메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 26, Issue 2, 1998, Pages 157-165

Doubts about Death: The Silence of the Institute of Medicine

(1)  Menikoff, Jerry a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords

ADVISORY COMMITTEE; ANALYTICAL APPROACH; ARTICLE; BRAIN DEATH; CADAVER; DEATH; DEATH AND EUTHANASIA; DONOR; EVALUATION; HUMAN; INFORMED CONSENT; INSTITUTE OF MEDICINE; INTERPERSONAL COMMUNICATION; LAW; MANAGEMENT; ORGANIZATION; POLICY; PRACTICE GUIDELINE; STANDARD; TIME; TRANSPLANTATION; UNIFORM DETERMINATION OF DEATH ACT; UNITED STATES; VENTILATOR;

EID: 0032081553     PISSN: 10731105     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1748-720X.1998.tb01671.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (64)

References (79)
  • 1
    • 84939073778 scopus 로고
    • Guidelines for the Determination of Death
    • Guidelines for the Determination of Death, hereinafter Report of the Medical Consultants
    • The tests involve checking specifically for the absence of various reflexes that would otherwise exist if the person's brain was still functioning. See, for example, Report of the Medical Consultants on the Diagnosis of Death to the President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, "Guidelines for the Determination of Death," JAMA, 246 (1981): 2184-86 [hereinafter Report of the Medical Consultants].
    • (1981) JAMA , vol.246 , pp. 2184-2186
  • 2
    • 0032556937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Transplantation of Kidneys from Donors Whose Hearts Have Stopped Beating
    • See, for example, Y.W. Cho et al., "Transplantation of Kidneys from Donors Whose Hearts Have Stopped Beating," N. Engl. J. Med., 338 (1998): 221-25.
    • (1998) N. Engl. J. Med. , vol.338 , pp. 221-225
    • Cho, Y.W.1
  • 3
    • 6444227983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Not Quite Dead
    • CBS television broadcast, Apr. 13
    • See, for example, "Not Quite Dead," 60 Minutes (CBS television broadcast, Apr. 13, 1997); G. Kolata, "Controversy Erupts Over Organ Removals," New York Times, Apr. 13, 1997, at 28; M. Carlson, "A Dead Issue," Time, Apr. 28, 1997, at 26; E. Neus, "Fight for Organ-Donation Awareness Gets Tougher," USA Today, Apr. 21, 1997, at 6D; and J. Funk and J. Mazzolini, "Clinic Puts Controversial Transplant Plan on Hold," Plain Dealer [Cleveland], Apr. 4, 1997, at 1A.
    • (1997) 60 Minutes
  • 4
    • 0006190237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Controversy Erupts over Organ Removals
    • Apr. 13
    • See, for example, "Not Quite Dead," 60 Minutes (CBS television broadcast, Apr. 13, 1997); G. Kolata, "Controversy Erupts Over Organ Removals," New York Times, Apr. 13, 1997, at 28; M. Carlson, "A Dead Issue," Time, Apr. 28, 1997, at 26; E. Neus, "Fight for Organ-Donation Awareness Gets Tougher," USA Today, Apr. 21, 1997, at 6D; and J. Funk and J. Mazzolini, "Clinic Puts Controversial Transplant Plan on Hold," Plain Dealer [Cleveland], Apr. 4, 1997, at 1A.
    • (1997) New York Times , pp. 28
    • Kolata, G.1
  • 5
    • 0347107775 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Dead Issue
    • Apr. 28
    • See, for example, "Not Quite Dead," 60 Minutes (CBS television broadcast, Apr. 13, 1997); G. Kolata, "Controversy Erupts Over Organ Removals," New York Times, Apr. 13, 1997, at 28; M. Carlson, "A Dead Issue," Time, Apr. 28, 1997, at 26; E. Neus, "Fight for Organ-Donation Awareness Gets Tougher," USA Today, Apr. 21, 1997, at 6D; and J. Funk and J. Mazzolini, "Clinic Puts Controversial Transplant Plan on Hold," Plain Dealer [Cleveland], Apr. 4, 1997, at 1A.
    • (1997) Time , pp. 26
    • Carlson, M.1
  • 6
    • 24544463362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fight for Organ-Donation Awareness Gets Tougher
    • Apr. 21
    • See, for example, "Not Quite Dead," 60 Minutes (CBS television broadcast, Apr. 13, 1997); G. Kolata, "Controversy Erupts Over Organ Removals," New York Times, Apr. 13, 1997, at 28; M. Carlson, "A Dead Issue," Time, Apr. 28, 1997, at 26; E. Neus, "Fight for Organ-Donation Awareness Gets Tougher," USA Today, Apr. 21, 1997, at 6D; and J. Funk and J. Mazzolini, "Clinic Puts Controversial Transplant Plan on Hold," Plain Dealer [Cleveland], Apr. 4, 1997, at 1A.
    • (1997) USA Today
    • Neus, E.1
  • 7
    • 0347107776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Clinic Puts Controversial Transplant Plan on Hold
    • [Cleveland], Apr. 4
    • See, for example, "Not Quite Dead," 60 Minutes (CBS television broadcast, Apr. 13, 1997); G. Kolata, "Controversy Erupts Over Organ Removals," New York Times, Apr. 13, 1997, at 28; M. Carlson, "A Dead Issue," Time, Apr. 28, 1997, at 26; E. Neus, "Fight for Organ-Donation Awareness Gets Tougher," USA Today, Apr. 21, 1997, at 6D; and J. Funk and J. Mazzolini, "Clinic Puts Controversial Transplant Plan on Hold," Plain Dealer [Cleveland], Apr. 4, 1997, at 1A.
    • (1997) Plain Dealer
    • Funk, J.1    Mazzolini, J.2
  • 8
    • 0030951513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Asystolic, or Non-heartbeating, Donor
    • as cited in Cho et al., supra note 2. Thus, strong incentives exist to interpret the legal and ethical issues in a way that permits use of such organs
    • The use of non-heart-beating donors (NHBDs) could have a major impact on the number of organs available for transplantation. For example, it has been suggested that the use of such donors could increase the supply of kidneys by a factor of 2 to 4.5. See G. Koostra, "The Asystolic, or Non-heartbeating, Donor," Transplantation, 63 (1997): 917-21, as cited in Cho et al., supra note 2. Thus, strong incentives exist to interpret the legal and ethical issues in a way that permits use of such organs.
    • (1997) Transplantation , vol.63 , pp. 917-921
    • Koostra, G.1
  • 10
    • 0346477554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The Institute of Medicine (IOM) described its mandate as being to determine the "alternative medical procedures that can be used to increase the availability of organs and at the same time ensure the ethically and medically sound treatment of donor patients before and after death." It also paraphrased this request to be "in essence, ... how can the United States have a good organ donor and transplantation program?" Id. at 2.
  • 11
    • 0347738231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some Hospitals Use Questionable Methods to Get Organs for Transplant, Panel Says
    • Dec. 19
    • See, for example, R. Weiss, "Some Hospitals Use Questionable Methods to Get Organs for Transplant, Panel Says," Washington Post, Dec. 19, 1997, at A27; and S. Sternberg, "Kidneys OK for Transplant Even After Heart Stops," USA Today, Jan. 22, 1998, at 10D.
    • (1997) Washington Post
    • Weiss, R.1
  • 12
    • 24544456764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kidneys OK for Transplant even after Heart Stops
    • Jan. 22
    • See, for example, R. Weiss, "Some Hospitals Use Questionable Methods to Get Organs for Transplant, Panel Says," Washington Post, Dec. 19, 1997, at A27; and S. Sternberg, "Kidneys OK for Transplant Even After Heart Stops," USA Today, Jan. 22, 1998, at 10D.
    • (1998) USA Today
    • Sternberg, S.1
  • 13
    • 0032010132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Institute of Medicine's Report on Non-Heart-Beating Organ Transplantation
    • The Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal has published an article by the principal investigator and others involved in producing the IOM report. See R. Herdman, T.L. Beauchamp, and J.T. Potts Jr., "The Institute of Medicine's Report on Non-Heart-Beating Organ Transplantation," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 8 (1998): 83-90. That journal had previously devoted an entire issue to what has remained the most extensive evaluation of the use of NHBDs. See Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3, no. 2 (1993), subsequently reissued as R.M. Arnold et al., eds., Procuring Organs for Transplant: The Debate Over Non-Heart-Beating Cadaver Protocols (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1995).
    • (1998) Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal , vol.8 , pp. 83-90
    • Herdman, R.1    Beauchamp, T.L.2    Potts J.T., Jr.3
  • 14
    • 0032010132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal has published an article by the principal investigator and others involved in producing the IOM report. See R. Herdman, T.L. Beauchamp, and J.T. Potts Jr., "The Institute of Medicine's Report on Non- Heart-Beating Organ Transplantation," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 8 (1998): 83-90. That journal had previously devoted an entire issue to what has remained the most extensive evaluation of the use of NHBDs. See Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3, no. 2 (1993), subsequently reissued as R.M. Arnold et al., eds., Procuring Organs for Transplant: The Debate Over Non-Heart-Beating Cadaver Protocols (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1995).
    • (1993) Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal , vol.3 , Issue.2
  • 15
    • 0032010132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press
    • The Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal has published an article by the principal investigator and others involved in producing the IOM report. See R. Herdman, T.L. Beauchamp, and J.T. Potts Jr., "The Institute of Medicine's Report on Non- Heart-Beating Organ Transplantation," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 8 (1998): 83-90. That journal had previously devoted an entire issue to what has remained the most extensive evaluation of the use of NHBDs. See Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3, no. 2 (1993), subsequently reissued as R.M. Arnold et al., eds., Procuring Organs for Transplant: The Debate Over Non-Heart-Beating Cadaver Protocols (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1995).
    • (1995) Procuring Organs for Transplant: The Debate over Non-Heart-Beating Cadaver Protocols
    • Arnold, R.M.1
  • 16
    • 17644376762 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5
    • See IOM Report, supra note 5, at 8.
    • IOM Report , pp. 8
  • 17
    • 0347738233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 59-60
    • Id. at 59-60.
  • 18
    • 0345845957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 59 n."*"
    • Id. at 59 n."*".
  • 19
    • 0343427827 scopus 로고
    • President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research
    • Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, "If deprived of blood flow for at least 10-15 minutes, the brain, including the brainstem, will completely cease functioning."
    • See, for example, President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Defining Death: A Report on the Medical, Legal and Ethical Issues in the Determination of Death (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1981): at 16-17 ("If deprived of blood flow for at least 10-15 minutes, the brain, including the brainstem, will completely cease functioning.").
    • (1981) Defining Death: A Report on the Medical, Legal and Ethical Issues in the Determination of Death , pp. 16-17
  • 20
    • 0346476818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This should be contrasted with what would be required explicitly to declare John "brain dead," which would involve numerous tests designed directly to demonstrate that his brain is not functioning. See Report of the Medical Consultants, supra note 1.
  • 21
    • 0347107025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Uniform Determination of Death Act, § 1, 12 U.L.A. 340 (Supp. 1991)
    • Uniform Determination of Death Act, § 1, 12 U.L.A. 340 (Supp. 1991).
  • 22
    • 0027621244 scopus 로고
    • Are the Patients Who Become Organ Donors under the Pittsburgh Protocol for 'Non-Heart-Beating Donors' Really Dead?
    • See, for example, J. Lynn, "Are the Patients Who Become Organ Donors under the Pittsburgh Protocol for 'Non-Heart-Beating Donors' Really Dead?," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3 (1993): 167-78; and D. Cole, "Statutory Definitions of Death and the Management of Terminally Ill Patients Who May Become Organ Donors After Death," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3 (1993): 145-55.
    • (1993) Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal , vol.3 , pp. 167-178
    • Lynn, J.1
  • 23
    • 0027619491 scopus 로고
    • Statutory Definitions of Death and the Management of Terminally Ill Patients Who May Become Organ Donors after Death
    • See, for example, J. Lynn, "Are the Patients Who Become Organ Donors under the Pittsburgh Protocol for 'Non- Heart-Beating Donors' Really Dead?," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3 (1993): 167-78; and D. Cole, "Statutory Definitions of Death and the Management of Terminally Ill Patients Who May Become Organ Donors After Death," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3 (1993): 145-55.
    • (1993) Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal , vol.3 , pp. 145-155
    • Cole, D.1
  • 24
    • 17644376762 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5
    • See IOM Report, supra note 5, at 58-59.
    • IOM Report , pp. 58-59
  • 26
    • 0347737533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • To some extent, there must be an element of real-world practicality in determining whether something is not capable of being reversed. Thus, for example, the theoretical possibility of a heart transplant would not alter a determination of irreversibility, absent some demonstration that the patient did in fact have access to an available heart. Issues such as this lead some to question the very use of "irreversibility" in the context of cardiopulmonary function, as opposed to determining brain function, where there is currently no way to reverse the damage to a brain that has suffered from loss of oxygen for a sufficient period of time. See, for example, Cole, supra note 15.
  • 27
    • 0030816313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intravenous Phenylephrine Preconditioning of Cardiac Grafts from Non-Heart-Beating Donors
    • In particular, waiting for that additional period of time would make the heart unusable for transplant. The heart is one of the organs for which NHBDs are viewed as a possible source. See, for example, J.T. Cope et al., "Intravenous Phenylephrine Preconditioning of Cardiac Grafts from Non-Heart-Beating Donors," Annals of Thoracic Surgery, 63 (1997): 1664-68. Indeed, in 1993 and 1994, the hearts were removed from 4.7 and 8.5 percent, respectively, of the NHBDs in each year. See IOM Report, supra note 5, at 27. It is curious that supporters of this practice see no inconsistency, on the one hand, in declaring a person dead as the result of the irreversible failure of that person's heart, and, on the other, in successfully using that very heart to replace the malfunctioning heart of another person.
    • (1997) Annals of Thoracic Surgery , vol.63 , pp. 1664-1668
    • Cope, J.T.1
  • 28
    • 0030816313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5
    • In particular, waiting for that additional period of time would make the heart unusable for transplant. The heart is one of the organs for which NHBDs are viewed as a possible source. See, for example, J.T. Cope et al., "Intravenous Phenylephrine Preconditioning of Cardiac Grafts from Non-Heart-Beating Donors," Annals of Thoracic Surgery, 63 (1997): 1664-68. Indeed, in 1993 and 1994, the hearts were removed from 4.7 and 8.5 percent, respectively, of the NHBDs in each year. See IOM Report, supra note 5, at 27. It is curious that supporters of this practice see no inconsistency, on the one hand, in declaring a person dead as the result of the irreversible failure of that person's heart, and, on the other, in successfully using that very heart to replace the malfunctioning heart of another person.
    • IOM Report , pp. 27
  • 29
    • 0002579322 scopus 로고
    • A Statutory Definition of the Standards for Determining Human Death: An Appraisal and a Proposal
    • See A.M. Capron and L.R. Kass, "A Statutory Definition of the Standards for Determining Human Death: An Appraisal and a Proposal," University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 121 (1972): at 89. Oddly, the medical literature is silent with regard to these traditional criteria. Thus, a 1968 article observed that, in a sample of fifty texts of physical diagnosis published within the prior half century, only one - published in 1926 - discussed the methods and techniques for diagnosing death. See J.D. Arnold, T.F. Zimmerman, and D.C. Martin, "Public Attitudes and the Diagnosis of Death," JAMA, 206 (1968): 1949- 54. A more informal survey of the library shelves of Kansas University Medical Center produced a similar result: although the criteria for declaring a patient "brain dead" are frequently discussed, rarely is there a discussion of the more traditional criteria. Indeed, the only text to discuss such criteria made a point of commenting on that fact: "Edwin V. Motto, M.D., a resident on our service, called the authors' attention to the dearth of instructions on this subject in books on diagnosis." E.L. DeGowin and R.L. DeGowin, Bedside Diagnostic Examination (New York: Macmillan, 4th ed., 1981): at 843. It bears noting that the "Death Examination (for Most Patients)" provided in this text involved not just tests for "cardiac activity" and "respiratory activity," but also tests for "neurologic function," such as checking for the "fixed dilated pupils of death." Id.
    • (1972) University of Pennsylvania Law Review , vol.121 , pp. 89
    • Capron, A.M.1    Kass, L.R.2
  • 30
    • 0014430344 scopus 로고
    • Public Attitudes and the Diagnosis of Death
    • See A.M. Capron and L.R. Kass, "A Statutory Definition of the Standards for Determining Human Death: An Appraisal and a Proposal," University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 121 (1972): at 89. Oddly, the medical literature is silent with regard to these traditional criteria. Thus, a 1968 article observed that, in a sample of fifty texts of physical diagnosis published within the prior half century, only one - published in 1926 -discussed the methods and techniques for diagnosing death. See J.D. Arnold, T.F. Zimmerman, and D.C. Martin, "Public Attitudes and the Diagnosis of Death," JAMA, 206 (1968): 1949-54. A more informal survey of the library shelves of Kansas University Medical Center produced a similar result: although the criteria for declaring a patient "brain dead" are frequently discussed, rarely is there a discussion of the more traditional criteria. Indeed, the only text to discuss such criteria made a point of commenting on that fact: "Edwin V. Motto, M.D., a resident on our service, called the authors' attention to the dearth of instructions on this subject in books on diagnosis." E.L. DeGowin and R.L. DeGowin, Bedside Diagnostic Examination (New York: Macmillan, 4th ed., 1981): at 843. It bears noting that the "Death Examination (for Most Patients)" provided in this text involved not just tests for "cardiac activity" and "respiratory activity," but also tests for "neurologic function," such as checking for the "fixed dilated pupils of death." Id.
    • (1968) JAMA , vol.206 , pp. 1949-1954
    • Arnold, J.D.1    Zimmerman, T.F.2    Martin, D.C.3
  • 31
    • 0004325353 scopus 로고
    • New York: Macmillan, 4th ed.
    • See A.M. Capron and L.R. Kass, "A Statutory Definition of the Standards for Determining Human Death: An Appraisal and a Proposal," University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 121 (1972): at 89. Oddly, the medical literature is silent with regard to these traditional criteria. Thus, a 1968 article observed that, in a sample of fifty texts of physical diagnosis published within the prior half century, only one - published in 1926 - discussed the methods and techniques for diagnosing death. See J.D. Arnold, T.F. Zimmerman, and D.C. Martin, "Public Attitudes and the Diagnosis of Death," JAMA, 206 (1968): 1949- 54. A more informal survey of the library shelves of Kansas University Medical Center produced a similar result: although the criteria for declaring a patient "brain dead" are frequently discussed, rarely is there a discussion of the more traditional criteria. Indeed, the only text to discuss such criteria made a point of commenting on that fact: "Edwin V. Motto, M.D., a resident on our service, called the authors' attention to the dearth of instructions on this subject in books on diagnosis." E.L. DeGowin and R.L. DeGowin, Bedside Diagnostic Examination (New York: Macmillan, 4th ed., 1981): at 843. It bears noting that the "Death Examination (for Most Patients)" provided in this text involved not just tests for "cardiac activity" and "respiratory activity," but also tests for "neurologic function," such as checking for the "fixed dilated pupils of death." Id.
    • (1981) Bedside Diagnostic Examination , pp. 843
    • DeGowin, E.L.1    DeGowin, R.L.2
  • 32
    • 0038266098 scopus 로고
    • Tucson: Galen Press, (discussing various tests for death, including making surgical incisions into bodies, touching the bodies with hot irons, and putting devices in coffins for signaling whether the body begins to move); and President's Commission, supra note 12, at 13-15
    • See, for example, K. V. Iserson, Death to Dust: What Happens to Dead Bodies? (Tucson: Galen Press, 1994): 34-38 (discussing various tests for death, including making surgical incisions into bodies, touching the bodies with hot irons, and putting devices in coffins for signaling whether the body begins to move); and President's Commission, supra note 12, at 13-15.
    • (1994) Death to Dust: What Happens to Dead Bodies? , pp. 34-38
    • Iserson, K.V.1
  • 33
    • 0014403727 scopus 로고
    • A Definition of Irreversible Coma
    • See Report of the Ad Hoc Committee of the Harvard Medical School to Examine the Definition of Brain Death, "A Definition of Irreversible Coma," JAMA, 205 (1968): 337-40.
    • (1968) JAMA , vol.205 , pp. 337-340
  • 34
    • 0014957006 scopus 로고
    • Definitions of 'Life' and 'Death' for Medical Science and Practice
    • Beecher did not confine his comments to those declared dead under the newly proposed criteria for brain death
    • Henry K. Beecher, the chair of the Ad Hoc Committee, was even more explicit in observing that whether our ancestors recognized the special role of the brain, "there is [now] a need to move death to the site of an individual's consciousness." H.K. Beecher, "Definitions of 'Life' and 'Death' for Medical Science and Practice," Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 169 (1969): at 474. Beecher did not confine his comments to those declared dead under the newly proposed criteria for brain death.
    • (1969) Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences , vol.169 , pp. 474
    • Beecher, H.K.1
  • 35
    • 0346476814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Report of the Ad Hoc Committee, supra note 22, at 339
    • See Report of the Ad Hoc Committee, supra note 22, at 339.
  • 36
    • 0346476812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, President's Commission, supra note 12, at 62-63
    • See, for example, President's Commission, supra note 12, at 62-63.
  • 37
    • 0346476810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Capron and Kass, supra note 20, at 87
    • See Capron and Kass, supra note 20, at 87.
  • 38
    • 0346476813 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 109-10. As Alexander Capron and Leon Kass further note, One hopes that the form the statute takes does not reflect a conclusion on the part of the Kansas legislature that death occurs at two distinct points during the process of dying. Yet this inference can be derived from the [Kansas Act], leaving open the prospect "that X at a certain stage in the process of dying can be pronounced dead, whereas Y, having arrived at the same point, is not said to be dead."
  • 39
    • 0347107023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 110. It is interesting that Capron and Kass were presumably worried that a person might be declared dead sooner under the brain death definition than under the cardiopulmonary definition, no doubt as a result of the pressures created by the need for transplantable organs. Somewhat paradoxically, the NHBD controversy has created the same issue, but flipped: the desire to get organs has created a reading of the cardiopulmonary definition that would allegedly allow these persons to be declared dead at a time when they clearly could not be declared dead under the brain death definition.
  • 40
    • 0347737532 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 112 (emphasis added)
    • Id. at 112 (emphasis added).
  • 41
    • 0345845955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 113-14
    • Id. at 113-14.
  • 43
    • 0347107024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The director of the President's Commission was an active participant in the drafting of what would become the Uniform Definition of Death Act (UDDA). See President's Commission, supra note 12, at 9.
  • 44
    • 0346476811 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 1, 57
    • Id. at 1, 57.
  • 45
    • 0345845952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although the President's Commission begins the chapter discussing these issues with the observation that "these views all yield interpretations consistent with the recommended statute," id. at 31, subsequent discussion in the report makes it very clear that the Commission rejected the higher brain and nonbrain views. With regard to the view that it is the destruction of the higher brain - the portions of the brain that deal with consciousness, thought, and feelings - that determines whether a person is dead, the Commission noted that "the adoption of a higher brain 'definition' would depart radically from the traditional standards." Id. at 40-41. And with regard to the nonbrain view of death, the Commission very explicitly noted that the "concept of death based upon the flow of bodily fluids cannot be completely reconciled with the proposed statute." Id. at 42.
  • 46
    • 0346476809 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. at 36. It is also the case that, among philosophers, there is "nearly a consensus" that one must look to brain function to determine death. See Furrow et al., supra note 30, at 1037.
  • 47
    • 0347107021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • President's Commission, supra note 12, at 37
    • President's Commission, supra note 12, at 37.
  • 48
    • 0347737528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 34
    • Id. at 34.
  • 49
    • 0347737527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Id. It is noteworthy that IOM's report fails to comment on whether any evidence suggests that a person would always lack pupillary light responses at the point in time five minutes after the heart has stopped beating. As the President's Commission notes, the examination of such pupillary responses has classically been a routine test for death under the traditional cardiopulmonary criteria, thus demonstrating that even those criteria did not fully ignore the functioning of the brain. See DeGowin and DeGowin, supra note 20, at 843.
  • 50
    • 0347107022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • President's Commission, supra note 12, at 37 (emphasis added)
    • President's Commission, supra note 12, at 37 (emphasis added).
  • 51
    • 0345845953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The President's Commission also considered it important that death not be viewed "as a process," but as a specific event that "separates the process of dying from the process of disintegration." Id. at 77. Thus, at the time a person would be declared dead, he would be declared dead because his status is at that time consistent with the concept of death being adopted, and not because he might merely in the near future have the desired status, whether or not his progression to that status was inevitable. In other words, "dying" is different from "being dead." Presumably, if the status of the person's brain was the relevant concept, then the condition of that brain - for example, being irreversibly nonfunctional - should exist at the time death is declared.
  • 52
    • 0347737529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 41
    • Id. at 41.
  • 53
    • 0027635952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Impending Collapse of the Whole-Brain Definition of Death
    • ("The President's Commission ... made clear, however, that circulatory and respiratory function loss are important only as indirect indicators that the brain has been permanently destroyed." (emphasis added));
    • See, for example, R.M. Veatch, "The Impending Collapse of the Whole-Brain Definition of Death," Hastings Center Report, 23, no. 4 (1993): at 18 ("The President's Commission ... made clear, however, that circulatory and respiratory function loss are important only as indirect indicators that the brain has been permanently destroyed." (emphasis added)); and J.D. Arras and B. Steinbock, eds., Ethical Issues in Modern Medicine (Mountain View: Mayfield, 4th ed., 1997): at 130 (making similar comments in discussion of the writings of Karen Gervais).
    • (1993) Hastings Center Report , vol.23 , Issue.4 , pp. 18
    • Veatch, R.M.1
  • 54
    • 0027635952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mountain View: Mayfield, 4th ed., (making similar comments in discussion of the writings of Karen Gervais)
    • See, for example, R.M. Veatch, "The Impending Collapse of the Whole-Brain Definition of Death," Hastings Center Report, 23, no. 4 (1993): at 18 ("The President's Commission ... made clear, however, that circulatory and respiratory function loss are important only as indirect indicators that the brain has been permanently destroyed." (emphasis added)); and J.D. Arras and B. Steinbock, eds., Ethical Issues in Modern Medicine (Mountain View: Mayfield, 4th ed., 1997): at 130 (making similar comments in discussion of the writings of Karen Gervais).
    • (1997) Ethical Issues in Modern Medicine , pp. 130
    • Arras, J.D.1    Steinbock, B.2
  • 55
    • 0346476808 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 15, at 152-53
    • IOM's report contains several references to articles generated by a conference that examined in detail the University of Pittsburgh NHBD protocol. A number of those articles raised issues discussed herein. See, for example, Cole, supra note 15, at 152-53; T. Tomlinson, "The Irreversibility of Death: A Reply to Cole," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3 (1993): 163- 64; and R.M. Veatch, "Consent for Perfusion and Other Dilemmas with Organ Procurement from Non-Heart-Beating Cadavers," in R.M. Arnold et al., supra note 8, at 198. Although the number of pages devoted to this issue are relatively few, it is highlighted in the conference's introductory essay. See R.M. Arnold and S.J. Youngner, "Back to the Future: Obtaining Organs from Non-Heart Beating Cadavers," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3 (1993): at 106-07: Cole, Tomlinson, and Lynn all note that the Pittsburgh protocol's sole emphasis on cardiopulmonary criteria for death poses unexpected questions regarding the concept of death. When the "brain death" criteria were introduced, its supporters argued it did not entail a new conception of death, but simply supplemented the traditional cardiopulmonary criteria.... According to this argument, both criteria serve as clinical tests for a unitary definition of death - the loss of integrative functioning of the whole brain. However, there are no clear empirical data proving that a patient who meets the Pittsburgh protocol's criteria for cardiopulmonary death, two minutes of pulselessness, also meets neurologic criteria for death, irreversible loss of all brain function. The importance of this issue has clearly increased in the context of IOM's report. Although the discussants of the Pittsburgh protocol could assume empirical data may ultimately resolve whether there is irreversible loss of all brain function at the time death is declared, IOM acknowledges it is unlikely that there is such loss of function at the time it approves for the declaration of death, and acknowledges it does not even care about the existence of such function. See IOM Report, supra note 5, at 59.
    • Cole1
  • 56
    • 0027621347 scopus 로고
    • The Irreversibility of Death: A Reply to Cole
    • IOM's report contains several references to articles generated by a conference that examined in detail the University of Pittsburgh NHBD protocol. A number of those articles raised issues discussed herein. See, for example, Cole, supra note 15, at 152-53; T. Tomlinson, "The Irreversibility of Death: A Reply to Cole," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3 (1993): 163-64; and R.M. Veatch, "Consent for Perfusion and Other Dilemmas with Organ Procurement from Non-Heart-Beating Cadavers," in R.M. Arnold et al., supra note 8, at 198. Although the number of pages devoted to this issue are relatively few, it is highlighted in the conference's introductory essay. See R.M. Arnold and S.J. Youngner, "Back to the Future: Obtaining Organs from Non-Heart Beating Cadavers," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3 (1993): at 106-07: Cole, Tomlinson, and Lynn all note that the Pittsburgh protocol's sole emphasis on cardiopulmonary criteria for death poses unexpected questions regarding the concept of death. When the "brain death" criteria were introduced, its supporters argued it did not entail a new conception of death, but simply supplemented the traditional cardiopulmonary criteria.... According to this argument, both criteria serve as clinical tests for a unitary definition of death - the loss of integrative functioning of the whole brain. However, there are no clear empirical data proving that a patient who meets the Pittsburgh protocol's criteria for cardiopulmonary death, two minutes of pulselessness, also meets neurologic criteria for death, irreversible loss of all brain function. The importance of this issue has clearly increased in the context of IOM's report. Although the discussants of the Pittsburgh protocol could assume empirical data may ultimately resolve whether there is irreversible loss of all brain function at the time death is declared, IOM acknowledges it is unlikely that there is such loss of function at the time it approves for the declaration of death, and acknowledges it does not even care about the existence of such function. See IOM Report, supra note 5, at 59.
    • (1993) Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal , vol.3 , pp. 163-164
    • Tomlinson, T.1
  • 57
    • 4243256340 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • R.M. Arnold et al., supra note 8, at 198
    • IOM's report contains several references to articles generated by a conference that examined in detail the University of Pittsburgh NHBD protocol. A number of those articles raised issues discussed herein. See, for example, Cole, supra note 15, at 152-53; T. Tomlinson, "The Irreversibility of Death: A Reply to Cole," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3 (1993): 163- 64; and R.M. Veatch, "Consent for Perfusion and Other Dilemmas with Organ Procurement from Non-Heart-Beating Cadavers," in R.M. Arnold et al., supra note 8, at 198. Although the number of pages devoted to this issue are relatively few, it is highlighted in the conference's introductory essay. See R.M. Arnold and S.J. Youngner, "Back to the Future: Obtaining Organs from Non-Heart Beating Cadavers," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3 (1993): at 106-07: Cole, Tomlinson, and Lynn all note that the Pittsburgh protocol's sole emphasis on cardiopulmonary criteria for death poses unexpected questions regarding the concept of death. When the "brain death" criteria were introduced, its supporters argued it did not entail a new conception of death, but simply supplemented the traditional cardiopulmonary criteria.... According to this argument, both criteria serve as clinical tests for a unitary definition of death - the loss of integrative functioning of the whole brain. However, there are no clear empirical data proving that a patient who meets the Pittsburgh protocol's criteria for cardiopulmonary death, two minutes of pulselessness, also meets neurologic criteria for death, irreversible loss of all brain function. The importance of this issue has clearly increased in the context of IOM's report. Although the discussants of the Pittsburgh protocol could assume empirical data may ultimately resolve whether there is irreversible loss of all brain function at the time death is declared, IOM acknowledges it is unlikely that there is such loss of function at the time it approves for the declaration of death, and acknowledges it does not even care about the existence of such function. See IOM Report, supra note 5, at 59.
    • Consent for Perfusion and Other Dilemmas with Organ Procurement from Non-Heart-Beating Cadavers
    • Veatch, R.M.1
  • 58
    • 0027621138 scopus 로고
    • Back to the Future: Obtaining Organs from Non-Heart Beating Cadavers
    • IOM's report contains several references to articles generated by a conference that examined in detail the University of Pittsburgh NHBD protocol. A number of those articles raised issues discussed herein. See, for example, Cole, supra note 15, at 152-53; T. Tomlinson, "The Irreversibility of Death: A Reply to Cole," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3 (1993): 163- 64; and R.M. Veatch, "Consent for Perfusion and Other Dilemmas with Organ Procurement from Non-Heart-Beating Cadavers," in R.M. Arnold et al., supra note 8, at 198. Although the number of pages devoted to this issue are relatively few, it is highlighted in the conference's introductory essay. See R.M. Arnold and S.J. Youngner, "Back to the Future: Obtaining Organs from Non-Heart Beating Cadavers," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3 (1993): at 106-07: Cole, Tomlinson, and Lynn all note that the Pittsburgh protocol's sole emphasis on cardiopulmonary criteria for death poses unexpected questions regarding the concept of death. When the "brain death" criteria were introduced, its supporters argued it did not entail a new conception of death, but simply supplemented the traditional cardiopulmonary criteria.... According to this argument, both criteria serve as clinical tests for a unitary definition of death -the loss of integrative functioning of the whole brain. However, there are no clear empirical data proving that a patient who meets the Pittsburgh protocol's criteria for cardiopulmonary death, two minutes of pulselessness, also meets neurologic criteria for death, irreversible loss of all brain function. The importance of this issue has clearly increased in the context of IOM's report. Although the discussants of the Pittsburgh protocol could assume empirical data may ultimately resolve whether there is irreversible loss of all brain function at the time death is declared, IOM acknowledges it is unlikely that there is such loss of function at the time it approves for the declaration of death, and acknowledges it does not even care about the existence of such function. See IOM Report, supra note 5, at 59.
    • (1993) Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal , vol.3 , pp. 106-107
    • Arnold, R.M.1    Youngner, S.J.2
  • 59
    • 0018085984 scopus 로고
    • Brain Death
    • Editorial
    • See W.H. Sweet, Editorial, "Brain Death," N. Engl. J. Med., 299 (1978): 410-12. Although the editorial does not specifically refer to the UDDA, the editorial board's interpretation of the cardiopulmonary criteria is provided in a brief two-sentence paragraph: "Indeed, it is clear that a person is not dead unless his brain is dead. The time-honored criteria of stoppage of the heartbeat and circulation are indicative of death only when they persist long enough for the brain to die." Id. at 410.
    • (1978) N. Engl. J. Med. , vol.299 , pp. 410-412
    • Sweet, W.H.1
  • 60
    • 0346476807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 30, at 1032-38
    • See Furrow et al., supra note 30, at 1032-38.
    • Furrow1
  • 61
    • 0345845950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The use of the word "prolonged" in this statute presumably highlights the need to wait long enough so that one can be confident that brain function has irreversibly ended.
  • 62
    • 0020095790 scopus 로고
    • Defining Death in Theory and Practice
    • President's Commission, supra note 12, at 74. The President's Commission was referring to a statute proposed by a Canadian law reform commission. For subsequent discussion of this Canadian proposal, see J.L. Bernat, C.M. Culver, and B. Gert, "Defining Death in Theory and Practice," Hastings Center Report, 12, no. 1 (1982): 5-9.
    • (1982) Hastings Center Report , vol.12 , Issue.1 , pp. 5-9
    • Bernat, J.L.1    Culver, C.M.2    Gert, B.3
  • 63
    • 0018271743 scopus 로고
    • Legal Definition of Death
    • Capron would appear to agree with this characterization of the dispute, because he had previously discussed exactly this issue under the heading "Disagreements Over Form," as opposed to "Disagreements Over Substance," which related to whether the entire brain, or just the "higher brain centers," had to be destroyed in order for a person to be declared dead. See A.M. Capron, "Legal Definition of Death," Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 315 (1978): at 354-55.
    • (1978) Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences , vol.315 , pp. 354-355
    • Capron, A.M.1
  • 64
    • 0347107011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 30, at 1037 (emphasis added)
    • Furrow et al., supra note 30, at 1037 (emphasis added).
    • Furrow1
  • 65
    • 0242294690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Westbury: Foundation Press, 2nd ed., Capron, who played a major role in the series of events that led to the UDDA, is one of the five co-authors of this text
    • See J. Areen et al., Law, Science and Medicine (Westbury: Foundation Press, 2nd ed., 1996). Capron, who played a major role in the series of events that led to the UDDA, is one of the five co-authors of this text.
    • (1996) Law, Science and Medicine
    • Areen, J.1
  • 67
    • 0346476805 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The apparent acceptability of deceiving the public in order to increase organ donation was affirmed by the comments I received from an anonymous reviewer: The author insists that "ethical behavior demands that we not shade the truth...." If the author had found a way to facilitate the use of non-heart-beating donors without shading the truth, the paper would constitute a substantial step forward. For the reasons given, I do not believe that the author accomplishes this. As stated, I do agree that the IOM report shades the truth. What is to be done?... In the end, we would have more candor, but organs would be denied to desperately ill patients.... The IOM is not alone in wrestling with this moral issue. Peer Review, at 3 (emphasis added) (on file with author).
  • 68
    • 0347737512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See President's Commission, supra note 12
    • See President's Commission, supra note 12.
  • 69
    • 0347737520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 2
    • See Cho et al., supra note 2.
    • Cho1
  • 70
    • 0031442160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Influence of Warm Ischemia Time on Initial Graft Function in Human Liver Transplantation
    • One recent report, for example, concludes that the time period during which the liver receives no blood flow prior to the beginning of the preservation process should not exceed ninety minutes. See K.-P. Platz et al., "Influence of Warm Ischemia Time on Initial Graft Function in Human Liver Transplantation," Transplantation Proceedings, 29 (1997): 3458-59. One can readily contemplate that improved techniques will eventually shave at least ten minutes off a period of that length.
    • (1997) Transplantation Proceedings , vol.29 , pp. 3458-3459
    • Platz, K.-P.1
  • 71
    • 0347107774 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at 3
    • IOM Report, supra note 5, at 3.
    • IOM Report
  • 72
    • 0345845951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 8
    • Id. at 8.
  • 73
    • 0347737521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See President's Commission, supra note 12. Under the interpretation of the UDDA I recommend, the person's entire brain would be irreversibly nonfunctional after such a period, thus allowing death to be declared even under clause (1) of the Act.
  • 74
    • 0346476801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This statement would, of course, require validation, presumably initially by appropriate studies in animals. Nonetheless, basic principles of physiology would appear to suggest that once blood flow has stopped, thus depriving all of the person's brain cells from not only the supply of oxygen, but also from the effects of hormones and other chemical factors that might somehow influence their viability, the removal of the other organs is unlikely to influence substantially negatively the condition of the now-dying brain cells. It should be assumed that appropriate anesthesia has been given to the patient, so that no pain is experienced during the organ removal, thus eliminating pain signals as a stress factor. Note that under this proposal, giving anesthesia is perfectly acceptable, as compared with the protocol recommended by IOM, wherein under exactly the same conditions, the patient would have already been declared dead, and thus presumably never need anesthesia. See, for example, Veatch, supra note 42, at 198 ("In fact, much of the literature advocating such death pronouncements really does not even present firm evidence that the patient is unconscious.").
  • 75
    • 0027620181 scopus 로고
    • The Dead Donor Rule: Should We Stretch It, Bend It, or Abandon It?
    • These arguments are similar to those made by advocates for the strict version of the dead donor rule, under which organs should not be removed from a living person, whether or not the removal causes or hastens the person's death. See R.M. Arnold and S.J. Youngner, "The Dead Donor Rule: Should We Stretch It, Bend It, or Abandon It?," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 3 (1993): at 265.
    • (1993) Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal , vol.3 , pp. 265
    • Arnold, R.M.1    Youngner, S.J.2
  • 76
    • 0346476806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Even this argument loses much of its force under IOM's interpretation of irreversibiliry, because the major element of that determination is the patient's intent that no actions be taken to reverse their condition. See supra note 14 and accompanying text. Thus, the irreversibility is largely illusory, and the fear of doctors hastening death to get organs would still exist.
  • 77
    • 0347107774 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at 24
    • See IOM Report, supra note 5, at 24.
    • IOM Report
  • 78
    • 0347737522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 73
    • Id. at 73.
  • 79
    • 0345845948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 49
    • Id. at 49.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.