 0010194668 scopus 로고
    • Note: A reply to Walter Lippmann's review of Laski
    • 31 May
    • 71 There is no need to assume that Laski derived this description of the self exclusively from James. On the one hand he thought highly of James's Principles, and on rereading it thought that it was 'a great book and full of the happy guesses so characteristic of his mind', Letters, I, p. 571 (13 December 1923). Later, in the Grammar, p. 23, he cited James on the importance of instinctive propensities in order to explain social motives. Yet he also could use and adapt others to similar affect. See the social psychological studies of William McDougall, An Introduction to Social Psychology (London, 1936), pp. 7-10, 13. McDougall wanted psychologists to move beyond introspective examinations of the stream of consciousness and begin to concentrate on outward forms of social behaviour. In his reply to Lippmann, Laski adapts McDougall's argument that economic or political theories which ascribe uniform motives to men and uphold the commanding power of reason in human affairs are bound to prove inadequate. Cf. Laski, 'Note: A Reply to Walter Lippmann's Review of Laski', Authority (31 May 1919), pp. 149-50; and Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 425.
    • (1919) Authority , pp. 149-150
    • Laski1
  • 183
    • 0004349241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 71 There is no need to assume that Laski derived this description of the self exclusively from James. On the one hand he thought highly of James's Principles, and on rereading it thought that it was 'a great book and full of the happy guesses so characteristic of his mind', Letters, I, p. 571 (13 December 1923). Later, in the Grammar, p. 23, he cited James on the importance of instinctive propensities in order to explain social motives. Yet he also could use and adapt others to similar affect. See the social psychological studies of William McDougall, An Introduction to Social Psychology (London, 1936), pp. 7-10, 13. McDougall wanted psychologists to move beyond introspective examinations of the stream of consciousness and begin to concentrate on outward forms of social behaviour. In his reply to Lippmann, Laski adapts McDougall's argument that economic or political theories which ascribe uniform motives to men and uphold the commanding power of reason in human affairs are bound to prove inadequate. Cf. Laski, 'Note: A Reply to Walter Lippmann's Review of Laski', Authority (31 May 1919), pp. 149-50; and Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 425.
    • The Personality of Associations , pp. 425
    • Laski1
  • 184
    • 0010151462 scopus 로고
    • Review of Laski's authority in the modern state
    • 31 May
    • 72 Walter Lippmann, Review of Laski's Authority in the Modern State, The New Republic (31 May 1919), p. 149.
    • (1919) The New Republic , pp. 149
    • Lippmann, W.1
  • 185
    • 0010151463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 73 Laski, 'A Reply to Walter Lippmann', p. 149. Note that Laski's federalism is not geographical but is based on function. See Laski, 'The Pluralistic State', Philosophical Review, 28 (1919), pp. 562-75. 'We believe that this can best be achieved in a state of which the structure is not hierarchical but coördinate, in which, that is to say, sovereignty is partitioned upon some basis of function.' (Ibid., pp. 569-70.) See also Laski, 'Law in the State', p. 294. Laski argued that given that social facts are anarchical the law must be pluralistic.
    • A Reply to Walter Lippmann , pp. 149
    • Laski1
  • 186
    • 0010157629 scopus 로고
    • The pluralistic state
    • 73 Laski, 'A Reply to Walter Lippmann', p. 149. Note that Laski's federalism is not geographical but is based on function. See Laski, 'The Pluralistic State', Philosophical Review, 28 (1919), pp. 562-75. 'We believe that this can best be achieved in a state of which the structure is not hierarchical but coördinate, in which, that is to say, sovereignty is partitioned upon some basis of function.' (Ibid., pp. 569-70.) See also Laski, 'Law in the State', p. 294. Laski argued that given that social facts are anarchical the law must be pluralistic.
    • (1919) Philosophical Review , vol.28 , pp. 562-575
    • Laski1
  • 187
    • 53249114013 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 73 Laski, 'A Reply to Walter Lippmann', p. 149. Note that Laski's federalism is not geographical but is based on function. See Laski, 'The Pluralistic State', Philosophical Review, 28 (1919), pp. 562-75. 'We believe that this can best be achieved in a state of which the structure is not hierarchical but coördinate, in which, that is to say, sovereignty is partitioned upon some basis of function.' (Ibid., pp. 569-70.) See also Laski, 'Law in the State', p. 294. Laski argued that given that social facts are anarchical the law must be pluralistic.
    • Philosophical Review , pp. 569-570
  • 188
    • 0010205850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Laski argued that given that social facts are anarchical the law must be pluralistic
    • 73 Laski, 'A Reply to Walter Lippmann', p. 149. Note that Laski's federalism is not geographical but is based on function. See Laski, 'The Pluralistic State', Philosophical Review, 28 (1919), pp. 562-75. 'We believe that this can best be achieved in a state of which the structure is not hierarchical but coördinate, in which, that is to say, sovereignty is partitioned upon some basis of function.' (Ibid., pp. 569-70.) See also Laski, 'Law in the State', p. 294. Laski argued that given that social facts are anarchical the law must be pluralistic.
    • Law in the State , pp. 294
    • Laski1
  • 189
    • 0004349810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • where he wrote the will of the state 'is a will largely competing with other wills, and Darwin-wise, surviving only by its ability to cope with its environment . . . Again and again my allegiance may be divided between the different groups to which I belong. The state has to fight hard to maintain my allegiance
    • 74 See Laski, 'The Personality of the State', p. 116, where he wrote the will of the state 'is a will largely competing with other wills, and Darwin-wise, surviving only by its ability to cope with its environment . . . Again and again my allegiance may be divided between the different groups to which I belong. The state has to fight hard to maintain my allegiance.' See also Laski, 'Rousseau', New Republic (16 July 1919), pp. 363-4, p. 364; and Studies, p. 23.
    • The Personality of the State , pp. 116
    • Laski1
  • 190
    • 0010196221 scopus 로고
    • Rousseau
    • 16 July
    • 74 See Laski, 'The Personality of the State', p. 116, where he wrote the will of the state 'is a will largely competing with other wills, and Darwin-wise, surviving only by its ability to cope with its environment . . . Again and again my allegiance may be divided between the different groups to which I belong. The state has to fight hard to maintain my allegiance.' See also Laski, 'Rousseau', New Republic (16 July 1919), pp. 363-4, p. 364; and Studies, p. 23.
    • (1919) New Republic , pp. 363-364
    • Laski1
  • 191
    • 0010158743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 74 See Laski, 'The Personality of the State', p. 116, where he wrote the will of the state 'is a will largely competing with other wills, and Darwin-wise, surviving only by its ability to cope with its environment . . . Again and again my allegiance may be divided between the different groups to which I belong. The state has to fight hard to maintain my allegiance.' See also Laski, 'Rousseau', New Republic (16 July 1919), pp. 363-4, p. 364; and Studies, p. 23.
    • Studies , pp. 23
  • 193
    • 0004210683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 75 Laski, 'The Personality of the State', p. 116. James, The Will to Believe, p. 61.
    • The Will to Believe , pp. 61
    • James1
  • 195
    • 0010143463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cited in Sarma
    • 76 Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 425. Dewey cited in Sarma, 'Harold J. Laski', p. 137.
    • Harold J. Laski , pp. 137
    • Dewey1
  • 196
    • 0003172634 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 77 Perry, Thought and Character, Vol. II, p. 315. James noted: 'the smaller and more intimate is the truer, - the man more than the home, the home more than the state or the church'. Notes for Metaphysical Seminary (1903-4), cited in Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 383.
    • Thought and Character , vol.2 , pp. 315
    • Perry1
  • 197
    • 0000154709 scopus 로고
    • Notes for metaphysical seminary
    • 77 Perry, Thought and Character, Vol. II, p. 315. James noted: 'the smaller and more intimate is the truer, - the man more than the home, the home more than the state or the church'. Notes for Metaphysical Seminary (1903-4), cited in Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 383.
    • (1903) Thought and Character , vol.2 , pp. 383
    • Perry1
  • 198
    • 0004085243 scopus 로고
    • trans. and intro. Frederic William Maitland London
    • 78 See Otto Gierke, Political Theories of the Middle Age, trans. and intro. Frederic William Maitland (London, 1900), pp. xxx, xl. John Neville Figgis, 'Churches in the Modern State', in The Pluralist Theory of the State: Selected Writings of G.D.H. Cole, J.N. Figgis and H.J. Laski, ed. John Q. Hirst (London, 1989), pp. 111, 114.
    • (1900) Political Theories of the Middle Age , pp. 30
    • Gierke, O.1
  • 200
    • 0010194671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 79 Studies, p. 272; cf. Laski, 'The Personality of the State', p. 115; and Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', pp. 418-19.
    • Studies , pp. 272
  • 201
    • 0004349810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 79 Studies, p. 272; cf. Laski, 'The Personality of the State', p. 115; and Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', pp. 418-19.
    • The Personality of the State , pp. 115
    • Laski1
  • 202
    • 0004349241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 79 Studies, p. 272; cf. Laski, 'The Personality of the State', p. 115; and Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', pp. 418-19.
    • The Personality of Associations , pp. 418-419
    • Laski1
  • 205
    • 0004349810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 82 Laski, 'The Personality of the State', p. 115. Laski wrote that the 'personality is real for us; for when we assume its truth, the assumption leads to concrete differences'. See also Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 424; cf. p. 405. Laski wrote that there is a 'compulsion in our personalising. We do it because we must. We do it because we feel in these things the red blood of a living personality. Here are no mere abstractions of an over-exuberant imagination. The need is so apparent as to make plain the reality beneath.' Cf. James, Pragmatism, p. 200. James wrote that the pragmatist asks 'what concrete difference will its [a belief] being true make in any one's actual life?'.
    • The Personality of the State , pp. 115
    • Laski1
  • 206
    • 0004349241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 82 Laski, 'The Personality of the State', p. 115. Laski wrote that the 'personality is real for us; for when we assume its truth, the assumption leads to concrete differences'. See also Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 424; cf. p. 405. Laski wrote that there is a 'compulsion in our personalising. We do it because we must. We do it because we feel in these things the red blood of a living personality. Here are no mere abstractions of an over-exuberant imagination. The need is so apparent as to make plain the reality beneath.' Cf. James, Pragmatism, p. 200. James wrote that the pragmatist asks 'what concrete difference will its [a belief] being true make in any one's actual life?'.
    • The Personality of Associations , pp. 424
    • Laski1
  • 207
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • James wrote that the pragmatist asks 'what concrete difference will its [a belief] being true make in any one's actual life?'
    • 82 Laski, 'The Personality of the State', p. 115. Laski wrote that the 'personality is real for us; for when we assume its truth, the assumption leads to concrete differences'. See also Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 424; cf. p. 405. Laski wrote that there is a 'compulsion in our personalising. We do it because we must. We do it because we feel in these things the red blood of a living personality. Here are no mere abstractions of an over-exuberant imagination. The need is so apparent as to make plain the reality beneath.' Cf. James, Pragmatism, p. 200. James wrote that the pragmatist asks 'what concrete difference will its [a belief] being true make in any one's actual life?'.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 200
    • James1
  • 208
    • 0010131142 scopus 로고
    • On the correlation of fertility with social value
    • 83 In 1911, before going up to Oxford (first to study zoology and then history), Laski spent several months working in Karl Pearson's eugenics laboratory at University College, London, and would have been versed in James's empiricism. See Harold J. Laski, Karl Pearson et al., 'On the Correlation of Fertility with Social Value', Eugenics Laboratory Memoirs, XVIII (1913), pp. 1-72. Cf. Roger Soltau, 'Professor Laski and Political Science', Political Quarterly, XXII (1950), pp. 301-10, p. 301; and Herbert Deane, The Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski (New York, 1955), p. 5. Laski wrote 'If we become inductive-minded, and look at the facts of social life . . .', 'The Personality of the State', p. 115; cf. Laski, 'Rousseau', p. 364; and Grammar, pp. 29, 91.
    • (1913) Eugenics Laboratory Memoirs , vol.18 , pp. 1-72
    • Laski, H.J.1    Pearson, K.2
  • 209
    • 84977709314 scopus 로고
    • Professor Laski and political science
    • 83 In 1911, before going up to Oxford (first to study zoology and then history), Laski spent several months working in Karl Pearson's eugenics laboratory at University College, London, and would have been versed in James's empiricism. See Harold J. Laski, Karl Pearson et al., 'On the Correlation of Fertility with Social Value', Eugenics Laboratory Memoirs, XVIII (1913), pp. 1-72. Cf. Roger Soltau, 'Professor Laski and Political Science', Political Quarterly, XXII (1950), pp. 301-10, p. 301; and Herbert Deane, The Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski (New York, 1955), p. 5. Laski wrote 'If we become inductive-minded, and look at the facts of social life . . .', 'The Personality of the State', p. 115; cf. Laski, 'Rousseau', p. 364; and Grammar, pp. 29, 91.
    • (1950) Political Quarterly , vol.22 , pp. 301-310
    • Soltau, R.1
  • 210
    • 0010100372 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • 83 In 1911, before going up to Oxford (first to study zoology and then history), Laski spent several months working in Karl Pearson's eugenics laboratory at University College, London, and would have been versed in James's empiricism. See Harold J. Laski, Karl Pearson et al., 'On the Correlation of Fertility with Social Value', Eugenics Laboratory Memoirs, XVIII (1913), pp. 1-72. Cf. Roger Soltau, 'Professor Laski and Political Science', Political Quarterly, XXII (1950), pp. 301-10, p. 301; and Herbert Deane, The Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski (New York, 1955), p. 5. Laski wrote 'If we become inductive-minded, and look at the facts of social life . . .', 'The Personality of the State', p. 115; cf. Laski, 'Rousseau', p. 364; and Grammar, pp. 29, 91.
    • (1955) The Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski , pp. 5
    • Deane, H.1
  • 211
    • 0010186887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If we become inductive-minded, and look at the facts of social life
    • 83 In 1911, before going up to Oxford (first to study zoology and then history), Laski spent several months working in Karl Pearson's eugenics laboratory at University College, London, and would have been versed in James's empiricism. See Harold J. Laski, Karl Pearson et al., 'On the Correlation of Fertility with Social Value', Eugenics Laboratory Memoirs, XVIII (1913), pp. 1-72. Cf. Roger Soltau, 'Professor Laski and Political Science', Political Quarterly, XXII (1950), pp. 301-10, p. 301; and Herbert Deane, The Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski (New York, 1955), p. 5. Laski wrote 'If we become inductive-minded, and look at the facts of social life . . .', 'The Personality of the State', p. 115; cf. Laski, 'Rousseau', p. 364; and Grammar, pp. 29, 91.
    • The Personality of the State , pp. 115
    • Laski1
  • 212
    • 0010131072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 83 In 1911, before going up to Oxford (first to study zoology and then history), Laski spent several months working in Karl Pearson's eugenics laboratory at University College, London, and would have been versed in James's empiricism. See Harold J. Laski, Karl Pearson et al., 'On the Correlation of Fertility with Social Value', Eugenics Laboratory Memoirs, XVIII (1913), pp. 1-72. Cf. Roger Soltau, 'Professor Laski and Political Science', Political Quarterly, XXII (1950), pp. 301-10, p. 301; and Herbert Deane, The Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski (New York, 1955), p. 5. Laski wrote 'If we become inductive-minded, and look at the facts of social life . . .', 'The Personality of the State', p. 115; cf. Laski, 'Rousseau', p. 364; and Grammar, pp. 29, 91.
    • Rousseau , pp. 364
    • Laski1
  • 213
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 83 In 1911, before going up to Oxford (first to study zoology and then history), Laski spent several months working in Karl Pearson's eugenics laboratory at University College, London, and would have been versed in James's empiricism. See Harold J. Laski, Karl Pearson et al., 'On the Correlation of Fertility with Social Value', Eugenics Laboratory Memoirs, XVIII (1913), pp. 1-72. Cf. Roger Soltau, 'Professor Laski and Political Science', Political Quarterly, XXII (1950), pp. 301-10, p. 301; and Herbert Deane, The Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski (New York, 1955), p. 5. Laski wrote 'If we become inductive-minded, and look at the facts of social life . . .', 'The Personality of the State', p. 115; cf. Laski, 'Rousseau', p. 364; and Grammar, pp. 29, 91.
    • Grammar , pp. 29
  • 214
    • 0004349241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 84 This tendency was indeed apparent in Laski's own work as evidenced by his comment that law is not 'the result of one man's will, but of a complex fusion of wills. It distils the quintessence of an infinite number of personalities. It displays the character not of a Many, but of One, - it becomes, in fact, unified and coherent. Ultimately pluralistic, the interactions of its diversities make it essentially, within the sphere of its operations, a single thing. Men obey its commands. It acts. It influences.' Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 417. Cf. M.P. Follett, The New State: Group Organisation the Solution of Popular Government (New York, 1918), p. 283. Follett, drawing on James's philosophy, asks why pluraliste who follow Gierke and Maitland accept that a group personality can evolve but do not allow for a similar compounding of consciousness at the level of the state.
    • The Personality of Associations , pp. 417
    • Laski1
  • 215
    • 0003451437 scopus 로고
    • New York, Follett, drawing on James's philosophy, asks why pluraliste who follow Gierke and Maitland accept that a group personality can evolve but do not allow for a similar compounding of consciousness at the level of the state
    • 84 This tendency was indeed apparent in Laski's own work as evidenced by his comment that law is not 'the result of one man's will, but of a complex fusion of wills. It distils the quintessence of an infinite number of personalities. It displays the character not of a Many, but of One, - it becomes, in fact, unified and coherent. Ultimately pluralistic, the interactions of its diversities make it essentially, within the sphere of its operations, a single thing. Men obey its commands. It acts. It influences.' Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 417. Cf. M.P. Follett, The New State: Group Organisation the Solution of Popular Government (New York, 1918), p. 283. Follett, drawing on James's philosophy, asks why pluraliste who follow Gierke and Maitland accept that a group personality can evolve but do not allow for a similar compounding of consciousness at the level of the state.
    • (1918) The New State: Group Organisation the Solution of Popular Government , pp. 283
    • Follett, M.P.1
  • 216
    • 0000840430 scopus 로고
    • 28 February
    • 85 Laski was criticizing Figgis for failing to recognize that religious groups fighting for their freedom may in turn oppress others. Letters, I (28 February 1920), pp. 246-7.
    • (1920) Letters , vol.1 , pp. 246-247
  • 217
    • 0010151465 scopus 로고
    • Communal ghosts and other perils in social philosophy
    • 86 Morris Cohen, 'Communal Ghosts and other Perils in Social Philosophy', Journal of Philosophy, 16 (1919), pp. 673-90, p. 678. Laski later wrote that Cohen's essay showed him that 'he had lain under a dangerous spell woven, above all, by the exquisite charm of Maitland . . . and that bottomless pit of Gierke's learning.' Laski, 'Morris Cohen's Approach to Legal Philosophy', University of Chicago Law Review, 15 (1948), pp. 577-82, p. 574 ; cited in Letters, I, p. 223 n.
    • (1919) Journal of Philosophy , vol.16 , pp. 673-690
    • Cohen, M.1
  • 218
    • 0010091097 scopus 로고
    • Morris Cohen's approach to legal philosophy
    • 86 Morris Cohen, 'Communal Ghosts and other Perils in Social Philosophy', Journal of Philosophy, 16 (1919), pp. 673-90, p. 678. Laski later wrote that Cohen's essay showed him that 'he had lain under a dangerous spell woven, above all, by the exquisite charm of Maitland . . . and that bottomless pit of Gierke's learning.' Laski, 'Morris Cohen's Approach to Legal Philosophy', University of Chicago Law Review, 15 (1948), pp. 577-82, p. 574 ; cited in Letters, I, p. 223 n.
    • (1948) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.15 , pp. 577-582
    • Laski1
  • 219
    • 84895567807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 86 Morris Cohen, 'Communal Ghosts and other Perils in Social Philosophy', Journal of Philosophy, 16 (1919), pp. 673-90, p. 678. Laski later wrote that Cohen's essay showed him that 'he had lain under a dangerous spell woven, above all, by the exquisite charm of Maitland . . . and that bottomless pit of Gierke's learning.' Laski, 'Morris Cohen's Approach to Legal Philosophy', University of Chicago Law Review, 15 (1948), pp. 577-82, p. 574 ; cited in Letters, I, p. 223 n.
    • Letters , vol.1
  • 220
    • 0010097036 scopus 로고
    • 23 November
    • 87 See Holmes's letter to Morris Cohen (23 November 1919), in the 'Holmes-Cohen Correspondence', p. 17; Cohen, 'Communal Ghosts', pp. 676-9.
    • (1919) Holmes-Cohen Correspondence , pp. 17
  • 221
    • 0010153125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 87 See Holmes's letter to Morris Cohen (23 November 1919), in the 'Holmes-Cohen Correspondence', p. 17; Cohen, 'Communal Ghosts', pp. 676-9.
    • Communal Ghosts , pp. 676-679
    • Cohen1
  • 223
    • 79958999318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 88 James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 274. See also Authority, p. 313.
    • Authority , pp. 313
  • 224
    • 79958999318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 89 Authority, pp. 67-8; cf. Grammar, pp. 29, 67, 260.
    • Authority , pp. 67-68
  • 225
    • 0010092934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 89 Authority, pp. 67-8; cf. Grammar, pp. 29, 67, 260.
    • Grammar1
  • 226
    • 0010091099 scopus 로고
    • Law and the state
    • 90 Léon Duguit, 'Law and the State', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917), pp. 1-185, pp. 184-5. See also Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917-18), pp. 186-92, p. 189; and Laski, 'A Note on M. Hariou', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917-18), pp. 875-6, p. 876. I owe the ascription of this article on Hariou to Bernard Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism: The Development of Harold Laski's Political Thought (Assen, 1968), p. 222. As well as including an extensive bibliography of Laski's works Zylstra's study, to which I am indebted, is also very illuminating on the question of Laski's engagement with James's thought. Laski wrote the introduction to Duguit's Law in the Modern State, trans. Frida and Harold Laski (New York, 1970), originally published as Les Transformations du droit public (Paris, 1913).
    • (1917) Harvard Law Review , vol.31 , pp. 1-185
    • Duguit, L.1
  • 227
    • 0010143465 scopus 로고
    • A note on M. Duguit
    • 90 Léon Duguit, 'Law and the State', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917), pp. 1-185, pp. 184-5. See also Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917-18), pp. 186-92, p. 189; and Laski, 'A Note on M. Hariou', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917-18), pp. 875-6, p. 876. I owe the ascription of this article on Hariou to Bernard Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism: The Development of Harold Laski's Political Thought (Assen, 1968), p. 222. As well as including an extensive bibliography of Laski's works Zylstra's study, to which I am indebted, is also very illuminating on the question of Laski's engagement with James's thought. Laski wrote the introduction to Duguit's Law in the Modern State, trans. Frida and Harold Laski (New York, 1970), originally published as Les Transformations du droit public (Paris, 1913).
    • (1917) Harvard Law Review , vol.31 , pp. 186-192
    • Laski1
  • 228
    • 0010101929 scopus 로고
    • A note on M. Hariou
    • 90 Léon Duguit, 'Law and the State', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917), pp. 1-185, pp. 184-5. See also Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917-18), pp. 186-92, p. 189; and Laski, 'A Note on M. Hariou', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917-18), pp. 875-6, p. 876. I owe the ascription of this article on Hariou to Bernard Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism: The Development of Harold Laski's Political Thought (Assen, 1968), p. 222. As well as including an extensive bibliography of Laski's works Zylstra's study, to which I am indebted, is also very illuminating on the question of Laski's engagement with James's thought. Laski wrote the introduction to Duguit's Law in the Modern State, trans. Frida and Harold Laski (New York, 1970), originally published as Les Transformations du droit public (Paris, 1913).
    • (1917) Harvard Law Review , vol.31 , pp. 875-876
    • Laski1
  • 229
    • 0010157631 scopus 로고
    • Assen
    • 90 Léon Duguit, 'Law and the State', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917), pp. 1-185, pp. 184-5. See also Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917-18), pp. 186-92, p. 189; and Laski, 'A Note on M. Hariou', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917-18), pp. 875-6, p. 876. I owe the ascription of this article on Hariou to Bernard Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism: The Development of Harold Laski's Political Thought (Assen, 1968), p. 222. As well as including an extensive bibliography of Laski's works Zylstra's study, to which I am indebted, is also very illuminating on the question of Laski's engagement with James's thought. Laski wrote the introduction to Duguit's Law in the Modern State, trans. Frida and Harold Laski (New York, 1970), originally published as Les Transformations du droit public (Paris, 1913).
    • (1968) From Political Pluralism to Collectivism: The Development of Harold Laski's Political Thought , pp. 222
    • Zylstra, B.1
  • 230
    • 0010098577 scopus 로고
    • trans. Frida and Harold Laski New York
    • 90 Léon Duguit, 'Law and the State', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917), pp. 1-185, pp. 184-5. See also Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917-18), pp. 186-92, p. 189; and Laski, 'A Note on M. Hariou', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917-18), pp. 875-6, p. 876. I owe the ascription of this article on Hariou to Bernard Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism: The Development of Harold Laski's Political Thought (Assen, 1968), p. 222. As well as including an extensive bibliography of Laski's works Zylstra's study, to which I am indebted, is also very illuminating on the question of Laski's engagement with James's thought. Laski wrote the introduction to Duguit's Law in the Modern State, trans. Frida and Harold Laski (New York, 1970), originally published as Les Transformations du droit public (Paris, 1913).
    • (1970) Duguit's Law in the Modern State
  • 231
    • 0011695782 scopus 로고
    • originally published as Paris
    • 90 Léon Duguit, 'Law and the State', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917), pp. 1-185, pp. 184-5. See also Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917-18), pp. 186-92, p. 189; and Laski, 'A Note on M. Hariou', Harvard Law Review, XXXI (1917-18), pp. 875-6, p. 876. I owe the ascription of this article on Hariou to Bernard Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism: The Development of Harold Laski's Political Thought (Assen, 1968), p. 222. As well as including an extensive bibliography of Laski's works Zylstra's study, to which I am indebted, is also very illuminating on the question of Laski's engagement with James's thought. Laski wrote the introduction to Duguit's Law in the Modern State, trans. Frida and Harold Laski (New York, 1970), originally published as Les Transformations du droit public (Paris, 1913).
    • (1913) Les Transformations du Droit Public
  • 232
    • 0004349810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 91 Laski, 'The Personality of the State', pp. 116-17. See also Grammar, p. 256, where Laski wrote that the group is 'real in the same sense as the State is real. It has . . . an interest to promote'; cf. Foundations, p. 62. On Duguit's pragmatism see Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', p. 192; cf. Grammar, p. 577. For a further discussion of Duguit in the light of pragmatism see W. Y. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt in Politics: Syndicalism, Fascism and the Constitutional State (New York, 1928), pp. 251 ff.; cf. James, Pragmatism, p. 53.
    • The Personality of the State , pp. 116-117
    • Laski1
  • 233
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • where Laski wrote that the group is 'real in the same sense as the State is real. It has . . . an interest to promote'
    • 91 Laski, 'The Personality of the State', pp. 116-17. See also Grammar, p. 256, where Laski wrote that the group is 'real in the same sense as the State is real. It has . . . an interest to promote'; cf. Foundations, p. 62. On Duguit's pragmatism see Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', p. 192; cf. Grammar, p. 577. For a further discussion of Duguit in the light of pragmatism see W. Y. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt in Politics: Syndicalism, Fascism and the Constitutional State (New York, 1928), pp. 251 ff.; cf. James, Pragmatism, p. 53.
    • Grammar , pp. 256
  • 234
    • 0039807101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 91 Laski, 'The Personality of the State', pp. 116-17. See also Grammar, p. 256, where Laski wrote that the group is 'real in the same sense as the State is real. It has . . . an interest to promote'; cf. Foundations, p. 62. On Duguit's pragmatism see Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', p. 192; cf. Grammar, p. 577. For a further discussion of Duguit in the light of pragmatism see W. Y. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt in Politics: Syndicalism, Fascism and the Constitutional State (New York, 1928), pp. 251 ff.; cf. James, Pragmatism, p. 53.
    • Foundations , pp. 62
  • 235
    • 0004352329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 91 Laski, 'The Personality of the State', pp. 116-17. See also Grammar, p. 256, where Laski wrote that the group is 'real in the same sense as the State is real. It has . . . an interest to promote'; cf. Foundations, p. 62. On Duguit's pragmatism see Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', p. 192; cf. Grammar, p. 577. For a further discussion of Duguit in the light of pragmatism see W. Y. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt in Politics: Syndicalism, Fascism and the Constitutional State (New York, 1928), pp. 251 ff.; cf. James, Pragmatism, p. 53.
    • A Note on M. Duguit , pp. 192
    • Laski1
  • 236
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 91 Laski, 'The Personality of the State', pp. 116-17. See also Grammar, p. 256, where Laski wrote that the group is 'real in the same sense as the State is real. It has . . . an interest to promote'; cf. Foundations, p. 62. On Duguit's pragmatism see Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', p. 192; cf. Grammar, p. 577. For a further discussion of Duguit in the light of pragmatism see W. Y. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt in Politics: Syndicalism, Fascism and the Constitutional State (New York, 1928), pp. 251 ff.; cf. James, Pragmatism, p. 53.
    • Grammar , pp. 577
  • 237
    • 0004094774 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • 91 Laski, 'The Personality of the State', pp. 116-17. See also Grammar, p. 256, where Laski wrote that the group is 'real in the same sense as the State is real. It has . . . an interest to promote'; cf. Foundations, p. 62. On Duguit's pragmatism see Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', p. 192; cf. Grammar, p. 577. For a further discussion of Duguit in the light of pragmatism see W. Y. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt in Politics: Syndicalism, Fascism and the Constitutional State (New York, 1928), pp. 251 ff.; cf. James, Pragmatism, p. 53.
    • (1928) Pragmatic Revolt in Politics: Syndicalism, Fascism and the Constitutional State
    • Elliott, W.Y.1
  • 238
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 91 Laski, 'The Personality of the State', pp. 116-17. See also Grammar, p. 256, where Laski wrote that the group is 'real in the same sense as the State is real. It has . . . an interest to promote'; cf. Foundations, p. 62. On Duguit's pragmatism see Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', p. 192; cf. Grammar, p. 577. For a further discussion of Duguit in the light of pragmatism see W. Y. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt in Politics: Syndicalism, Fascism and the Constitutional State (New York, 1928), pp. 251 ff.; cf. James, Pragmatism, p. 53.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 53
    • James1
  • 239
    • 0004349241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • where he wrote of the state: 'We make it justify itself by its consequences . . . Like any other group, what it is and what it will be, it can be only by virtue of its achievement. So only can it hope to hand down undimmed the torch of its conscious life
    • 92 See Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 426, where he wrote of the state: 'We make it justify itself by its consequences . . . Like any other group, what it is and what it will be, it can be only by virtue of its achievement. So only can it hope to hand down undimmed the torch of its conscious life.' Cf. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', p. 304; Authority, p. 69; and Grammar, pp. 39, 283.
    • The Personality of Associations , pp. 426
    • Laski1
  • 240
    • 0004348017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 92 See Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 426, where he wrote of the state: 'We make it justify itself by its consequences . . . Like any other group, what it is and what it will be, it can be only by virtue of its achievement. So only can it hope to hand down undimmed the torch of its conscious life.' Cf. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', p. 304; Authority, p. 69; and Grammar, pp. 39, 283.
    • The Apotheosis of the State , pp. 304
    • Laski1
  • 241
    • 79958999318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 92 See Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 426, where he wrote of the state: 'We make it justify itself by its consequences . . . Like any other group, what it is and what it will be, it can be only by virtue of its achievement. So only can it hope to hand down undimmed the torch of its conscious life.' Cf. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', p. 304; Authority, p. 69; and Grammar, pp. 39, 283.
    • Authority , pp. 69
  • 242
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 92 See Laski, 'The Personality of Associations', p. 426, where he wrote of the state: 'We make it justify itself by its consequences . . . Like any other group, what it is and what it will be, it can be only by virtue of its achievement. So only can it hope to hand down undimmed the torch of its conscious life.' Cf. Laski, 'The Apotheosis of the State', p. 304; Authority, p. 69; and Grammar, pp. 39, 283.
    • Grammar , pp. 39
  • 243
    • 0010148321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 93 Laski, Studies, p. 18; and Grammar, p. 35. On the decline of groups see Laski, 'Political Science In Great Britain', American Political Science Review, XIX (1925), pp. 96-9, p. 99. For Laski's comments on the value of the state see Letters, I, pp. 246-7 (28 February 1920).
    • Studies , pp. 18
    • Laski1
  • 244
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 93 Laski, Studies, p. 18; and Grammar, p. 35. On the decline of groups see Laski, 'Political Science In Great Britain', American Political Science Review, XIX (1925), pp. 96-9, p. 99. For Laski's comments on the value of the state see Letters, I, pp. 246-7 (28 February 1920).
    • Grammar , pp. 35
  • 245
    • 84959702906 scopus 로고
    • Political science in Great Britain
    • 93 Laski, Studies, p. 18; and Grammar, p. 35. On the decline of groups see Laski, 'Political Science In Great Britain', American Political Science Review, XIX (1925), pp. 96-9, p. 99. For Laski's comments on the value of the state see Letters, I, pp. 246-7 (28 February 1920).
    • (1925) American Political Science Review , vol.19 , pp. 96-99
    • Laski1
  • 246
    • 0000840430 scopus 로고
    • 28 February
    • 93 Laski, Studies, p. 18; and Grammar, p. 35. On the decline of groups see Laski, 'Political Science In Great Britain', American Political Science Review, XIX (1925), pp. 96-9, p. 99. For Laski's comments on the value of the state see Letters, I, pp. 246-7 (28 February 1920).
    • (1920) Letters , vol.1 , pp. 246-247
  • 247
    • 79958999318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 94 See Authority, p. 123. 'For no theory can now hope for survival which is not based upon the changing necessities of social life. The obvious generalisation that the creation of dogma carries with it . . . its own negation'. See also his comment on the 'relativity of ideas', ibid., p. 124. For further comments on the changeful nature of the human world see Grammar, p. 90: 'Our natural order is, at any moment, a problem of pragmatic analysis. Its only permanence lies in the certainty that it will change.' See also ibid., pp. 24, 101. Laski cited Dewey in Studies, p. 23. No reference for this expression was given but Laski had read and enjoyed Dewey's Essays in Experimental Logic. See Letters, I, p. 25 (24 September 1916). For Dewey's comments on the experimental method see Dewey, Essays, pp. 100-2, 241, 306, 332, 442. Note that Dewey's view of experimentation was more scientific and less voluntaristic than that of James. See Dewey, Essays, p. 347. On this point see also Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 83; and Sidney Hook, The Metaphysics of Pragmatism (New York, 1927), pp. 6-9. On Laski's experimental attitude towards political theory and the state see also Authority, p. 34; and Grammar, pp. 21, 100.
    • Authority , pp. 123
  • 248
    • 79958999318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 94 See Authority, p. 123. 'For no theory can now hope for survival which is not based upon the changing necessities of social life. The obvious generalisation that the creation of dogma carries with it . . . its own negation'. See also his comment on the 'relativity of ideas', ibid., p. 124. For further comments on the changeful nature of the human world see Grammar, p. 90: 'Our natural order is, at any moment, a problem of pragmatic analysis. Its only permanence lies in the certainty that it will change.' See also ibid., pp. 24, 101. Laski cited Dewey in Studies, p. 23. No reference for this expression was given but Laski had read and enjoyed Dewey's Essays in Experimental Logic. See Letters, I, p. 25 (24 September 1916). For Dewey's comments on the experimental method see Dewey, Essays, pp. 100-2, 241, 306, 332, 442. Note that Dewey's view of experimentation was more scientific and less voluntaristic than that of James. See Dewey, Essays, p. 347. On this point see also Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 83; and Sidney Hook, The Metaphysics of Pragmatism (New York, 1927), pp. 6-9. On Laski's experimental attitude towards political theory and the state see also Authority, p. 34; and Grammar, pp. 21, 100.
    • Authority , pp. 124
  • 249
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 94 See Authority, p. 123. 'For no theory can now hope for survival which is not based upon the changing necessities of social life. The obvious generalisation that the creation of dogma carries with it . . . its own negation'. See also his comment on the 'relativity of ideas', ibid., p. 124. For further comments on the changeful nature of the human world see Grammar, p. 90: 'Our natural order is, at any moment, a problem of pragmatic analysis. Its only permanence lies in the certainty that it will change.' See also ibid., pp. 24, 101. Laski cited Dewey in Studies, p. 23. No reference for this expression was given but Laski had read and enjoyed Dewey's Essays in Experimental Logic. See Letters, I, p. 25 (24 September 1916). For Dewey's comments on the experimental method see Dewey, Essays, pp. 100-2, 241, 306, 332, 442. Note that Dewey's view of experimentation was more scientific and less voluntaristic than that of James. See Dewey, Essays, p. 347. On this point see also Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 83; and Sidney Hook, The Metaphysics of Pragmatism (New York, 1927), pp. 6-9. On Laski's experimental attitude towards political theory and the state see also Authority, p. 34; and Grammar, pp. 21, 100.
    • Grammar , pp. 90
  • 250
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 94 See Authority, p. 123. 'For no theory can now hope for survival which is not based upon the changing necessities of social life. The obvious generalisation that the creation of dogma carries with it . . . its own negation'. See also his comment on the 'relativity of ideas', ibid., p. 124. For further comments on the changeful nature of the human world see Grammar, p. 90: 'Our natural order is, at any moment, a problem of pragmatic analysis. Its only permanence lies in the certainty that it will change.' See also ibid., pp. 24, 101. Laski cited Dewey in Studies, p. 23. No reference for this expression was given but Laski had read and enjoyed Dewey's Essays in Experimental Logic. See Letters, I, p. 25 (24 September 1916). For Dewey's comments on the experimental method see Dewey, Essays, pp. 100-2, 241, 306, 332, 442. Note that Dewey's view of experimentation was more scientific and less voluntaristic than that of James. See Dewey, Essays, p. 347. On this point see also Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 83; and Sidney Hook, The Metaphysics of Pragmatism (New York, 1927), pp. 6-9. On Laski's experimental attitude towards political theory and the state see also Authority, p. 34; and Grammar, pp. 21, 100.
    • Grammar , pp. 24
  • 251
    • 0010148321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cited Dewey in
    • 94 See Authority, p. 123. 'For no theory can now hope for survival which is not based upon the changing necessities of social life. The obvious generalisation that the creation of dogma carries with it . . . its own negation'. See also his comment on the 'relativity of ideas', ibid., p. 124. For further comments on the changeful nature of the human world see Grammar, p. 90: 'Our natural order is, at any moment, a problem of pragmatic analysis. Its only permanence lies in the certainty that it will change.' See also ibid., pp. 24, 101. Laski cited Dewey in Studies, p. 23. No reference for this expression was given but Laski had read and enjoyed Dewey's Essays in Experimental Logic. See Letters, I, p. 25 (24 September 1916). For Dewey's comments on the experimental method see Dewey, Essays, pp. 100-2, 241, 306, 332, 442. Note that Dewey's view of experimentation was more scientific and less voluntaristic than that of James. See Dewey, Essays, p. 347. On this point see also Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 83; and Sidney Hook, The Metaphysics of Pragmatism (New York, 1927), pp. 6-9. On Laski's experimental attitude towards political theory and the state see also Authority, p. 34; and Grammar, pp. 21, 100.
    • Studies , pp. 23
    • Laski1
  • 252
    • 0010092935 scopus 로고
    • 24 September
    • 94 See Authority, p. 123. 'For no theory can now hope for survival which is not based upon the changing necessities of social life. The obvious generalisation that the creation of dogma carries with it . . . its own negation'. See also his comment on the 'relativity of ideas', ibid., p. 124. For further comments on the changeful nature of the human world see Grammar, p. 90: 'Our natural order is, at any moment, a problem of pragmatic analysis. Its only permanence lies in the certainty that it will change.' See also ibid., pp. 24, 101. Laski cited Dewey in Studies, p. 23. No reference for this expression was given but Laski had read and enjoyed Dewey's Essays in Experimental Logic. See Letters, I, p. 25 (24 September 1916). For Dewey's comments on the experimental method see Dewey, Essays, pp. 100-2, 241, 306, 332, 442. Note that Dewey's view of experimentation was more scientific and less voluntaristic than that of James. See Dewey, Essays, p. 347. On this point see also Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 83; and Sidney Hook, The Metaphysics of Pragmatism (New York, 1927), pp. 6-9. On Laski's experimental attitude towards political theory and the state see also Authority, p. 34; and Grammar, pp. 21, 100.
    • (1916) Letters , vol.1 , pp. 25
  • 253
    • 0010203465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 94 See Authority, p. 123. 'For no theory can now hope for survival which is not based upon the changing necessities of social life. The obvious generalisation that the creation of dogma carries with it . . . its own negation'. See also his comment on the 'relativity of ideas', ibid., p. 124. For further comments on the changeful nature of the human world see Grammar, p. 90: 'Our natural order is, at any moment, a problem of pragmatic analysis. Its only permanence lies in the certainty that it will change.' See also ibid., pp. 24, 101. Laski cited Dewey in Studies, p. 23. No reference for this expression was
    • Essays , pp. 100-102
    • Dewey1
  • 254
    • 0010203465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 94 See Authority, p. 123. 'For no theory can now hope for survival which is not based upon the changing necessities of social life. The obvious generalisation that the creation of dogma carries with it . . . its own negation'. See also his comment on the 'relativity of ideas', ibid., p. 124. For further comments on the changeful nature of the human world see Grammar, p. 90: 'Our natural order is, at any moment, a problem of pragmatic analysis. Its only permanence lies in the certainty that it will change.' See also ibid., pp. 24, 101. Laski cited Dewey in Studies, p. 23. No reference for this expression was given but Laski had read and enjoyed Dewey's Essays in Experimental Logic. See Letters, I, p. 25 (24 September 1916). For Dewey's comments on the experimental method see Dewey, Essays, pp. 100-2, 241, 306, 332, 442. Note that Dewey's view of experimentation was more scientific and less voluntaristic than that of James. See Dewey, Essays, p. 347. On this point see also Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 83; and Sidney Hook, The Metaphysics of Pragmatism (New York, 1927), pp. 6-9. On Laski's experimental attitude towards political theory and the state see also Authority, p. 34; and Grammar, pp. 21, 100.
    • Essays , pp. 347
    • Dewey1
  • 255
    • 0002774492 scopus 로고
    • On American philosophy
    • 17 March
    • 94 See Authority, p. 123. 'For no theory can now hope for survival which is not based upon the changing necessities of social life. The obvious generalisation that the creation of dogma carries with it . . . its own negation'. See also his comment on the 'relativity of ideas', ibid., p. 124. For further comments on the changeful nature of the human world see Grammar, p. 90: 'Our natural order is, at any moment, a problem of pragmatic analysis. Its only permanence lies in the certainty that it will change.' See also ibid., pp. 24, 101. Laski cited Dewey in Studies, p. 23. No reference for this expression was given but Laski had read and enjoyed Dewey's Essays in Experimental Logic. See Letters, I, p. 25 (24 September 1916). For Dewey's comments on the experimental method see Dewey, Essays, pp. 100-2, 241, 306, 332, 442. Note that Dewey's view of experimentation was more scientific and less voluntaristic than that of James. See Dewey, Essays, p. 347. On this point see also Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 83; and Sidney Hook, The Metaphysics of Pragmatism (New York, 1927), pp. 6-9. On Laski's experimental attitude towards political theory and the state see also Authority, p. 34; and Grammar, pp. 21, 100.
    • (1920) The New Republic , pp. 82-86
    • Cohen, M.R.1
  • 256
    • 0010091101 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • 94 See Authority, p. 123. 'For no theory can now hope for survival which is not based upon the changing necessities of social life. The obvious generalisation that the creation of dogma carries with it . . . its own negation'. See also his comment on the 'relativity of ideas', ibid., p. 124. For further comments on the changeful nature of the human world see Grammar, p. 90: 'Our natural order is, at any moment, a problem of pragmatic analysis. Its only permanence lies in the certainty that it will change.' See also ibid., pp. 24, 101. Laski cited Dewey in Studies, p. 23. No reference for this expression was given but Laski had read and enjoyed Dewey's Essays in Experimental Logic. See Letters, I, p. 25 (24 September 1916). For Dewey's comments on the experimental method see Dewey, Essays, pp. 100-2, 241, 306, 332, 442. Note that Dewey's view of experimentation was more scientific and less voluntaristic than that of James. See Dewey, Essays, p. 347. On this point see also Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 83; and Sidney Hook, The Metaphysics of Pragmatism (New York, 1927), pp. 6-9. On Laski's experimental attitude towards political theory and the state see also Authority, p. 34; and Grammar, pp. 21, 100.
    • (1927) The Metaphysics of Pragmatism , pp. 6-9
    • Hook, S.1
  • 257
    • 79958999318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 94 See Authority, p. 123. 'For no theory can now hope for survival which is not based upon the changing necessities of social life. The obvious generalisation that the creation of dogma carries with it . . . its own negation'. See also his comment on the 'relativity of ideas', ibid., p. 124. For further comments on the changeful nature of the human world see Grammar, p. 90: 'Our natural order is, at any moment, a problem of pragmatic analysis. Its only permanence lies in the certainty that it will change.' See also ibid., pp. 24, 101. Laski cited Dewey in Studies, p. 23. No reference for this expression was given but Laski had read and enjoyed Dewey's Essays in Experimental Logic. See Letters, I, p. 25 (24 September 1916). For Dewey's comments on the experimental method see Dewey, Essays, pp. 100-2, 241, 306, 332, 442. Note that Dewey's view of experimentation was more scientific and less voluntaristic than that of James. See Dewey, Essays, p. 347. On this point see also Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 83; and Sidney Hook, The Metaphysics of Pragmatism (New York, 1927), pp. 6-9. On Laski's experimental attitude towards political theory and the state see also Authority, p. 34; and Grammar, pp. 21, 100.
    • Authority , pp. 34
  • 258
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 94 See Authority, p. 123. 'For no theory can now hope for survival which is not based upon the changing necessities of social life. The obvious generalisation that the creation of dogma carries with it . . . its own negation'. See also his comment on the 'relativity of ideas', ibid., p. 124. For further comments on the changeful nature of the human world see Grammar, p. 90: 'Our natural order is, at any moment, a problem of pragmatic analysis. Its only permanence lies in the certainty that it will change.' See also ibid., pp. 24, 101. Laski cited Dewey in Studies, p. 23. No reference for this expression was given but Laski had read and enjoyed Dewey's Essays in Experimental Logic. See Letters, I, p. 25 (24 September 1916). For Dewey's comments on the experimental method see Dewey, Essays, pp. 100-2, 241, 306, 332, 442. Note that Dewey's view of experimentation was more scientific and less voluntaristic than that of James. See Dewey, Essays, p. 347. On this point see also Morris R. Cohen, 'On American Philosophy', The New Republic (17 March 1920), pp. 82-6, p. 83; and Sidney Hook, The Metaphysics of Pragmatism (New York, 1927), pp. 6-9. On Laski's experimental attitude towards political theory and the state see also Authority, p. 34; and Grammar, pp. 21, 100.
    • Grammar , pp. 21
  • 259
    • 0010091618 scopus 로고
    • Social absolutism
    • 9 February
    • 95 John Dewey, 'Social Absolutism', The New Republic (9 February 1921), pp. 315-18, pp. 316-17. Laski, 'The Value and Defects of the Marxist Philosophy', Current History (October 1928), pp. 23-9, p. 29. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 282, 288, 292-3. Laski, 'The Roosevelt Experiment', Atlantic Monthly, CLIII (1934), pp. 143-53, pp. 143-4. Laski, 'Choosing the Planners', in Plan for Britain: A Collection of Essays prepared for the Fabian Society (London, 1943), p. 114. For Laski's thoughts on world government see Grammar, pp. 588 f.
    • (1921) The New Republic , pp. 315-318
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 260
    • 0010156698 scopus 로고
    • The value and defects of the marxist philosophy
    • October
    • 95 John Dewey, 'Social Absolutism', The New Republic (9 February 1921), pp. 315-18, pp. 316-17. Laski, 'The Value and Defects of the Marxist Philosophy', Current History (October 1928), pp. 23-9, p. 29. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 282, 288, 292-3. Laski, 'The Roosevelt Experiment', Atlantic Monthly, CLIII (1934), pp. 143-53, pp. 143-4. Laski, 'Choosing the Planners', in Plan for Britain: A Collection of Essays prepared for the Fabian Society (London, 1943), p. 114. For Laski's thoughts on world government see Grammar, pp. 588 f.
    • (1928) Current History , pp. 23-29
    • Laski1
  • 261
    • 0001231526 scopus 로고
    • Law and the state
    • 95 John Dewey, 'Social Absolutism', The New Republic (9 February 1921), pp. 315-18, pp. 316-17. Laski, 'The Value and Defects of the Marxist Philosophy', Current History (October 1928), pp. 23-9, p. 29. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 282, 288, 292-3. Laski, 'The Roosevelt Experiment', Atlantic Monthly, CLIII (1934), pp. 143-53, pp. 143-4. Laski, 'Choosing the Planners', in Plan for Britain: A Collection of Essays prepared for the Fabian Society (London, 1943), p. 114. For Laski's thoughts on world government see Grammar, pp. 588 f.
    • (1929) Economica , vol.27 , pp. 267-295
    • Laski1
  • 262
    • 0010092936 scopus 로고
    • The Roosevelt experiment
    • 95 John Dewey, 'Social Absolutism', The New Republic (9 February 1921), pp. 315-18, pp. 316-17. Laski, 'The Value and Defects of the Marxist Philosophy', Current History (October 1928), pp. 23-9, p. 29. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 282, 288, 292-3. Laski, 'The Roosevelt Experiment', Atlantic Monthly, CLIII (1934), pp. 143-53, pp. 143-4. Laski, 'Choosing the Planners', in Plan for Britain: A Collection of Essays prepared for the Fabian Society (London, 1943), p. 114. For Laski's thoughts on world government see Grammar, pp. 588 f.
    • (1934) Atlantic Monthly , vol.153 , pp. 143-153
    • Laski1
  • 263
    • 0010155647 scopus 로고
    • Choosing the planners
    • London
    • 95 John Dewey, 'Social Absolutism', The New Republic (9 February 1921), pp. 315-18, pp. 316-17. Laski, 'The Value and Defects of the Marxist Philosophy', Current History (October 1928), pp. 23-9, p. 29. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 282, 288, 292-3. Laski, 'The Roosevelt Experiment', Atlantic Monthly, CLIII (1934), pp. 143-53, pp. 143-4. Laski, 'Choosing the Planners', in Plan for Britain: A Collection of Essays prepared for the Fabian Society (London, 1943), p. 114. For Laski's thoughts on world government see Grammar, pp. 588 f.
    • (1943) Plan for Britain: A Collection of Essays Prepared for the Fabian Society , pp. 114
    • Laski1
  • 264
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 95 John Dewey, 'Social Absolutism', The New Republic (9 February 1921), pp. 315-18, pp. 316-17. Laski, 'The Value and Defects of the Marxist Philosophy', Current History (October 1928), pp. 23-9, p. 29. Laski, 'Law and the State', Economica, 27 (1929), pp. 267-95, pp. 282, 288, 292-3. Laski, 'The Roosevelt Experiment', Atlantic Monthly, CLIII (1934), pp. 143-53, pp. 143-4. Laski, 'Choosing the Planners', in Plan for Britain: A Collection of Essays prepared for the Fabian Society (London, 1943), p. 114. For Laski's thoughts on world government see Grammar, pp. 588 f.
    • Grammar
  • 265
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 96 Grammar, p. 250. For further comments on anarchy see ibid., pp. 39, 289. 'Every government is thus built upon a contingent moral obligation. Its actions are right to the degree that they maintain rights.' Ibid., p. 57. For his comments on how the state is judged by members see ibid., p. 37. For similar remarks see Authority, p. 35; and Studies, pp. 18 f.
    • Grammar , pp. 250
  • 266
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 96 Grammar, p. 250. For further comments on anarchy see ibid., pp. 39, 289. 'Every government is thus built upon a contingent moral obligation. Its actions are right to the degree that they maintain rights.' Ibid., p. 57. For his comments on how the state is judged by members see ibid., p. 37. For similar remarks see Authority, p. 35; and Studies, pp. 18 f.
    • Grammar , pp. 39
  • 267
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 96 Grammar, p. 250. For further comments on anarchy see ibid., pp. 39, 289. 'Every government is thus built upon a contingent moral obligation. Its actions are right to the degree that they maintain rights.' Ibid., p. 57. For his comments on how the state is judged by members see ibid., p. 37. For similar remarks see Authority, p. 35; and Studies, pp. 18 f.
    • Grammar , pp. 57
  • 268
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 96 Grammar, p. 250. For further comments on anarchy see ibid., pp. 39, 289. 'Every government is thus built upon a contingent moral obligation. Its actions are right to the degree that they maintain rights.' Ibid., p. 57. For his comments on how the state is judged by members see ibid., p. 37. For similar remarks see Authority, p. 35; and Studies, pp. 18 f.
    • Grammar , pp. 37
  • 269
    • 79958999318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 96 Grammar, p. 250. For further comments on anarchy see ibid., pp. 39, 289. 'Every government is thus built upon a contingent moral obligation. Its actions are right to the degree that they maintain rights.' Ibid., p. 57. For his comments on how the state is judged by members see ibid., p. 37. For similar remarks see Authority, p. 35; and Studies, pp. 18 f.
    • Authority , pp. 35
  • 270
    • 4243455325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 96 Grammar, p. 250. For further comments on anarchy see ibid., pp. 39, 289. 'Every government is thus built upon a contingent moral obligation. Its actions are right to the degree that they maintain rights.' Ibid., p. 57. For his comments on how the state is judged by members see ibid., p. 37. For similar remarks see Authority, p. 35; and Studies, pp. 18 f.
    • Studies
  • 271
    • 0010097964 scopus 로고
    • Laski wrote that he always had a 'sneaking sympathy for James's definition of good as the satisfaction of demand' 7 February
    • 97 Letters, II, p. 1025. Laski wrote that he always had a 'sneaking sympathy for James's definition of good as the satisfaction of demand' (7 February 1927). James wrote that the 'essence of good is simply to satisfy demand', James, The Will to Believe, p. 201.
    • (1927) Letters , vol.2 , pp. 1025
  • 272
    • 0004210683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 97 Letters, II, p. 1025. Laski wrote that he always had a 'sneaking sympathy for James's definition of good as the satisfaction of demand' (7 February 1927). James wrote that the 'essence of good is simply to satisfy demand', James, The Will to Believe, p. 201.
    • The Will to Believe , pp. 201
    • James1
  • 273
    • 0004210683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • where he wrote: 'Thus, then, we see that mere instinctive curiosity, pugnacity, and honor may make life on a purely naturalistic basis seem worth living from day to day to men who have cast away all metaphysics in order to get rid of hypochondria, but who are resolved to owe nothing as yet to religion and its more positive gifts. A poor half-way stage, some of you may be inclined to say; but at least you must grant it to be an honest stage; and no man should dare to speak meanly of these instincts which are our nature's best equipment, and to which religion herself must in the last resort address her own peculiar appeals
    • 98 cf. James, The Will to Believe, p. 51, where he wrote: 'Thus, then, we see that mere instinctive curiosity, pugnacity, and honor may make life on a purely naturalistic basis seem worth living from day to day to men who have cast away all metaphysics in order to get rid of hypochondria, but who are resolved to owe nothing as yet to religion and its more positive gifts. A poor half-way stage, some of you may be inclined to say; but at least you must grant it to be an honest stage; and no man should dare to speak meanly of these instincts which are our nature's best equipment, and to which religion herself must in the last resort address her own peculiar appeals.' See also ibid., p. 47: 'Need and struggle are what excite and inspire us'.
    • The Will to Believe , pp. 51
    • James1
  • 274
    • 84865585509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Need and struggle are what excite and inspire us
    • 98 cf. James, The Will to Believe, p. 51, where he wrote: 'Thus, then, we see that mere instinctive curiosity, pugnacity, and honor may make life on a purely naturalistic basis seem worth living from day to day to men who have cast away all metaphysics in order to get rid of hypochondria, but who are resolved to owe nothing as yet to religion and its more positive gifts. A poor half-way stage, some of you may be inclined to say; but at least you must grant it to be an honest stage; and no man should dare to speak meanly of these instincts which are our nature's best equipment, and to which religion herself must in the last resort address her own peculiar appeals.' See also ibid., p. 47: 'Need and struggle are what excite and inspire us'.
    • The Will to Believe , pp. 47
  • 275
    • 0004346760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 99 'the veto . . . which the strict positivist pronounces upon our faith - sound to us like mere chatterings of the teeth', James, Will to Believe, p. 62. Cf. James, Pragmatism, p. 268, where he rejects the view that pragmatism implies materialism, agnosticism and naturalism.
    • Will to Believe , pp. 62
    • James1
  • 276
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 99 'the veto . . . which the strict positivist pronounces upon our faith - sound to us like mere chatterings of the teeth', James, Will to Believe, p. 62. Cf. James, Pragmatism, p. 268, where he rejects the view that pragmatism implies materialism, agnosticism and naturalism.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 268
    • James1
  • 277
    • 0004351457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 100 On the scientific and romantic sides of pragmatism see Perry, Thought and Character, pp. 581-2; and Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, p. 7.
    • Thought and Character , pp. 581-582
    • Perry1
  • 278
    • 0004335604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 100 On the scientific and romantic sides of pragmatism see Perry, Thought and Character, pp. 581-2; and Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, p. 7.
    • Pragmatic Revolt , pp. 7
    • Elliott1
  • 279
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 101 Grammar, pp. 22-3.
    • Grammar , pp. 22-23
  • 280
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 102 Ibid., p. 260. See also ibid., p. 141, where Laski wrote of the 'ultimate isolation of the self'. For similar remarks on 'ultimately unassimilable' character of the self see ibid., pp. 29-31, 247, 261. Many of these ideas are repeated in Laski's Liberty in the Modern State (Harmondsworth, 1930). Laski wrote therein (pp. 58-9) that the real self is the 'self that is isolated from his fellows'. It is 'all that I am and do. It is the total impression produced by the bewildering variety of my acts, good and bad and indifferent.'
    • Grammar , pp. 260
  • 281
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • where Laski wrote of the 'ultimate isolation of the self'
    • 102 Ibid., p. 260. See also ibid., p. 141, where Laski wrote of the 'ultimate isolation of the self'. For similar remarks on 'ultimately unassimilable' character of the self see ibid., pp. 29-31, 247, 261. Many of these ideas are repeated in Laski's Liberty in the Modern State (Harmondsworth, 1930). Laski wrote therein (pp. 58-9) that the real self is the 'self that is isolated from his fellows'. It is 'all that I am and do. It is the total impression produced by the bewildering variety of my acts, good and bad and indifferent.'
    • Grammar , pp. 141
  • 282
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 102 Ibid., p. 260. See also ibid., p. 141, where Laski wrote of the 'ultimate isolation of the self'. For similar remarks on 'ultimately unassimilable' character of the self see ibid., pp. 29-31, 247, 261. Many of these ideas are repeated in Laski's Liberty in the Modern State (Harmondsworth, 1930). Laski wrote therein (pp. 58-9) that the real self is the 'self that is isolated from his fellows'. It is 'all that I am and do. It is the total impression produced by the bewildering variety of my acts, good and bad and indifferent.'
    • Grammar , pp. 29-31
  • 283
    • 0010131073 scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth, Laski wrote therein that the real self is the 'self that is isolated from his fellows'. It is 'all that I am and do. It is the total impression produced by the bewildering variety of my acts, good and bad and indifferent.'
    • 102 Ibid., p. 260. See also ibid., p. 141, where Laski wrote of the 'ultimate isolation of the self'. For similar remarks on 'ultimately unassimilable' character of the self see ibid., pp. 29-31, 247, 261. Many of these ideas are repeated in Laski's Liberty in the Modern State (Harmondsworth, 1930). Laski wrote therein (pp. 58-9) that the real self is the 'self that is isolated from his fellows'. It is 'all that I am and do. It is the total impression produced by the bewildering variety of my acts, good and bad and indifferent.'
    • (1930) Liberty in the Modern State , pp. 58-59
  • 284
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Each individual . . . is entitled to expect from the performance of the State an environment in which, at least potentially, he can hope to realise the best of himself
    • 103 Grammar, pp. 142, 273, 289. Cf. p. 57: 'Each individual . . . is entitled to expect from the performance of the State an environment in which, at least potentially, he can hope to realise the best of himself.' Cf. Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', p. 190.
    • Grammar , pp. 142
  • 285
    • 0004352329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 103 Grammar, pp. 142, 273, 289. Cf. p. 57: 'Each individual . . . is entitled to expect from the performance of the State an environment in which, at least potentially, he can hope to realise the best of himself.' Cf. Laski, 'A Note on M. Duguit', p. 190.
    • A Note on M. Duguit , pp. 190
    • Laski1
  • 286
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 104 On the importance of freedom of speech see Grammar, pp. 118, 272-3, 283. On the notion that rights grow out of experience see ibid., pp. 91-2.
    • Grammar , pp. 118
  • 287
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 104 On the importance of freedom of speech see Grammar, pp. 118, 272-3, 283. On the notion that rights grow out of experience see ibid., pp. 91-2.
    • Grammar , pp. 91-92
  • 288
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 105 Grammar, pp. 260-1.
    • Grammar , pp. 260-261
  • 289
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 106 See Laski's comment that: 'The will of the State, in short, is the will which is adopted out of the conflict of myriad wills which contend with each other for the mastery of social forces.' Grammar, p. 35. See also ibid., p. 279: 'the social order means not one only, but the whole of the myriad forces in our midst which are striving to fulfil their wants'.
    • Grammar , pp. 35
  • 290
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • the social order means not one only, but the whole of the myriad forces in our midst which are striving to fulfil their wants
    • 106 See Laski's comment that: 'The will of the State, in short, is the will which is adopted out of the conflict of myriad wills which contend with each other for the mastery of social forces.' Grammar, p. 35. See also ibid., p. 279: 'the social order means not one only, but the whole of the myriad forces in our midst which are striving to fulfil their wants'.
    • Grammar , pp. 279
  • 291
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 107 See James, Pragmatism, p. 218. James wrote in Pragmatism, p. 222: '"The true", to put it briefly, is only the expedient in the way of our thinking, just as "the right" is only the expedient in the way of our behaving.' See also Essays, p. 109.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 218
    • James1
  • 292
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "The true", to put it briefly, is only the expedient in the way of our thinking, just as "the right" is only the expedient in the way of our behaving
    • 107 See James, Pragmatism, p. 218. James wrote in Pragmatism, p. 222: '"The true", to put it briefly, is only the expedient in the way of our thinking, just as "the right" is only the expedient in the way of our behaving.' See also Essays, p. 109.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 222
    • James1
  • 293
    • 0010089318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 107 See James, Pragmatism, p. 218. James wrote in Pragmatism, p. 222: '"The true", to put it briefly, is only the expedient in the way of our thinking, just as "the right" is only the expedient in the way of our behaving.' See also Essays, p. 109.
    • Essays , pp. 109
  • 295
  • 296
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 110 Grammar, p. 263. Cf. Studies, p. 18: 'What I mean by "right" is something the pragmatist will understand. It is something the individual ought to concede because experience has proved it to be good.'
    • Grammar , pp. 263
  • 297
    • 0010091102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What I mean by "right" is something the pragmatist will understand. It is something the individual ought to concede because experience has proved it to be good
    • 110 Grammar, p. 263. Cf. Studies, p. 18: 'What I mean by "right" is something the pragmatist will understand. It is something the individual ought to concede because experience has proved it to be good.'
    • Studies , pp. 18
  • 298
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 111 Grammar, pp. 278, 288.
    • Grammar , pp. 278
  • 299
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 112 Ibid., pp. 33, 142.
    • Grammar , pp. 33
  • 300
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 113 Ibid., pp. 23-4. Cf. ibid., p. 100: 'Men must learn to subordinate their self-interest to the common welfare.'
    • Grammar , pp. 23-24
  • 301
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Men must learn to subordinate their self-interest to the common welfare
    • 113 Ibid., pp. 23-4. Cf. ibid., p. 100: 'Men must learn to subordinate their self-interest to the common welfare.'
    • Grammar , pp. 100
  • 302
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 114 Ibid., p. 39. Cf. ibid., p. 130: 'No man . . . has the right to own property beyond that extent which enables the decent satisfaction of impulse.'
    • Grammar , pp. 39
  • 303
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • No man . . . has the right to own property beyond that extent which enables the decent satisfaction of impulse
    • 114 Ibid., p. 39. Cf. ibid., p. 130: 'No man . . . has the right to own property beyond that extent which enables the decent satisfaction of impulse.'
    • Grammar , pp. 130
  • 304
    • 0010143467 scopus 로고
    • Authority and social change
    • Harvard
    • 115 See for instance Dewey, 'Authority and Social Change', Authority and the Individual (Harvard, 1937), pp. 171-90. Cf. Mannheim, Man and Society in an Age of Reconstruction (London, 1940), pp. 263-4.
    • (1937) Authority and the Individual , pp. 171-190
    • Dewey1
  • 305
    • 0004123441 scopus 로고
    • London
    • 115 See for instance Dewey, 'Authority and Social Change', Authority and the Individual (Harvard, 1937), pp. 171-90. Cf. Mannheim, Man and Society in an Age of Reconstruction (London, 1940), pp. 263-4.
    • (1940) Man and Society in an Age of Reconstruction , pp. 263-264
    • Mannheim1
  • 306
    • 0010196224 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 116 Laski, 'Choosing the Planners', p. 114. See also Laski, Will Planning Restrict Freedom? (Aberdeen, 1944). Laski, 'The Roosevelt Experiment', pp. 143-5, 153. Cf. Charles W. Morris, Pragmatism and the Crisis of Democracy, Public Policy Pamphlet No. 12 (Chicago, 1934), pp. 8, 12, 19-21.
    • Choosing the Planners , pp. 114
    • Laski1
  • 307
    • 0004335961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aberdeen
    • 116 Laski, 'Choosing the Planners', p. 114. See also Laski, Will Planning Restrict Freedom? (Aberdeen, 1944). Laski, 'The Roosevelt Experiment', pp. 143-5, 153. Cf. Charles W. Morris, Pragmatism and the Crisis of Democracy, Public Policy Pamphlet No. 12 (Chicago, 1934), pp. 8, 12, 19-21.
    • (1944) Will Planning Restrict Freedom?
    • Laski1
  • 308
    • 0010203467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 116 Laski, 'Choosing the Planners', p. 114. See also Laski, Will Planning Restrict Freedom? (Aberdeen, 1944). Laski, 'The Roosevelt Experiment', pp. 143-5, 153. Cf. Charles W. Morris, Pragmatism and the Crisis of Democracy, Public Policy Pamphlet No. 12 (Chicago, 1934), pp. 8, 12, 19-21.
    • The Roosevelt Experiment , pp. 143-145
    • Laski1
  • 309
    • 0010131143 scopus 로고
    • Public Policy Pamphlet No. 12 Chicago
    • 116 Laski, 'Choosing the Planners', p. 114. See also Laski, Will Planning Restrict Freedom? (Aberdeen, 1944). Laski, 'The Roosevelt Experiment', pp. 143-5, 153. Cf. Charles W. Morris, Pragmatism and the Crisis of Democracy, Public Policy Pamphlet No. 12 (Chicago, 1934), pp. 8, 12, 19-21.
    • (1934) Pragmatism and the Crisis of Democracy , pp. 8
    • Morris, C.W.1
  • 310
    • 0010092940 scopus 로고
    • 22 December
    • 117 See Letters, I, pp. 691 (22 December 1924), 697 (6 January 1925), for comments by Laski on his definition of the good in terms of social utility. Cf. Grammar, p. 62.
    • (1924) Letters , vol.1 , pp. 691
  • 311
    • 0010100375 scopus 로고
    • 6 January, for comments by Laski on his definition of the good in terms of social utility
    • 117 See Letters, I, pp. 691 (22 December 1924), 697 (6 January 1925), for comments by Laski on his definition of the good in terms of social utility. Cf. Grammar, p. 62.
    • (1925) Letters , pp. 697
  • 312
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 117 See Letters, I, pp. 691 (22 December 1924), 697 (6 January 1925), for comments by Laski on his definition of the good in terms of social utility. Cf. Grammar, p. 62.
    • Grammar , pp. 62
  • 313
    • 0004335604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 118 Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 149-50. Note James's comment (Essays, p. 159) that some people assumed that: '. . . whatever the socialist postulates as desirable is wanted without limit of qualification, - for socialist read pluralist and the parallel holds good, - it is to imagine that whatever proposal is made by him is to be carried out by uncontrolled monomaniacs, and so to make a picture of the socialist dream which can be presented to the simpleminded person in doubt - "This is socialism" - or pluralism, as the case may be. "Surely! - surely! you don't want this!".'
    • Pragmatic Revolt , pp. 149-150
    • Elliott1
  • 314
    • 0010213106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • that some people assumed that: '. . . whatever the socialist postulates as desirable is wanted without limit of qualification, - for socialist read pluralist and the parallel holds good, - it is to imagine that whatever proposal is made by him is to be carried out by uncontrolled monomaniacs, and so to make a picture of the socialist dream which can be presented to the simpleminded person in doubt - "This is socialism" - or pluralism, as the case may be. "Surely! - surely! you don't want this!".'
    • 118 Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 149-50. Note James's comment (Essays, p. 159) that some people assumed that: '. . . whatever the socialist postulates as desirable is wanted without limit of qualification, - for socialist read pluralist and the parallel holds good, - it is to imagine that whatever proposal is made by him is to be carried out by uncontrolled monomaniacs, and so to make a picture of the socialist dream which can be presented to the simpleminded person in doubt - "This is socialism" - or pluralism, as the case may be. "Surely! - surely! you don't want this!".'
    • Essays , pp. 159
  • 315
    • 0004348006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 119 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 193. Hsiao wrote that pragmatism declares the 'independence of the pragmatic-humanist spirit against all reality, claiming for men the natural right to take the government of the universe into their own hands'. In this revolutionary analogy Hsiao cast James as the 'prophetic Rousseau' and Laski as the 'irresistible Danton'. For Laski's comments on Hsiao's work see Letters, II, p. 982 (24 September 1927); and Laski, 'Political Pluralism', The New Republic (28 March 1928), pp. 197-8.
    • Political Pluralism , pp. 193
    • Hsiao1
  • 316
    • 0010155648 scopus 로고
    • 24 September
    • 119 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 193. Hsiao wrote that pragmatism declares the 'independence of the pragmatic-humanist spirit against all reality, claiming for men the natural right to take the government of the universe into their own hands'. In this revolutionary analogy Hsiao cast James as the 'prophetic Rousseau' and Laski as the 'irresistible Danton'. For Laski's comments on Hsiao's work see Letters, II, p. 982 (24 September 1927); and Laski, 'Political Pluralism', The New Republic (28 March 1928), pp. 197-8.
    • (1927) Letters , vol.2 , pp. 982
  • 317
    • 0010151467 scopus 로고
    • Political pluralism
    • 28 March
    • 119 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 193. Hsiao wrote that pragmatism declares the 'independence of the pragmatic-humanist spirit against all reality, claiming for men the natural right to take the government of the universe into their own hands'. In this revolutionary analogy Hsiao cast James as the 'prophetic Rousseau' and Laski as the 'irresistible Danton'. For Laski's comments on Hsiao's work see Letters, II, p. 982 (24 September 1927); and Laski, 'Political Pluralism', The New Republic (28 March 1928), pp. 197-8.
    • (1928) The New Republic , pp. 197-198
    • Laski1
  • 318
    • 0004348006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 120 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 126, 206-7 ; and Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', p. 252. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 10-11, 55-6.
    • Political Pluralism , pp. 126
    • Hsiao1
  • 319
    • 0004332742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 120 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 126, 206-7 ; and Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', p. 252. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 10-11, 55-6.
    • Pragmatic Politics , pp. 252
    • Elliott1
  • 320
    • 0004335604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 120 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 126, 206-7 ; and Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', p. 252. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 10-11, 55-6.
    • Pragmatic Revolt , pp. 10-11
    • Elliott1
  • 321
    • 0004348006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 121 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 166-8, 192-3. Hsiao wrote that pragmatic, pluralist politics would degenerate into 'anarchism and irresponsibility', ibid., p. 204. On this point see also Elliott, 'Pragmatic Polities', p. 257. See also Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 83, 90, 103-4, 119. Elliott wrote that Laski's doctrine of contingent anarchy would beget Fascism (Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 149-50).
    • Political Pluralism , pp. 166-168
    • Hsiao1
  • 322
    • 0010203468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 121 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 166-8, 192-3. Hsiao wrote that pragmatic, pluralist politics would degenerate into 'anarchism and irresponsibility', ibid., p. 204. On this point see also Elliott, 'Pragmatic Polities', p. 257. See also Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 83, 90, 103-4, 119. Elliott wrote that Laski's doctrine of contingent anarchy would beget Fascism (Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 149-50).
    • Political Pluralism , pp. 204
  • 323
    • 0010140399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 121 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 166-8, 192-3. Hsiao wrote that pragmatic, pluralist politics would degenerate into 'anarchism and irresponsibility', ibid., p. 204. On this point see also Elliott, 'Pragmatic Polities', p. 257. See also Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 83, 90, 103-4, 119. Elliott wrote that Laski's doctrine of contingent anarchy would beget Fascism (Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 149-50).
    • Pragmatic Polities , pp. 257
    • Elliott1
  • 324
    • 0004335604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 121 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 166-8, 192-3. Hsiao wrote that pragmatic, pluralist politics would degenerate into 'anarchism and irresponsibility', ibid., p. 204. On this point see also Elliott, 'Pragmatic Polities', p. 257. See also Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 83, 90, 103-4, 119. Elliott wrote that Laski's doctrine of contingent anarchy would beget Fascism (Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 149-50).
    • Pragmatic Revolt , pp. 83
    • Elliott1
  • 325
    • 0010101936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 121 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 166-8, 192-3. Hsiao wrote that pragmatic, pluralist politics would degenerate into 'anarchism and irresponsibility', ibid., p. 204. On this point see also Elliott, 'Pragmatic Polities', p. 257. See also Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 83, 90, 103-4, 119. Elliott wrote that Laski's doctrine of contingent anarchy would beget Fascism (Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 149-50).
    • Pragmatic Revolt , pp. 149-150
  • 326
    • 0004332742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 122 On the 'pragmatist' aspects of Sorel's and Mussolini's thought see Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 257, 274-5; and Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 111-13, 116, 120, 316, 323, 324. Sorel's interest in James, which seems to have been both intellectual and political, is reflected in the 1920 edition of his Illusions of Progress, trans. John and Charlotte Stanley (Berkeley, 1969). See also Sorel's De l'Utilité du Pragmatisme (Librairie des Sciences Sociales et Politiques, 2nd edn., 1928). Mussolini's alleged interest in James came to public attention in an interview with Dr André Révesz in The Sunday Times (11 April 1926), p. 15. Mussolini cited James, along with Sorel and Nietzsche, as a formative influence. 'The pragmatism of William James was of great use to me in my political career. James taught me that an action should be judged rather by its results than by its doctrinary basis. I learnt of James that faith in action, that ardent will to life and fight, to which Fascism owes a great part of its success.' Cf. William Kinbourne Stewart, 'The Mentors of Mussolini', American Political Science Review, XXXII (1928), pp. 843-69. For a dispassionate analysis of the connections between James's thought and the ideas of Sorel and Mussolini see Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 575-9. For later comments on this topic see V.J. McGill, 'Pragmatism Reconsidered: An Aspect of John Dewey's Philosophy', Science and Society, III (1939), pp. 289-322, p. 314. Thomas P. Neill, 'Democracy's Intellectual "Fifth Column"', Catholic World, CLV (1942), pp. 151-5, p. 151. Bertrand Russell, 'The Revolt Against Reason', in Political Quarterly in the 1930s, ed. W.A. Robson (London, 1971), pp. 155-6. Cf. Horace M. Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', Antioch Review, XXX (1959), pp. 299-314, p. 307. Kallen disparaged those who attempted to associate pragmatism with fascism or nazism.
    • Pragmatic Politics , pp. 257
    • Elliott1
  • 327
    • 0004335604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 122 On the 'pragmatist' aspects of Sorel's and Mussolini's thought see Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 257, 274-5; and Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 111-13, 116, 120, 316, 323, 324. Sorel's interest in James, which seems to have been both intellectual and political, is reflected in the 1920 edition of his Illusions of Progress, trans. John and Charlotte Stanley (Berkeley, 1969). See also Sorel's De l'Utilité du Pragmatisme (Librairie des Sciences Sociales et Politiques, 2nd edn., 1928). Mussolini's alleged interest in James came to public attention in an interview with Dr André Révesz in The Sunday Times (11 April 1926), p. 15. Mussolini cited James, along with Sorel and Nietzsche, as a formative influence. 'The pragmatism of William James was of great use to me in my political career. James taught me that an action should be judged rather by its results than by its doctrinary basis. I learnt of James that faith in action, that ardent will to life and fight, to which Fascism owes a great part of its success.' Cf. William Kinbourne Stewart, 'The Mentors of Mussolini', American Political Science Review, XXXII (1928), pp. 843-69. For a dispassionate analysis of the connections between James's thought and the ideas of Sorel and Mussolini see Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 575-9. For later comments on this topic see V.J. McGill, 'Pragmatism Reconsidered: An Aspect of John Dewey's Philosophy', Science and Society, III (1939), pp. 289-322, p. 314. Thomas P. Neill, 'Democracy's Intellectual "Fifth Column"', Catholic World, CLV (1942), pp. 151-5, p. 151. Bertrand Russell, 'The Revolt Against Reason', in Political Quarterly in the 1930s, ed. W.A. Robson (London, 1971), pp. 155-6. Cf. Horace M. Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', Antioch Review, XXX (1959), pp. 299-314, p. 307. Kallen disparaged those who attempted to associate pragmatism with fascism or nazism.
    • Pragmatic Revolt , pp. 111-113
    • Elliott1
  • 328
    • 63549101242 scopus 로고
    • trans. John and Charlotte Stanley Berkeley
    • 122 On the 'pragmatist' aspects of Sorel's and Mussolini's thought see Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 257, 274-5; and Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 111-13, 116, 120, 316, 323, 324. Sorel's interest in James, which seems to have been both intellectual and political, is reflected in the 1920 edition of his Illusions of Progress, trans. John and Charlotte Stanley (Berkeley, 1969). See also Sorel's De l'Utilité du Pragmatisme (Librairie des Sciences Sociales et Politiques, 2nd edn., 1928). Mussolini's alleged interest in James came to public attention in an interview with Dr André Révesz in The Sunday Times (11 April 1926), p. 15. Mussolini cited James, along with Sorel and Nietzsche, as a formative influence. 'The pragmatism of William James was of great use to me in my political career. James taught me that an action should be judged rather by its results than by its doctrinary basis. I learnt of James that faith in action, that ardent will to life and fight, to which Fascism owes a great part of its success.' Cf. William Kinbourne Stewart, 'The Mentors of Mussolini', American Political Science Review, XXXII (1928), pp. 843-69. For a dispassionate analysis of the connections between James's thought and the ideas of Sorel and Mussolini see Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 575-9. For later comments on this topic see V.J. McGill, 'Pragmatism Reconsidered: An Aspect of John Dewey's Philosophy', Science and Society, III (1939), pp. 289-322, p. 314. Thomas P. Neill, 'Democracy's Intellectual "Fifth Column"', Catholic World, CLV (1942), pp. 151-5, p. 151. Bertrand Russell, 'The Revolt Against Reason', in Political Quarterly in the 1930s, ed. W.A. Robson (London, 1971), pp. 155-6. Cf. Horace M. Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', Antioch Review, XXX (1959), pp. 299-314, p. 307. Kallen disparaged those who attempted to associate pragmatism with fascism or nazism.
    • (1969) Illusions of Progress
  • 329
    • 0010203469 scopus 로고
    • Librairie des Sciences Sociales et Politiques, 2nd edn.
    • 122 On the 'pragmatist' aspects of Sorel's and Mussolini's thought see Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 257, 274-5; and Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 111-13, 116, 120, 316, 323, 324. Sorel's interest in James, which seems to have been both intellectual and political, is reflected in the 1920 edition of his Illusions of Progress, trans. John and Charlotte Stanley (Berkeley, 1969). See also Sorel's De l'Utilité du Pragmatisme (Librairie des Sciences Sociales et Politiques, 2nd edn., 1928). Mussolini's alleged interest in James came to public attention in an interview with Dr André Révesz in The Sunday Times (11 April 1926), p. 15. Mussolini cited James, along with Sorel and Nietzsche, as a formative influence. 'The pragmatism of William James was of great use to me in my political career. James taught me that an action should be judged rather by its results than by its doctrinary basis. I learnt of James that faith in action, that ardent will to life and fight, to which Fascism owes a great part of its success.' Cf. William Kinbourne Stewart, 'The Mentors of Mussolini', American Political Science Review, XXXII (1928), pp. 843-69. For a dispassionate analysis of the connections between James's thought and the ideas of Sorel and Mussolini see Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 575-9. For later comments on this topic see V.J. McGill, 'Pragmatism Reconsidered: An Aspect of John Dewey's Philosophy', Science and Society, III (1939), pp. 289-322, p. 314. Thomas P. Neill, 'Democracy's Intellectual "Fifth Column"', Catholic World, CLV (1942), pp. 151-5, p. 151. Bertrand Russell, 'The Revolt Against Reason', in Political Quarterly in the 1930s, ed. W.A. Robson (London, 1971), pp. 155-6. Cf. Horace M. Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', Antioch Review, XXX (1959), pp. 299-314, p. 307. Kallen disparaged those who attempted to associate pragmatism with fascism or nazism.
    • (1928) Sorel's de l'Utilité du Pragmatisme
  • 330
    • 0010101937 scopus 로고
    • 11 April
    • 122 On the 'pragmatist' aspects of Sorel's and Mussolini's thought see Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 257, 274-5; and Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 111-13, 116, 120, 316, 323, 324. Sorel's interest in James, which seems to have been both intellectual and political, is reflected in the 1920 edition of his Illusions of Progress, trans. John and Charlotte Stanley (Berkeley, 1969). See also Sorel's De l'Utilité du Pragmatisme (Librairie des Sciences Sociales et Politiques, 2nd edn., 1928). Mussolini's alleged interest in James came to public attention in an interview with Dr André Révesz in The Sunday Times (11 April 1926), p. 15. Mussolini cited James, along with Sorel and Nietzsche, as a formative influence. 'The pragmatism of William James was of great use to me in my political career. James taught me that an action should be judged rather by its results than by its doctrinary basis. I learnt of James that faith in action, that ardent will to life and fight, to which Fascism owes a great part of its success.' Cf. William Kinbourne Stewart, 'The Mentors of Mussolini', American Political Science Review, XXXII (1928), pp. 843-69. For a dispassionate analysis of the connections between James's thought and the ideas of Sorel and Mussolini see Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 575-9. For later comments on this topic see V.J. McGill, 'Pragmatism Reconsidered: An Aspect of John Dewey's Philosophy', Science and Society, III (1939), pp. 289-322, p. 314. Thomas P. Neill, 'Democracy's Intellectual "Fifth Column"', Catholic World, CLV (1942), pp. 151-5, p. 151. Bertrand Russell, 'The Revolt Against Reason', in Political Quarterly in the 1930s, ed. W.A. Robson (London, 1971), pp. 155-6. Cf. Horace M. Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', Antioch Review, XXX (1959), pp. 299-314, p. 307. Kallen disparaged those who attempted to associate pragmatism with fascism or nazism.
    • (1926) The Sunday Times , pp. 15
  • 331
    • 84928053433 scopus 로고
    • The mentors of Mussolini
    • 122 On the 'pragmatist' aspects of Sorel's and Mussolini's thought see Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 257, 274-5; and Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 111-13, 116, 120, 316, 323, 324. Sorel's interest in James, which seems to have been both intellectual and political, is reflected in the 1920 edition of his Illusions of Progress, trans. John and Charlotte Stanley (Berkeley, 1969). See also Sorel's De l'Utilité du Pragmatisme (Librairie des Sciences Sociales et Politiques, 2nd edn., 1928). Mussolini's alleged interest in James came to public attention in an interview with Dr André Révesz in The Sunday Times (11 April 1926), p. 15. Mussolini cited James, along with Sorel and Nietzsche, as a formative influence. 'The pragmatism of William James was of great use to me in my political career. James taught me that an action should be judged rather by its results than by its doctrinary basis. I learnt of James that faith in action, that ardent will to life and fight, to which Fascism owes a great part of its success.' Cf. William Kinbourne Stewart, 'The Mentors of Mussolini', American Political Science Review, XXXII (1928), pp. 843-69. For a dispassionate analysis of the connections between James's thought and the ideas of Sorel and Mussolini see Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 575-9. For later comments on this topic see V.J. McGill, 'Pragmatism Reconsidered: An Aspect of John Dewey's Philosophy', Science and Society, III (1939), pp. 289-322, p. 314. Thomas P. Neill, 'Democracy's Intellectual "Fifth Column"', Catholic World, CLV (1942), pp. 151-5, p. 151. Bertrand Russell, 'The Revolt Against Reason', in Political Quarterly in the 1930s, ed. W.A. Robson (London, 1971), pp. 155-6. Cf. Horace M. Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', Antioch Review, XXX (1959), pp. 299-314, p. 307. Kallen disparaged those who attempted to associate pragmatism with fascism or nazism.
    • (1928) American Political Science Review , vol.32 , pp. 843-869
    • Stewart, W.K.1
  • 332
    • 0010213107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 122 On the 'pragmatist' aspects of Sorel's and Mussolini's thought see Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 257, 274-5; and Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 111-13, 116, 120, 316, 323, 324. Sorel's interest in James, which seems to have been both intellectual and political, is reflected in the 1920 edition of his Illusions of Progress, trans. John and Charlotte Stanley (Berkeley, 1969). See also Sorel's De l'Utilité du Pragmatisme (Librairie des Sciences Sociales et Politiques, 2nd edn., 1928). Mussolini's alleged interest in James came to public attention in an interview with Dr André Révesz in The Sunday Times (11 April 1926), p. 15. Mussolini cited James, along with Sorel and Nietzsche, as a formative influence. 'The pragmatism of William James was of great use to me in my political career. James taught me that an action should be judged rather by its results than by its doctrinary basis. I learnt of James that faith in action, that ardent will to life and fight, to which Fascism owes a great part of its success.' Cf. William Kinbourne Stewart, 'The Mentors of Mussolini', American Political Science Review, XXXII (1928), pp. 843-69. For a dispassionate analysis of the connections between James's thought and the ideas of Sorel and Mussolini see Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 575-9. For later comments on this topic see V.J. McGill, 'Pragmatism Reconsidered: An Aspect of John Dewey's Philosophy', Science and Society, III (1939), pp. 289-322, p. 314. Thomas P. Neill, 'Democracy's Intellectual "Fifth Column"', Catholic World, CLV (1942), pp. 151-5, p. 151. Bertrand Russell, 'The Revolt Against Reason', in Political Quarterly in the 1930s, ed. W.A. Robson (London, 1971), pp. 155-6. Cf. Horace M. Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', Antioch Review, XXX (1959), pp. 299-314, p. 307. Kallen disparaged those who attempted to associate pragmatism with fascism or nazism.
    • Thought and Character , vol.2 , pp. 575-579
    • Perry1
  • 333
    • 0010100376 scopus 로고
    • Pragmatism reconsidered: An aspect of John Dewey's philosophy
    • 122 On the 'pragmatist' aspects of Sorel's and Mussolini's thought see Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 257, 274-5; and Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 111-13, 116, 120, 316, 323, 324. Sorel's interest in James, which seems to have been both intellectual and political, is reflected in the 1920 edition of his Illusions of Progress, trans. John and Charlotte Stanley (Berkeley, 1969). See also Sorel's De l'Utilité du Pragmatisme (Librairie des Sciences Sociales et Politiques, 2nd edn., 1928). Mussolini's alleged interest in James came to public attention in an interview with Dr André Révesz in The Sunday Times (11 April 1926), p. 15. Mussolini cited James, along with Sorel and Nietzsche, as a formative influence. 'The pragmatism of William James was of great use to me in my political career. James taught me that an action should be judged rather by its results than by its doctrinary basis. I learnt of James that faith in action, that ardent will to life and fight, to which Fascism owes a great part of its success.' Cf. William Kinbourne Stewart, 'The Mentors of Mussolini', American Political Science Review, XXXII (1928), pp. 843-69. For a dispassionate analysis of the connections between James's thought and the ideas of Sorel and Mussolini see Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 575-9. For later comments on this topic see V.J. McGill, 'Pragmatism Reconsidered: An Aspect of John Dewey's Philosophy', Science and Society, III (1939), pp. 289-322, p. 314. Thomas P. Neill, 'Democracy's Intellectual "Fifth Column"', Catholic World, CLV (1942), pp. 151-5, p. 151. Bertrand Russell, 'The Revolt Against Reason', in Political Quarterly in the 1930s, ed. W.A. Robson (London, 1971), pp. 155-6. Cf. Horace M. Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', Antioch Review, XXX (1959), pp. 299-314, p. 307. Kallen disparaged those who attempted to associate pragmatism with fascism or nazism.
    • (1939) Science and Society , vol.3 , pp. 289-322
    • McGill, V.J.1
  • 334
    • 0010151468 scopus 로고
    • Democracy's intellectual "fifth column"
    • 122 On the 'pragmatist' aspects of Sorel's and Mussolini's thought see Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 257, 274-5; and Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 111-13, 116, 120, 316, 323, 324. Sorel's interest in James, which seems to have been both intellectual and political, is reflected in the 1920 edition of his Illusions of Progress, trans. John and Charlotte Stanley (Berkeley, 1969). See also Sorel's De l'Utilité du Pragmatisme (Librairie des Sciences Sociales et Politiques, 2nd edn., 1928). Mussolini's alleged interest in James came to public attention in an interview with Dr André Révesz in The Sunday Times (11 April 1926), p. 15. Mussolini cited James, along with Sorel and Nietzsche, as a formative influence. 'The pragmatism of William James was of great use to me in my political career. James taught me that an action should be judged rather by its results than by its doctrinary basis. I learnt of James that faith in action, that ardent will to life and fight, to which Fascism owes a great part of its success.' Cf. William Kinbourne Stewart, 'The Mentors of Mussolini', American Political Science Review, XXXII (1928), pp. 843-69. For a dispassionate analysis of the connections between James's thought and the ideas of Sorel and Mussolini see Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 575-9. For later comments on this topic see V.J. McGill, 'Pragmatism Reconsidered: An Aspect of John Dewey's Philosophy', Science and Society, III (1939), pp. 289-322, p. 314. Thomas P. Neill, 'Democracy's Intellectual "Fifth Column"', Catholic World, CLV (1942), pp. 151-5, p. 151. Bertrand Russell, 'The Revolt Against Reason', in Political Quarterly in the 1930s, ed. W.A. Robson (London, 1971), pp. 155-6. Cf. Horace M. Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', Antioch Review, XXX (1959), pp. 299-314, p. 307. Kallen disparaged those who attempted to associate pragmatism with fascism or nazism.
    • (1942) Catholic World , vol.155 , pp. 151-155
    • Neill, T.P.1
  • 335
    • 0010196225 scopus 로고
    • The revolt against reason
    • ed. W.A. Robson London
    • 122 On the 'pragmatist' aspects of Sorel's and Mussolini's thought see Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 257, 274-5; and Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 111-13, 116, 120, 316, 323, 324. Sorel's interest in James, which seems to have been both intellectual and political, is reflected in the 1920 edition of his Illusions of Progress, trans. John and Charlotte Stanley (Berkeley, 1969). See also Sorel's De l'Utilité du Pragmatisme (Librairie des Sciences Sociales et Politiques, 2nd edn., 1928). Mussolini's alleged interest in James came to public attention in an interview with Dr André Révesz in The Sunday Times (11 April 1926), p. 15. Mussolini cited James, along with Sorel and Nietzsche, as a formative influence. 'The pragmatism of William James was of great use to me in my political career. James taught me that an action should be judged rather by its results than by its doctrinary basis. I learnt of James that faith in action, that ardent will to life and fight, to which Fascism owes a great part of its success.' Cf. William Kinbourne Stewart, 'The Mentors of Mussolini', American Political Science Review, XXXII (1928), pp. 843-69. For a dispassionate analysis of the connections between James's thought and the ideas of Sorel and Mussolini see Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 575-9. For later comments on this topic see V.J. McGill, 'Pragmatism Reconsidered: An Aspect of John Dewey's Philosophy', Science and Society, III (1939), pp. 289-322, p. 314. Thomas P. Neill, 'Democracy's Intellectual "Fifth Column"', Catholic World, CLV (1942), pp. 151-5, p. 151. Bertrand Russell, 'The Revolt Against Reason', in Political Quarterly in the 1930s, ed. W.A. Robson (London, 1971), pp. 155-6. Cf. Horace M. Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', Antioch Review, XXX (1959), pp. 299-314, p. 307. Kallen disparaged those who attempted to associate pragmatism with fascism or nazism.
    • (1971) Political Quarterly in the 1930s , pp. 155-156
    • Russell, B.1
  • 336
    • 0010131144 scopus 로고
    • Individuality, individualism and John Dewey
    • Kallen disparaged those who attempted to associate pragmatism with fascism or nazism
    • 122 On the 'pragmatist' aspects of Sorel's and Mussolini's thought see Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 257, 274-5; and Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 111-13, 116, 120, 316, 323, 324. Sorel's interest in James, which seems to have been both intellectual and political, is reflected in the 1920 edition of his Illusions of Progress, trans. John and Charlotte Stanley (Berkeley, 1969). See also Sorel's De l'Utilité du Pragmatisme (Librairie des Sciences Sociales et Politiques, 2nd edn., 1928). Mussolini's alleged interest in James came to public attention in an interview with Dr André Révesz in The Sunday Times (11 April 1926), p. 15. Mussolini cited James, along with Sorel and Nietzsche, as a formative influence. 'The pragmatism of William James was of great use to me in my political career. James taught me that an action should be judged rather by its results than by its doctrinary basis. I learnt of James that faith in action, that ardent will to life and fight, to which Fascism owes a great part of its success.' Cf. William Kinbourne Stewart, 'The Mentors of Mussolini', American Political Science Review, XXXII (1928), pp. 843-69. For a dispassionate analysis of the connections between James's thought and the ideas of Sorel and Mussolini see Perry, Thought and Character, II, pp. 575-9. For later comments on this topic see V.J. McGill, 'Pragmatism Reconsidered: An Aspect of John Dewey's Philosophy', Science and Society, III (1939), pp. 289-322, p. 314. Thomas P. Neill, 'Democracy's Intellectual "Fifth Column"', Catholic World, CLV (1942), pp. 151-5, p. 151. Bertrand Russell, 'The Revolt Against Reason', in Political Quarterly in the 1930s, ed. W.A. Robson (London, 1971), pp. 155-6. Cf. Horace M. Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', Antioch Review, XXX (1959), pp. 299-314, p. 307. Kallen disparaged those who attempted to associate pragmatism with fascism or nazism.
    • (1959) Antioch Review , vol.30 , pp. 299-314
    • Kallen, H.M.1
  • 337
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 123 Grammar, p. 272. For Laski's depiction of community members as consumers and for his functionalist and instrumentalist account of the state and rights see ibid., pp. 39, 69, 130; cf. ibid., p. 24. Laski described his theory as a 'special adaptation of the Benthamite theory to the special needs of the time'. Laski's use of expressions such as 'effective demand gave rise to economistic interpretations of his idea of the good. Laski, 'Law and the State', p. 294. See Foundations, pp. 244-5: 'Law apart, every community is a congeries of men and associations seeking the satisfaction of wants . . . [the state] . . . entrusted with power in order that it may satisfy, or organize the satisfaction of, the wants of men on the largest possible scale.' Cf. Laski, Liberty in the Modern State, p. 51: 'A compulsory training of the mind is still compulsion. It is a sacrifice of some liberty to a greater freedom when the compulsion ceases.' For criticisms of the collectivist aspects of the Grammar see Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism, pp. 189-202. See also Deane, Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski, pp. 333 ff. Cf. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 363-4; and Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 207. See also Alan Shaw, 'Liberty and Happiness', Australian Quarterly (1942), pp. 86-95, p. 88.
    • Grammar , pp. 272
  • 338
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 123 Grammar, p. 272. For Laski's depiction of community members as consumers and for his functionalist and instrumentalist account of the state and rights see ibid., pp. 39, 69, 130; cf. ibid., p. 24. Laski described his theory as a 'special adaptation of the Benthamite theory to the special needs of the time'. Laski's use of expressions such as 'effective demand gave rise to economistic interpretations of his idea of the good. Laski, 'Law and the State', p. 294. See Foundations, pp. 244-5: 'Law apart, every community is a congeries of men and associations seeking the satisfaction of wants . . . [the state] . . . entrusted with power in order that it may satisfy, or organize the satisfaction of, the wants of men on the largest possible scale.' Cf. Laski, Liberty in the Modern State, p. 51: 'A compulsory training of the mind is still compulsion. It is a sacrifice of some liberty to a greater freedom when the compulsion ceases.' For criticisms of the collectivist aspects of the Grammar see Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism, pp. 189-202. See also Deane, Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski, pp. 333 ff. Cf. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 363-4; and Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 207. See also Alan Shaw, 'Liberty and Happiness', Australian Quarterly (1942), pp. 86-95, p. 88.
    • Grammar , pp. 39
  • 339
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 123 Grammar, p. 272. For Laski's depiction of community members as consumers and for his functionalist and instrumentalist account of the state and rights see ibid., pp. 39, 69, 130; cf. ibid., p. 24. Laski described his theory as a 'special adaptation of the Benthamite theory to the special needs of the time'. Laski's use of expressions such as 'effective demand gave rise to economistic interpretations of his idea of the good. Laski, 'Law and the State', p. 294. See Foundations, pp. 244-5: 'Law apart, every community is a congeries of men and associations seeking the satisfaction of wants . . . [the state] . . . entrusted with power in order that it may satisfy, or organize the satisfaction of, the wants of men on the largest possible scale.' Cf. Laski, Liberty in the Modern State, p. 51: 'A compulsory training of the mind is still compulsion. It is a sacrifice of some liberty to a greater freedom when the compulsion ceases.' For criticisms of the collectivist aspects of the Grammar see Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism, pp. 189-202. See also Deane, Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski, pp. 333 ff. Cf. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 363-4; and Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 207. See also Alan Shaw, 'Liberty and Happiness', Australian Quarterly (1942), pp. 86-95, p. 88.
    • Grammar , pp. 24
  • 340
    • 0004352379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 123 Grammar, p. 272. For Laski's depiction of community members as consumers and for his functionalist and instrumentalist account of the state and rights see ibid., pp. 39, 69, 130; cf. ibid., p. 24. Laski described his theory as a 'special adaptation of the Benthamite theory to the special needs of the time'. Laski's use of expressions such as 'effective demand gave rise to economistic interpretations of his idea of the good. Laski, 'Law and the State', p. 294. See Foundations, pp. 244-5: 'Law apart, every community is a congeries of men and associations seeking the satisfaction of wants . . . [the state] . . . entrusted with power in order that it may satisfy, or organize the satisfaction of, the wants of men on the largest possible scale.' Cf. Laski, Liberty in the Modern State, p. 51: 'A compulsory training of the mind is still compulsion. It is a sacrifice of some liberty to a greater freedom when the compulsion ceases.' For criticisms of the collectivist aspects of the Grammar see Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism, pp. 189-202. See also Deane, Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski, pp. 333 ff. Cf. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 363-4; and Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 207. See also Alan Shaw, 'Liberty and Happiness', Australian Quarterly (1942), pp. 86-95, p. 88.
    • Law and the State , pp. 294
    • Laski1
  • 341
    • 0040454255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law apart, every community is a congeries of men and associations seeking the satisfaction of wants . . . [the state] . . . entrusted with power in order that it may satisfy, or organize the satisfaction of, the wants of men on the largest possible scale
    • 123 Grammar, p. 272. For Laski's depiction of community members as consumers and for his functionalist and instrumentalist account of the state and rights see ibid., pp. 39, 69, 130; cf. ibid., p. 24. Laski described his theory as a 'special adaptation of the Benthamite theory to the special needs of the time'. Laski's use of expressions such as 'effective demand gave rise to economistic interpretations of his idea of the good. Laski, 'Law and the State', p. 294. See Foundations, pp. 244-5: 'Law apart, every community is a congeries of men and associations seeking the satisfaction of wants . . . [the state] . . . entrusted with power in order that it may satisfy, or organize the satisfaction of, the wants of men on the largest possible scale.' Cf. Laski, Liberty in the Modern State, p. 51: 'A compulsory training of the mind is still compulsion. It is a sacrifice of some liberty to a greater freedom when the compulsion ceases.' For criticisms of the collectivist aspects of the Grammar see Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism, pp. 189-202. See also Deane, Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski, pp. 333 ff. Cf. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 363-4; and Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 207. See also Alan Shaw, 'Liberty and Happiness', Australian Quarterly (1942), pp. 86-95, p. 88.
    • Foundations , pp. 244-245
  • 342
    • 0010131074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A compulsory training of the mind is still compulsion. It is a sacrifice of some liberty to a greater freedom when the compulsion ceases
    • 123 Grammar, p. 272. For Laski's depiction of community members as consumers and for his functionalist and instrumentalist account of the state and rights see ibid., pp. 39, 69, 130; cf. ibid., p. 24. Laski described his theory as a 'special adaptation of the Benthamite theory to the special needs of the time'. Laski's use of expressions such as 'effective demand gave rise to economistic interpretations of his idea of the good. Laski, 'Law and the State', p. 294. See Foundations, pp. 244-5: 'Law apart, every community is a congeries of men and associations seeking the satisfaction of wants . . . [the state] . . . entrusted with power in order that it may satisfy, or organize the satisfaction of, the wants of men on the largest possible scale.' Cf. Laski, Liberty in the Modern State, p. 51: 'A compulsory training of the mind is still compulsion. It is a sacrifice of some liberty to a greater freedom when the compulsion ceases.' For criticisms of the collectivist aspects of the Grammar see Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism, pp. 189-202. See also Deane, Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski, pp. 333 ff. Cf. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 363-4; and Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 207. See also Alan Shaw, 'Liberty and Happiness', Australian Quarterly (1942), pp. 86-95, p. 88.
    • Liberty in the Modern State , pp. 51
    • Laski1
  • 343
    • 0010089320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 123 Grammar, p. 272. For Laski's depiction of community members as consumers and for his functionalist and instrumentalist account of the state and rights see ibid., pp. 39, 69, 130; cf. ibid., p. 24. Laski described his theory as a 'special adaptation of the Benthamite theory to the special needs of the time'. Laski's use of expressions such as 'effective demand gave rise to economistic interpretations of his idea of the good. Laski, 'Law and the State', p. 294. See Foundations, pp. 244-5: 'Law apart, every community is a congeries of men and associations seeking the satisfaction of wants . . . [the state] . . . entrusted with power in order that it may satisfy, or organize the satisfaction of, the wants of men on the largest possible scale.' Cf. Laski, Liberty in the Modern State, p. 51: 'A compulsory training of the mind is still compulsion. It is a sacrifice of some liberty to a greater freedom when the
    • From Political Pluralism to Collectivism , pp. 189-202
    • Zylstra1
  • 344
    • 4243454844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 123 Grammar, p. 272. For Laski's depiction of community members as consumers and for his functionalist and instrumentalist account of the state and rights see ibid., pp. 39, 69, 130; cf. ibid., p. 24. Laski described his theory as a 'special adaptation of the Benthamite theory to the special needs of the time'. Laski's use of expressions such as 'effective demand gave rise to economistic interpretations of his idea of the good. Laski, 'Law and the State', p. 294. See Foundations, pp. 244-5: 'Law apart, every community is a congeries of men and associations seeking the satisfaction of wants . . . [the state] . . . entrusted with power in order that it may satisfy, or organize the satisfaction of, the wants of men on the largest possible scale.' Cf. Laski, Liberty in the Modern State, p. 51: 'A compulsory training of the mind is still compulsion. It is a sacrifice of some liberty to a greater freedom when the compulsion ceases.' For criticisms of the collectivist aspects of the Grammar see Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism, pp. 189-202. See also Deane, Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski, pp. 333 ff. Cf. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 363-4; and Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 207. See also Alan Shaw, 'Liberty and Happiness', Australian Quarterly (1942), pp. 86-95, p. 88.
    • Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski
    • Deane1
  • 345
    • 0004335604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 123 Grammar, p. 272. For Laski's depiction of community members as consumers and for his functionalist and instrumentalist account of the state and rights see ibid., pp. 39, 69, 130; cf. ibid., p. 24. Laski described his theory as a 'special adaptation of the Benthamite theory to the special needs of the time'. Laski's use of expressions such as 'effective demand gave rise to economistic interpretations of his idea of the good. Laski, 'Law and the State', p. 294. See Foundations, pp. 244-5: 'Law apart, every community is a congeries of men and associations seeking the satisfaction of wants . . . [the state] . . . entrusted with power in order that it may satisfy, or organize the satisfaction of, the wants of men on the largest possible scale.' Cf. Laski, Liberty in the Modern State, p. 51: 'A compulsory training of the mind is still compulsion. It is a sacrifice of some liberty to a greater freedom when the compulsion ceases.' For criticisms of the collectivist aspects of the Grammar see Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism, pp. 189-202. See also Deane, Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski, pp. 333 ff. Cf. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 363-4; and Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 207. See also Alan Shaw, 'Liberty and Happiness', Australian Quarterly (1942), pp. 86-95, p. 88.
    • Pragmatic Revolt , pp. 363-364
    • Elliott1
  • 346
    • 0004348006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 123 Grammar, p. 272. For Laski's depiction of community members as consumers and for his functionalist and instrumentalist account of the state and rights see ibid., pp. 39, 69, 130; cf. ibid., p. 24. Laski described his theory as a 'special adaptation of the Benthamite theory to the special needs of the time'. Laski's use of expressions such as 'effective demand gave rise to economistic interpretations of his idea of the good. Laski, 'Law and the State', p. 294. See Foundations, pp. 244-5: 'Law apart, every community is a congeries of men and associations seeking the satisfaction of wants . . . [the state] . . . entrusted with power in order that it may satisfy, or organize the satisfaction of, the wants of men on the largest possible scale.' Cf. Laski, Liberty in the Modern State, p. 51: 'A compulsory training of the mind is still compulsion. It is a sacrifice of some liberty to a greater freedom when the compulsion ceases.' For criticisms of the collectivist aspects of the Grammar see Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism, pp. 189-202. See also Deane, Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski, pp. 333 ff. Cf. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 363-4; and Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 207. See also Alan Shaw, 'Liberty and Happiness', Australian Quarterly (1942), pp. 86-95, p. 88.
    • Political Pluralism , pp. 207
    • Hsiao1
  • 347
    • 0010192079 scopus 로고
    • Liberty and happiness
    • 123 Grammar, p. 272. For Laski's depiction of community members as consumers and for his functionalist and instrumentalist account of the state and rights see ibid., pp. 39, 69, 130; cf. ibid., p. 24. Laski described his theory as a 'special adaptation of the Benthamite theory to the special needs of the time'. Laski's use of expressions such as 'effective demand gave rise to economistic interpretations of his idea of the good. Laski, 'Law and the State', p. 294. See Foundations, pp. 244-5: 'Law apart, every community is a congeries of men and associations seeking the satisfaction of wants . . . [the state] . . . entrusted with power in order that it may satisfy, or organize the satisfaction of, the wants of men on the largest possible scale.' Cf. Laski, Liberty in the Modern State, p. 51: 'A compulsory training of the mind is still compulsion. It is a sacrifice of some liberty to a greater freedom when the compulsion ceases.' For criticisms of the collectivist aspects of the Grammar see Zylstra, From Political Pluralism to Collectivism, pp. 189-202. See also Deane, Political Ideas of Harold J. Laski, pp. 333 ff. Cf. Elliott, Pragmatic Revolt, pp. 363-4; and Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 207. See also Alan Shaw, 'Liberty and Happiness', Australian Quarterly (1942), pp. 86-95, p. 88.
    • (1942) Australian Quarterly , pp. 86-95
    • Shaw, A.1
  • 348
    • 0004332742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 124 The collectivist implications of Laski's functionalist interpretation of law and the state were discussed also by Elliott in relation to Duguit's influence. Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 253-4. For Elliott's comments on the practical implications of Dewey's political thought see ibid., pp. 225-9. See also Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 163. He described Duguit's notion of the social good as 'Rousseau's general will in a strange garb'. Cf. Laski, Will Planning Restrict Freedom?, p. 10.
    • Pragmatic Politics , pp. 253-254
    • Elliott1
  • 349
    • 0010100377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 124 The collectivist implications of Laski's functionalist interpretation of law and the state were discussed also by Elliott in relation to Duguit's influence. Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 253-4. For Elliott's comments on the practical implications of Dewey's political thought see ibid., pp. 225-9. See also Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 163. He described Duguit's notion of the social good as 'Rousseau's general will in a strange garb'. Cf. Laski, Will Planning Restrict Freedom?, p. 10.
    • Pragmatic Politics , pp. 225-229
  • 350
    • 0004348006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 124 The collectivist implications of Laski's functionalist interpretation of law and the state were discussed also by Elliott in relation to Duguit's influence. Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 253-4. For Elliott's comments on the practical implications of Dewey's political thought see ibid., pp. 225-9. See also Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 163. He described Duguit's notion of the social good as 'Rousseau's general will in a strange garb'. Cf. Laski, Will Planning Restrict Freedom?, p. 10.
    • Political Pluralism , pp. 163
    • Hsiao1
  • 351
    • 0004335961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 124 The collectivist implications of Laski's functionalist interpretation of law and the state were discussed also by Elliott in relation to Duguit's influence. Elliott, 'Pragmatic Politics', pp. 253-4. For Elliott's comments on the practical implications of Dewey's political thought see ibid., pp. 225-9. See also Hsiao, Political Pluralism, p. 163. He described Duguit's notion of the social good as 'Rousseau's general will in a strange garb'. Cf. Laski, Will Planning Restrict Freedom?, p. 10.
    • Will Planning Restrict Freedom? , pp. 10
    • Laski1
  • 352
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 125 For Laski's comments on Elliott see Grammar, pp. 249 n, 282. For further background on Elliott see Isaac Kramnick and Barry Sheerman, Harold Laski: A Life and the Left (London, 1993), pp. 234, 359, 404. Follett, The New State, p. 84. Drawing upon James, Follett seeks to reconcile '"irreducible pluralism" and the self-unifying principle'. For references to James see ibid., pp. 34 n, 60, 264-7, 302, 314, 318-19, 334. See also M.P. Follett, Creative Experience (New York, 1924), p. 114.
    • Grammar
  • 353
    • 0004096092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London
    • 125 For Laski's comments on Elliott see Grammar, pp. 249 n, 282. For further background on Elliott see Isaac Kramnick and Barry Sheerman, Harold Laski: A Life and the Left (London, 1993), pp. 234, 359, 404. Follett, The New State, p. 84. Drawing upon James, Follett seeks to reconcile '"irreducible pluralism" and the self-unifying principle'. For references to James see ibid., pp. 34 n, 60, 264-7, 302, 314, 318-19, 334. See also M.P. Follett, Creative Experience (New York, 1924), p. 114.
    • (1993) Harold Laski: A Life and the Left , pp. 234
    • Kramnick, I.1    Sheerman, B.2
  • 354
    • 0004326702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 125 For Laski's comments on Elliott see Grammar, pp. 249 n, 282. For further background on Elliott see Isaac Kramnick and Barry Sheerman, Harold Laski: A Life and the Left (London, 1993), pp. 234, 359, 404. Follett, The New State, p. 84. Drawing upon James, Follett seeks to reconcile '"irreducible pluralism" and the self-unifying principle'. For references to James see ibid., pp. 34 n, 60, 264-7, 302, 314, 318-19, 334. See also M.P. Follett, Creative Experience (New York, 1924), p. 114.
    • The New State , pp. 84
    • Follett1
  • 355
    • 0004326702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 125 For Laski's comments on Elliott see Grammar, pp. 249 n, 282. For further background on Elliott see Isaac Kramnick and Barry Sheerman, Harold Laski: A Life and the Left (London, 1993), pp. 234, 359, 404. Follett, The New State, p. 84. Drawing upon James, Follett seeks to reconcile '"irreducible pluralism" and the self-unifying principle'. For references to James see ibid., pp. 34 n, 60, 264-7, 302, 314, 318-19, 334. See also M.P. Follett, Creative Experience (New York, 1924), p. 114.
    • The New State
  • 356
    • 0004264463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York
    • 125 For Laski's comments on Elliott see Grammar, pp. 249 n, 282. For further background on Elliott see Isaac Kramnick and Barry Sheerman, Harold Laski: A Life and the Left (London, 1993), pp. 234, 359, 404. Follett, The New State, p. 84. Drawing upon James, Follett seeks to reconcile '"irreducible pluralism" and the self-unifying principle'. For references to James see ibid., pp. 34 n, 60, 264-7, 302, 314, 318-19, 334. See also M.P. Follett, Creative Experience (New York, 1924), p. 114.
    • (1924) Creative Experience , pp. 114
    • Follett, M.P.1
  • 358
    • 0004326702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 127 Ibid., p. 304 n. Follett wrote (ibid., p. 315) that the 'great lesson of Mr. Laski's book is in its implication that we do not have a sovereign state until we make one. Political theory will not create sovereignty, acts of Parliament cannot confer sovereignty, only living the life will turn us, subjects indeed at present, into kings of our own destiny.'
    • The New State
  • 359
    • 0004326702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • that the 'great lesson of Mr. Laski's book is in its implication that we do not have a sovereign state until we make one. Political theory will not create sovereignty, acts of Parliament cannot confer sovereignty, only living the life will turn us, subjects indeed at present, into kings of our own destiny
    • 127 Ibid., p. 304 n. Follett wrote (ibid., p. 315) that the 'great lesson of Mr. Laski's book is in its implication that we do not have a sovereign state until we make one. Political theory will not create sovereignty, acts of Parliament cannot confer sovereignty, only living the life will turn us, subjects indeed at present, into kings of our own destiny.'
    • The New State , pp. 315
    • Follett1
  • 360
    • 0010212416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 128 See Studies, p. 23. Laski wrote that we achieve order 'by being able to convince men that some unity we make means added richness to their lives. We encounter everywhere not allegiance, but allegiances in men.' Grammar, p. 287.
    • Studies , pp. 23
  • 361
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 128 See Studies, p. 23. Laski wrote that we achieve order 'by being able to convince men that some unity we make means added richness to their lives. We encounter everywhere not allegiance, but allegiances in men.' Grammar, p. 287.
    • Grammar , pp. 287
  • 362
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 129 Grammar, p. 287. Laski wrote that loyalty 'cannot be imposed upon us. It must grow spontaneously out of our experience'; cf. ibid., p. 263. See also Follett, The New State, p. 69, on the possibility of 'interweaving' wills. For Laski's citation of Follett see Grammar, p. 276. This definition was taken from Follett, Creative Experience, p. 264. James also wrote of the need to grow unity. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 382. See also Essays, pp. 42-3.
    • Grammar , pp. 287
  • 363
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 129 Grammar, p. 287. Laski wrote that loyalty 'cannot be imposed upon us. It must grow spontaneously out of our experience'; cf. ibid., p. 263. See also Follett, The New State, p. 69, on the possibility of 'interweaving' wills. For Laski's citation of Follett see Grammar, p. 276. This definition was taken from Follett, Creative Experience, p. 264. James also wrote of the need to grow unity. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 382. See also Essays, pp. 42-3.
    • Grammar , pp. 263
  • 364
    • 0004326702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • on the possibility of 'interweaving' wills
    • 129 Grammar, p. 287. Laski wrote that loyalty 'cannot be imposed upon us. It must grow spontaneously out of our experience'; cf. ibid., p. 263. See also Follett, The New State, p. 69, on the possibility of 'interweaving' wills. For Laski's citation of Follett see Grammar, p. 276. This definition was taken from Follett, Creative Experience, p. 264. James also wrote of the need to grow unity. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 382. See also Essays, pp. 42-3.
    • The New State , pp. 69
    • Follett1
  • 365
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 129 Grammar, p. 287. Laski wrote that loyalty 'cannot be imposed upon us. It must grow spontaneously out of our experience'; cf. ibid., p. 263. See also Follett, The New State, p. 69, on the possibility of 'interweaving' wills. For Laski's citation of Follett see Grammar, p. 276. This definition was taken from Follett, Creative Experience, p. 264. James also wrote of the need to grow unity. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 382. See also Essays, pp. 42-3.
    • Grammar , pp. 276
  • 366
    • 0004264463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 129 Grammar, p. 287. Laski wrote that loyalty 'cannot be imposed upon us. It must grow spontaneously out of our experience'; cf. ibid., p. 263. See also Follett, The New State, p. 69, on the possibility of 'interweaving' wills. For Laski's citation of Follett see Grammar, p. 276. This definition was taken from Follett, Creative Experience, p. 264. James also wrote of the need to grow unity. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 382. See also Essays, pp. 42-3.
    • Creative Experience , pp. 264
    • Follett1
  • 367
    • 0010098581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 129 Grammar, p. 287. Laski wrote that loyalty 'cannot be imposed upon us. It must grow spontaneously out of our experience'; cf. ibid., p. 263. See also Follett, The New State, p. 69, on the possibility of 'interweaving' wills. For Laski's citation of Follett see Grammar, p. 276. This definition was taken from Follett, Creative Experience, p. 264. James also wrote of the need to grow unity. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 382. See also Essays, pp. 42-3.
    • Thought and Character , vol.2 , pp. 382
    • Perry1
  • 368
    • 0010212417 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 129 Grammar, p. 287. Laski wrote that loyalty 'cannot be imposed upon us. It must grow spontaneously out of our experience'; cf. ibid., p. 263. See also Follett, The New State, p. 69, on the possibility of 'interweaving' wills. For Laski's citation of Follett see Grammar, p. 276. This definition was taken from Follett, Creative Experience, p. 264. James also wrote of the need to grow unity. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 382. See also Essays, pp. 42-3.
    • Essays , pp. 42-43
  • 369
    • 0010091623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 130 Dewey cited in Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', p. 301. Follett, The New State, pp. 266-7. Bernard Bosanquet in the 1919 edition of the Philosophical Theory of the State (London, 1965), pp. xiii, liv, described Follett's work as the 'most sane and brilliant of recent works in political theory'. See ibid., p. xl for Bosanquet's comment on James's anti-intellectualism. Note that while James gives a sympathetic hearing to Hegel the general tenor of his philosophy is closer to pluralism than monism. See Essays, p. 29; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 273-4.
    • Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey , pp. 301
    • Kallen1
  • 370
    • 0004326702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 130 Dewey cited in Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', p. 301. Follett, The New State, pp. 266-7. Bernard Bosanquet in the 1919 edition of the Philosophical Theory of the State (London, 1965), pp. xiii, liv, described Follett's work as the 'most sane and brilliant of recent works in political theory'. See ibid., p. xl for Bosanquet's comment on James's anti-intellectualism. Note that while James gives a sympathetic hearing to Hegel the general tenor of his philosophy is closer to pluralism than monism. See Essays, p. 29; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 273-4.
    • The New State , pp. 266-267
    • Follett1
  • 371
    • 0004199507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London, described Follett's work as the 'most sane and brilliant of recent works in political theory
    • 130 Dewey cited in Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', p. 301. Follett, The New State, pp. 266-7. Bernard Bosanquet in the 1919 edition of the Philosophical Theory of the State (London, 1965), pp. xiii, liv, described Follett's work as the 'most sane and brilliant of recent works in political theory'. See ibid., p. xl for Bosanquet's comment on James's anti-intellectualism. Note that while James gives a sympathetic hearing to Hegel the general tenor of his philosophy is closer to pluralism than monism. See Essays, p. 29; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 273-4.
    • (1965) Philosophical Theory of the State , pp. 13
  • 372
    • 0004199507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for Bosanquet's comment on James's anti-intellectualism. Note that while James gives a sympathetic hearing to Hegel the general tenor of his philosophy is closer to pluralism than monism
    • 130 Dewey cited in Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', p. 301. Follett, The New State, pp. 266-7. Bernard Bosanquet in the 1919 edition of the Philosophical Theory of the State (London, 1965), pp. xiii, liv, described Follett's work as the 'most sane and brilliant of recent works in political theory'. See ibid., p. xl for Bosanquet's comment on James's anti-intellectualism. Note that while James gives a sympathetic hearing to Hegel the general tenor of his philosophy is closer to pluralism than monism. See Essays, p. 29; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 273-4.
    • Philosophical Theory of the State , pp. 11
  • 373
    • 0010213108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 130 Dewey cited in Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', p. 301. Follett, The New State, pp. 266-7. Bernard Bosanquet in the 1919 edition of the Philosophical Theory of the State (London, 1965), pp. xiii, liv, described Follett's work as the 'most sane and brilliant of recent works in political theory'. See ibid., p. xl for Bosanquet's comment on James's anti-intellectualism. Note that while James gives a sympathetic hearing to Hegel the general tenor of his philosophy is closer to pluralism than monism. See Essays, p. 29; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 273-4.
    • Essays , pp. 29
  • 374
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 130 Dewey cited in Kallen, 'Individuality, Individualism and John Dewey', p. 301. Follett, The New State, pp. 266-7. Bernard Bosanquet in the 1919 edition of the Philosophical Theory of the State (London, 1965), pp. xiii, liv, described Follett's work as the 'most sane and brilliant of recent works in political theory'. See ibid., p. xl for Bosanquet's comment on James's anti-intellectualism. Note that while James gives a sympathetic hearing to Hegel the general tenor of his philosophy is closer to pluralism than monism. See Essays, p. 29; and James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 273-4.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 273-274
    • James1
  • 375
    • 0004326702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 131 Follett, The New State, pp. xxx, 11, 344 ff. On the notion of the self as a self-unifying centre see ibid., p. 76. On the psychological nature of her notion of manyness in oneness see Follett, The New State, pp. 14 n, 65, 158, 272. See also Follett, 'Community is a Process', Philosophical Review, XXVIII (1919), pp. 576-88, pp. 576-9.
    • The New State , pp. 30
    • Follett1
  • 376
    • 0004326702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 131 Follett, The New State, pp. xxx, 11, 344 ff. On the notion of the self as a self-unifying centre see ibid., p. 76. On the psychological nature of her notion of manyness in oneness see Follett, The New State, pp. 14 n, 65, 158, 272. See also Follett, 'Community is a Process', Philosophical Review, XXVIII (1919), pp. 576-88, pp. 576-9.
    • The New State , pp. 76
  • 377
    • 0004326702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 131 Follett, The New State, pp. xxx, 11, 344 ff. On the notion of the self as a self-unifying centre see ibid., p. 76. On the psychological nature of her notion of manyness in oneness see Follett, The New State, pp. 14 n, 65, 158, 272. See also Follett, 'Community is a Process', Philosophical Review, XXVIII (1919), pp. 576-88, pp. 576-9.
    • The New State
    • Follett1
  • 378
    • 0001369053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Community is a process
    • 131 Follett, The New State, pp. xxx, 11, 344 ff. On the notion of the self as a self-unifying centre see ibid., p. 76. On the psychological nature of her notion of manyness in oneness see Follett, The New State, pp. 14 n, 65, 158, 272. See also Follett, 'Community is a Process', Philosophical Review, XXVIII (1919), pp. 576-88, pp. 576-9.
    • (1919) Philosophical Review , vol.28 , pp. 576-588
    • Follett1
  • 380
    • 0004096092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 133 On Laski's syndicalism see Kramnick and Sheerman, Harold Laski: A Life and the Left, pp. 91-2. Grammar, pp. 256, 262, 263. See also on this idea Follett, 'Community is a Process', pp. 576-88. James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 251-2. See also Grammar, pp. 260, 270; cf. ibid., p. 264.
    • Harold Laski: A Life and the Left , pp. 91-92
    • Kramnick1    Sheerman2
  • 381
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 133 On Laski's syndicalism see Kramnick and Sheerman, Harold Laski: A Life and the Left, pp. 91-2. Grammar, pp. 256, 262, 263. See also on this idea Follett, 'Community is a Process', pp. 576-88. James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 251-2. See also Grammar, pp. 260, 270; cf. ibid., p. 264.
    • Grammar , pp. 256
  • 382
    • 0001369053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 133 On Laski's syndicalism see Kramnick and Sheerman, Harold Laski: A Life and the Left, pp. 91-2. Grammar, pp. 256, 262, 263. See also on this idea Follett, 'Community is a Process', pp. 576-88. James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 251-2. See also Grammar, pp. 260, 270; cf. ibid., p. 264.
    • Community is a Process , pp. 576-588
    • Follett1
  • 383
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 133 On Laski's syndicalism see Kramnick and Sheerman, Harold Laski: A Life and the Left, pp. 91-2. Grammar, pp. 256, 262, 263. See also on this idea Follett, 'Community is a Process', pp. 576-88. James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 251-2. See also Grammar, pp. 260, 270; cf. ibid., p. 264.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 251-252
    • James1
  • 384
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 133 On Laski's syndicalism see Kramnick and Sheerman, Harold Laski: A Life and the Left, pp. 91-2. Grammar, pp. 256, 262, 263. See also on this idea Follett, 'Community is a Process', pp. 576-88. James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 251-2. See also Grammar, pp. 260, 270; cf. ibid., p. 264.
    • Grammar , pp. 260
  • 385
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 133 On Laski's syndicalism see Kramnick and Sheerman, Harold Laski: A Life and the Left, pp. 91-2. Grammar, pp. 256, 262, 263. See also on this idea Follett, 'Community is a Process', pp. 576-88. James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 251-2. See also Grammar, pp. 260, 270; cf. ibid., p. 264.
    • Grammar , pp. 264
  • 386
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 134 On social integration as an enriching process see Grammar, pp. 29, 32, 37, 261-2, 282. For Follett's comments on this matter see 'Community is a Process', p. 587. Cf. James, Notes for Metaphysical Seminary (1903-4), cited in Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 383. See also Essays, pp. 7, 119; and James, Pragmatism, p. 166.
    • Grammar , pp. 29
  • 387
    • 0010212419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 134 On social integration as an enriching process see Grammar, pp. 29, 32, 37, 261-2, 282. For Follett's comments on this matter see 'Community is a Process', p. 587. Cf. James, Notes for Metaphysical Seminary (1903-4), cited in Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 383. See also Essays, pp. 7, 119; and James, Pragmatism, p. 166.
    • Community is a Process , pp. 587
  • 388
    • 0000154709 scopus 로고
    • Notes for metaphysical seminary
    • cited in Perry
    • 134 On social integration as an enriching process see Grammar, pp. 29, 32, 37, 261-2, 282. For Follett's comments on this matter see 'Community is a Process', p. 587. Cf. James, Notes for Metaphysical Seminary (1903-4), cited in Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 383. See also Essays, pp. 7, 119; and James, Pragmatism, p. 166.
    • (1903) Thought and Character , vol.2 , pp. 383
    • James1
  • 389
    • 0010091103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 134 On social integration as an enriching process see Grammar, pp. 29, 32, 37, 261-2, 282. For Follett's comments on this matter see 'Community is a Process', p. 587. Cf. James, Notes for Metaphysical Seminary (1903-4), cited in Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 383. See also Essays, pp. 7, 119; and James, Pragmatism, p. 166.
    • Essays , pp. 7
  • 390
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 134 On social integration as an enriching process see Grammar, pp. 29, 32, 37, 261-2, 282. For Follett's comments on this matter see 'Community is a Process', p. 587. Cf. James, Notes for Metaphysical Seminary (1903-4), cited in Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 383. See also Essays, pp. 7, 119; and James, Pragmatism, p. 166.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 166
    • James1
  • 391
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 135 Grammar, p. 260; cf. pp. 263-5.
    • Grammar , pp. 260
  • 392
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 136 Grammar, pp. 260, 262. James wrote that the transcendentalists believed that 'Most of us are . . . mere syllables in the mouth of Allah', James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 212.
    • Grammar , pp. 260
  • 393
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 136 Grammar, pp. 260, 262. James wrote that the transcendentalists believed that 'Most of us are . . . mere syllables in the mouth of Allah', James, A Pluralistic Universe, p. 212.
    • A Pluralistic Universe , pp. 212
    • James1
  • 394
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 137 Grammar, pp. 26, 29-34, 68.
    • Grammar , pp. 26
  • 395
    • 0004348006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 138 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 205-6, 208. Hsiao regarded James's failure to achieve a comprehension of the whole as revealing a fundamental weakness in his philosophy, adding that pragmatism did not give enough credit to its monistic or rationalist opponents. Cf. Follett, The New State, pp. 265-72. It is important to note that both Hsiao and Follett used the words pragmatism to refer to all the major aspects of James's thought.
    • Political Pluralism , pp. 205-206
    • Hsiao1
  • 396
    • 0004326702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is important to note that both Hsiao and Follett used the words pragmatism to refer to all the major aspects of James's thought
    • 138 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 205-6, 208. Hsiao regarded James's failure to achieve a comprehension of the whole as revealing a fundamental weakness in his philosophy, adding that pragmatism did not give enough credit to its monistic or rationalist opponents. Cf. Follett, The New State, pp. 265-72. It is important to note that both Hsiao and Follett used the words pragmatism to refer to all the major aspects of James's thought.
    • The New State , pp. 265-272
    • Follett1
  • 398
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 139 Hsiao, Political Pluralism, pp. 165-6. Cf. Grammar, pp. 270-1.
    • Grammar , pp. 270-271
  • 399
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 140 Grammar, p. 261. For James's comments on the distributive and the collective see James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 275 ff. Cf. Authority, p. 68. Laski wrote, again borrowing from James, that while in theory all our actions 'move in unity down the endless stream of time' in practice it is the discontinuous action that proves 'vital'. For Laski's review of Hsiao's book see the New Republic (28 March 1928), p. 197.
    • Grammar , pp. 261
  • 400
    • 0004213458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 140 Grammar, p. 261. For James's comments on the distributive and the collective see James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 275 ff. Cf. Authority, p. 68. Laski wrote, again borrowing from James, that while in theory all our actions 'move in unity down the endless stream of time' in practice it is the discontinuous action that proves 'vital'. For Laski's review of Hsiao's book see the New Republic (28 March 1928), p. 197.
    • A Pluralistic Universe
    • James1
  • 401
    • 79958999318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 140 Grammar, p. 261. For James's comments on the distributive and the collective see James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 275 ff. Cf. Authority, p. 68. Laski wrote, again borrowing from James, that while in theory all our actions 'move in unity down the endless stream of time' in practice it is the discontinuous action that proves 'vital'. For Laski's review of Hsiao's book see the New Republic (28 March 1928), p. 197.
    • Authority , pp. 68
  • 402
    • 0010155650 scopus 로고
    • 28 March
    • 140 Grammar, p. 261. For James's comments on the distributive and the collective see James, A Pluralistic Universe, pp. 275 ff. Cf. Authority, p. 68. Laski wrote, again borrowing from James, that while in theory all our actions 'move in unity down the endless stream of time' in practice it is the discontinuous action that proves 'vital'. For Laski's review of Hsiao's book see the New Republic (28 March 1928), p. 197.
    • (1928) New Republic , pp. 197
  • 403
    • 0004346760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 141 James, Will to Believe, p. 61. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 282, 286.
    • Will to Believe , pp. 61
    • James1
  • 404
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 141 James, Will to Believe, p. 61. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 282, 286.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 282
    • James1
  • 405
    • 0010205855 scopus 로고
    • 15 July
    • 142 Letters, I, p. 633 (15 July 1924).
    • (1924) Letters , vol.1 , pp. 633
  • 406
    • 84953505332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 143 Grammar, p. 260. See also Foundations, p. 169: 'we are forced to the admission that the parts are as real, as primary, and as sell-sufficing as the whole'. Cf. James, The Will to Believe, pp. viii, 46. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 271.
    • Grammar , pp. 260
  • 407
    • 0038977243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • we are forced to the admission that the parts are as real, as primary, and as sell-sufficing as the whole
    • 143 Grammar, p. 260. See also Foundations, p. 169: 'we are forced to the admission that the parts are as real, as primary, and as sell-sufficing as the whole'. Cf. James, The Will to Believe, pp. viii, 46. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 271.
    • Foundations , pp. 169
  • 408
    • 0004210683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 143 Grammar, p. 260. See also Foundations, p. 169: 'we are forced to the admission that the parts are as real, as primary, and as sell-sufficing as the whole'. Cf. James, The Will to Believe, pp. viii, 46. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 271.
    • The Will to Believe , pp. 8
    • James1
  • 409
    • 0010157636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 143 Grammar, p. 260. See also Foundations, p. 169: 'we are forced to the admission that the parts are as real, as primary, and as sell-sufficing as the whole'. Cf. James, The Will to Believe, pp. viii, 46. Cf. Perry, Thought and Character, II, p. 271.
    • Thought and Character , vol.2 , pp. 271
    • Perry1
  • 410
    • 0010205855 scopus 로고
    • 15 July
    • 144 Letters, I, p. 633 (15 July 1924).
    • (1924) Letters , vol.1 , pp. 633
  • 412
    • 0004339746 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 146 Laski wrote that James and Dewey had failed to make their meaning clear for fear of being misunderstood, and as a result pragmatism became 'part of the defensive mechanism of a privileged order'. Laski, The American Democracy, pp. 726-7.
    • The American Democracy , pp. 726-727
    • Laski1
  • 413
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 147 James, Pragmatism, pp. 53, 199, 207, 209, 218. See also Dewey, Essays, pp. 306, 347.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 53
    • James1
  • 414
    • 0010203465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 147 James, Pragmatism, pp. 53, 199, 207, 209, 218. See also Dewey, Essays, pp. 306, 347.
    • Essays , pp. 306
    • Dewey1
  • 415
    • 0010148322 scopus 로고
    • Boston
    • 148 For criticisms of pragmatist philosophy on this and related scores see: Albert Schinz, Anti-Pragmatism (Boston, 1909). For James's dismissal of Schinz's argument see Letters of William James, II, pp. 319, 337. Cf. Charles Morris who noted that pragmatism was dismissed as the 'philosophy of the business man'; and 'the reductio ad absurdum of empiricism'. With pragmatism, some had argued, true philosophy had 'vanished'; philosophy was now brought to the 'brink of comedy, if not downright charlatanism'. C. Morris, 'Neo-Pragmatism and the Ways of Knowing', Monist, XXXVII (1928), pp. 494-510. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 198-9. See also Benjamin Stolberg, 'Degradation of American Psychology', The Nation (15 October 1930), pp. 395-8.
    • (1909) Anti-pragmatism
    • Schinz, A.1
  • 416
    • 0010131075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 148 For criticisms of pragmatist philosophy on this and related scores see: Albert Schinz, Anti-Pragmatism (Boston, 1909). For James's dismissal of Schinz's argument see Letters of William James, II, pp. 319, 337. Cf. Charles Morris who noted that pragmatism was dismissed as the 'philosophy of the business man'; and 'the reductio ad absurdum of empiricism'. With pragmatism, some had argued, true philosophy had 'vanished'; philosophy was now brought to the 'brink of comedy, if not downright charlatanism'. C. Morris, 'Neo-Pragmatism and the Ways of Knowing', Monist, XXXVII (1928), pp. 494-510. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 198-9. See also Benjamin Stolberg, 'Degradation of American Psychology', The Nation (15 October 1930), pp. 395-8.
    • Letters of William James , vol.2 , pp. 319
  • 417
    • 0010148323 scopus 로고
    • Neo-pragmatism and the ways of knowing
    • 148 For criticisms of pragmatist philosophy on this and related scores see: Albert Schinz, Anti-Pragmatism (Boston, 1909). For James's dismissal of Schinz's argument see Letters of William James, II, pp. 319, 337. Cf. Charles Morris who noted that pragmatism was dismissed as the 'philosophy of the business man'; and 'the reductio ad absurdum of empiricism'. With pragmatism, some had argued, true philosophy had 'vanished'; philosophy was now brought to the 'brink of comedy, if not downright charlatanism'. C. Morris, 'Neo-Pragmatism and the Ways of Knowing', Monist, XXXVII (1928), pp. 494-510. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 198-9. See also Benjamin Stolberg, 'Degradation of American Psychology', The Nation (15 October 1930), pp. 395-8.
    • (1928) Monist , vol.37 , pp. 494-510
    • Morris, C.1
  • 418
    • 0004275191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 148 For criticisms of pragmatist philosophy on this and related scores see: Albert Schinz, Anti-Pragmatism (Boston, 1909). For James's dismissal of Schinz's argument see Letters of William James, II, pp. 319, 337. Cf. Charles Morris who noted that pragmatism was dismissed as the 'philosophy of the business man'; and 'the reductio ad absurdum of empiricism'. With pragmatism, some had argued, true philosophy had 'vanished'; philosophy was now brought to the 'brink of comedy, if not downright charlatanism'. C. Morris, 'Neo-Pragmatism and the Ways of Knowing', Monist, XXXVII (1928), pp. 494-510. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 198-9. See also Benjamin Stolberg, 'Degradation of American Psychology', The Nation (15 October 1930), pp. 395-8.
    • Pragmatism , pp. 198-199
    • James1
  • 419
    • 0010194674 scopus 로고
    • Degradation of American psychology
    • 15 October
    • 148 For criticisms of pragmatist philosophy on this and related scores see: Albert Schinz, Anti-Pragmatism (Boston, 1909). For James's dismissal of Schinz's argument see Letters of William James, II, pp. 319, 337. Cf. Charles Morris who noted that pragmatism was dismissed as the 'philosophy of the business man'; and 'the reductio ad absurdum of empiricism'. With pragmatism, some had argued, true philosophy had 'vanished'; philosophy was now brought to the 'brink of comedy, if not downright charlatanism'. C. Morris, 'Neo-Pragmatism and the Ways of Knowing', Monist, XXXVII (1928), pp. 494-510. Cf. James, Pragmatism, pp. 198-9. See also Benjamin Stolberg, 'Degradation of American Psychology', The Nation (15 October 1930), pp. 395-8.
    • (1930) The Nation , pp. 395-398
    • Stolberg, B.1
  • 421
    • 0010155651 scopus 로고
    • 25 August
    • 150 Letters, I, p. 364 (25 August 1921).
    • (1921) Letters , vol.1 , pp. 364


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.