메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 17, Issue 4, 1997, Pages 589-608

Tort law and internalization: The gap between private loss and social cost

(1)  Gilead, Israel a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0031537331     PISSN: 01448188     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1016/S0144-8188(97)00038-0     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (23)

References (148)
  • 1
    • 0002449630 scopus 로고
    • The concept of external economics
    • 1 The concept of externalities is "one of the most elusive in economic literature." T. Scitovsky, "The Concept of External Economics," 62 Journal of Political Economy 143 (1954), reprinted in Externalities: Theoretical Dimensions of Political Economy, eds. R. J. Staaf and F. X. Tannian, Dunellen, New York, 1973, p. 77. This concept can be defined in various ways. See W. J. Baumol and W. E. Oates, The Theory of Environmental Policy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2d ed. 1988) pp. 15-18. For the purposes of this article, externality may be defined as "a cost or benefit that the voluntary action of one or more people impose or confer on a third party without their consent." See R. Gooter and T. Ulen, Law and Economics (New York: Harper Collins, 1988), p. 45. According to Baumol and Oates, p. 17, "[an] externality is present whenever some individual's (say A's) utility or production relationships include real (that is, nonmonetary) variables, whose values are chosen by others (persons, corporations, governments) without particular attention to the effects on A's welfare." Externalities, according to this definition, are the outcome of interdependencies between different utility and production functions. The difference between the two definitions originates in the distinction between "technological" externalities and "pecuniary" externalities. Technological externalities affect the welfare of others directly through their production or utility functions. Pecuniary externalities affect the welfare of others indirectly, usually through price and cost changes transmitted via the market, without affecting utility or production functions (see Baumol and Oates, pp. 29-31). Baumol and Oate's definition refers only to technological externalities. It excludes pecuniary externalities on the assumption that such externalities do not produce inefficiencies. In contrast, the former definition covers pecuniary externalities as well. In this article, it is assumed that pecuniary externalities may also produce inefficiencies, although in a very limited context. See below, note 35.
    • (1954) 62 Journal of Political Economy , vol.143
    • Scitovsky, T.1
  • 2
    • 84950833495 scopus 로고
    • Dunellen, New York
    • 1 The concept of externalities is "one of the most elusive in economic literature." T. Scitovsky, "The Concept of External Economics," 62 Journal of Political Economy 143 (1954), reprinted in Externalities: Theoretical Dimensions of Political Economy, eds. R. J. Staaf and F. X. Tannian, Dunellen, New York, 1973, p. 77. This concept can be defined in various ways. See W. J. Baumol and W. E. Oates, The Theory of Environmental Policy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2d ed. 1988) pp. 15-18. For the purposes of this article, externality may be defined as "a cost or benefit that the voluntary action of one or more people impose or confer on a third party without their consent." See R. Gooter and T. Ulen, Law and Economics (New York: Harper Collins, 1988), p. 45. According to Baumol and Oates, p. 17, "[an] externality is present whenever some individual's (say A's) utility or production relationships include real (that is, nonmonetary) variables, whose values are chosen by others (persons, corporations, governments) without particular attention to the effects on A's welfare." Externalities, according to this definition, are the outcome of interdependencies between different utility and production functions. The difference between the two definitions originates in the distinction between "technological" externalities and "pecuniary" externalities. Technological externalities affect the welfare of others directly through their production or utility functions. Pecuniary externalities affect the welfare of others indirectly, usually through price and cost changes transmitted via the market, without affecting utility or production functions (see Baumol and Oates, pp. 29-31). Baumol and Oate's definition refers only to technological externalities. It excludes pecuniary externalities on the assumption that such externalities do not produce inefficiencies. In contrast, the former definition covers pecuniary externalities as well. In this article, it is assumed that pecuniary externalities may also produce inefficiencies, although in a very limited context. See below, note 35.
    • (1973) Externalities: Theoretical Dimensions of Political Economy , pp. 77
    • Staaf, R.J.1    Tannian, F.X.2
  • 3
    • 0003860506 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2d ed.
    • 1 The concept of externalities is "one of the most elusive in economic literature." T. Scitovsky, "The Concept of External Economics," 62 Journal of Political Economy 143 (1954), reprinted in Externalities: Theoretical Dimensions of Political Economy, eds. R. J. Staaf and F. X. Tannian, Dunellen, New York, 1973, p. 77. This concept can be defined in various ways. See W. J. Baumol and W. E. Oates, The Theory of Environmental Policy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2d ed. 1988) pp. 15-18. For the purposes of this article, externality may be defined as "a cost or benefit that the voluntary action of one or more people impose or confer on a third party without their consent." See R. Gooter and T. Ulen, Law and Economics (New York: Harper Collins, 1988), p. 45. According to Baumol and Oates, p. 17, "[an] externality is present whenever some individual's (say A's) utility or production relationships include real (that is, nonmonetary) variables, whose values are chosen by others (persons, corporations, governments) without particular attention to the effects on A's welfare." Externalities, according to this definition, are the outcome of interdependencies between different utility and production functions. The difference between the two definitions originates in the distinction between "technological" externalities and "pecuniary" externalities. Technological externalities affect the welfare of others directly through their production or utility functions. Pecuniary externalities affect the welfare of others indirectly, usually through price and cost changes transmitted via the market, without affecting utility or production functions (see Baumol and Oates, pp. 29-31). Baumol and Oate's definition refers only to technological externalities. It excludes pecuniary externalities on the assumption that such externalities do not produce inefficiencies. In contrast, the former definition covers pecuniary externalities as well. In this article, it is assumed that pecuniary externalities may also produce inefficiencies, although in a very limited context. See below, note 35.
    • (1988) The Theory of Environmental Policy , pp. 15-18
    • Baumol, W.J.1    Oates, W.E.2
  • 4
    • 0003732343 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harper Collins
    • 1 The concept of externalities is "one of the most elusive in economic literature." T. Scitovsky, "The Concept of External Economics," 62 Journal of Political Economy 143 (1954), reprinted in Externalities: Theoretical Dimensions of Political Economy, eds. R. J. Staaf and F. X. Tannian, Dunellen, New York, 1973, p. 77. This concept can be defined in various ways. See W. J. Baumol and W. E. Oates, The Theory of Environmental Policy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2d ed. 1988) pp. 15-18. For the purposes of this article, externality may be defined as "a cost or benefit that the voluntary action of one or more people impose or confer on a third party without their consent." See R. Gooter and T. Ulen, Law and Economics (New York: Harper Collins, 1988), p. 45. According to Baumol and Oates, p. 17, "[an] externality is present whenever some individual's (say A's) utility or production relationships include real (that is, nonmonetary) variables, whose values are chosen by others (persons, corporations, governments) without particular attention to the effects on A's welfare." Externalities, according to this definition, are the outcome of interdependencies between different utility and production functions. The difference between the two definitions originates in the distinction between "technological" externalities and "pecuniary" externalities. Technological externalities affect the welfare of others directly through their production or utility functions. Pecuniary externalities affect the welfare of others indirectly, usually through price and cost changes transmitted via the market, without affecting utility or production functions (see Baumol and Oates, pp. 29-31). Baumol and Oate's definition refers only to technological externalities. It excludes pecuniary externalities on the assumption that such externalities do not produce inefficiencies. In contrast, the former definition covers pecuniary externalities as well. In this article, it is assumed that pecuniary externalities may also produce inefficiencies, although in a very limited context. See below, note 35.
    • (1988) Law and Economics , pp. 45
    • Gooter, R.1    Ulen, T.2
  • 5
    • 0010960509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The term "efficiency" is used to indicate an increase in aggregate welfare. As to the different types of efficiency see below, note 35. "Welfare" is used as a synonym for "utility" and "wealth," and it is measured in money terms, assuming risk neutrality
    • 2 The term "efficiency" is used to indicate an increase in aggregate welfare. As to the different types of efficiency see below, note 35. "Welfare" is used as a synonym for "utility" and "wealth," and it is measured in money terms, assuming risk neutrality.
  • 6
    • 0000843939 scopus 로고
    • Externality
    • note 29
    • 3 It should be noted that externalities do not necessarily produce inefficiencies, but may do so. It is quite possible for externalities to exist in an efficient state, and in such cases there is no need to internalize. See J. Buchanan and W. C. Stubblebine, "Externality," note 29 Economica 371 (1962) reprinted in Externalities, above note 1, 277, p. 286, and Baumol and Oates, above note 1, p. 18.
    • (1962) Economica , vol.371
    • Buchanan, J.1    Stubblebine, W.C.2
  • 7
    • 0010961493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 1, 277, and Baumol and Oates, above note 1, p. 18
    • 3 It should be noted that externalities do not necessarily produce inefficiencies, but may do so. It is quite possible for externalities to exist in an efficient state, and in such cases there is no need to internalize. See J. Buchanan and W. C. Stubblebine, "Externality," note 29 Economica 371 (1962) reprinted in Externalities, above note 1, 277, p. 286, and Baumol and Oates, above note 1, p. 18.
    • Externalities , pp. 286
  • 8
    • 0004082608 scopus 로고
    • 4 Posner sees himself as a follower of Coase. See W. M. Landes and R. A. Posner, The Economic Structure of Tort Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987), pp. 7-8. Coase, on the other hand, has recently remarked, rather ambiguously, "Posner . . . picked up what I had said about the judges and ran with it. I have never attempted to follow him. For one thing, he runs much faster than I do. He also runs in a somewhat different direction." R. H. Coase, "Law and Economics at Chicago," 36 Journal of Law and Economics 239 (1993) p. 251. The discrepancy between them contradicts the prevailing view claiming that Coase was followed by lawyers rather than by economists. See S. Schwab, "Coase defends Coase: Why Lawyers Listen and Economists Do Not," 87 Michigan Law Review 1171 (1989), p. 1191.
    • (1987) The Economic Structure of Tort Law , pp. 7-8
    • Landes, W.M.1    Posner, R.A.2
  • 9
    • 0010960510 scopus 로고
    • Law and economics at Chicago
    • 4 Posner sees himself as a follower of Coase. See W. M. Landes and R. A. Posner, The Economic Structure of Tort Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987), pp. 7-8. Coase, on the other hand, has recently remarked, rather ambiguously, "Posner . . . picked up what I had said about the judges and ran with it. I have never attempted to follow him. For one thing, he runs much faster than I do. He also runs in a somewhat different direction." R. H. Coase, "Law and Economics at Chicago," 36 Journal of Law and Economics 239 (1993) p. 251. The discrepancy between them contradicts the prevailing view claiming that Coase was followed by lawyers rather than by economists. See S. Schwab, "Coase defends Coase: Why Lawyers Listen and Economists Do Not," 87 Michigan Law Review 1171 (1989), p. 1191.
    • (1993) 36 Journal of Law and Economics , vol.239 , pp. 251
    • Coase, R.H.1
  • 10
    • 0005165090 scopus 로고
    • Coase defends Coase: Why lawyers listen and economists do not
    • 4 Posner sees himself as a follower of Coase. See W. M. Landes and R. A. Posner, The Economic Structure of Tort Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987), pp. 7-8. Coase, on the other hand, has recently remarked, rather ambiguously, "Posner . . . picked up what I had said about the judges and ran with it. I have never attempted to follow him. For one thing, he runs much faster than I do. He also runs in a somewhat different direction." R. H. Coase, "Law and Economics at Chicago," 36 Journal of Law and Economics 239 (1993) p. 251. The discrepancy between them contradicts the prevailing view claiming that Coase was followed by lawyers rather than by economists. See S. Schwab, "Coase defends Coase: Why Lawyers Listen and Economists Do Not," 87 Michigan Law Review 1171 (1989), p. 1191.
    • (1989) 87 Michigan Law Review , vol.1171 , pp. 1191
    • Schwab, S.1
  • 11
    • 0010960320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The former, however, may influence the latter indirectly, through the operation of liability rules. See below, first part of Section III
    • 5 The former, however, may influence the latter indirectly, through the operation of liability rules. See below, first part of Section III.
  • 12
    • 21844521574 scopus 로고
    • Reality in the economic analysis of tort law: Does tort law really deter?
    • the author argues that, although tort law provides a significant amount of deterrence, its actual impact on the parties' behavior is less than economists tend to predict
    • 6 In G. T. Schwartz, "Reality in the Economic Analysis of Tort Law: Does Tort Law Really Deter?" 42 UCLA Law Review 379 (1994), pp. 425-426, the author argues that, although tort law provides a significant amount of deterrence, its actual impact on the parties' behavior is less than economists tend to predict.
    • (1994) 42 UCLA Law Review , vol.379 , pp. 425-426
    • Schwartz, G.T.1
  • 13
    • 0002071502 scopus 로고
    • The problem of social cost
    • Coase later clarified, however, that the assumption of zero transaction costs is unrealistic, and that he had used the Coase Theorem to illuminate the fallacies of an economic analysis that does factor in transaction costs
    • 7 According to the Coase Theorem, in the absence of transaction costs, externalities are internalized through a bargaining process between victims and injurers, and there is no need for liability rules. See R. H. Coase "The Problem of Social Cost," Journal of Law and Economics 1 (1960). Coase later clarified, however, that the assumption of zero transaction costs is unrealistic, and that he had used the Coase Theorem to illuminate the fallacies of an economic analysis that does factor in transaction costs. See R. H. Coase, The Firm, the Market, and the Law (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988) pp. 174-175.
    • (1960) Journal of Law and Economics , vol.1
    • Coase, R.H.1
  • 14
    • 0003802548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • 7 According to the Coase Theorem, in the absence of transaction costs, externalities are internalized through a bargaining process between victims and injurers, and there is no need for liability rules. See R. H. Coase "The Problem of Social Cost," Journal of Law and Economics 1 (1960). Coase later clarified, however, that the assumption of zero transaction costs is unrealistic, and that he had used the Coase Theorem to illuminate the fallacies of an economic analysis that does factor in transaction costs. See R. H. Coase, The Firm, the Market, and the Law (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988) pp. 174-175.
    • (1988) The Firm, the Market, and the Law , pp. 174-175
    • Coase, R.H.1
  • 15
    • 0010988214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The term "loss mitigation" usually refers only to the reduction of loss that has already been inflicted. Here we shall use it in a broader sense, to include prevention of loss before its infliction
    • 8 The term "loss mitigation" usually refers only to the reduction of loss that has already been inflicted. Here we shall use it in a broader sense, to include prevention of loss before its infliction.
  • 16
    • 0004320812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the railroad's sparks example, the actual private loss of revenues on the abandoned cultivation can be mitigated by revenues from alternative cultivation or alternative use of the released inputs. in note 7 above, The externalized social cost is the loss that farmers would have suffered had they changed their activity. In the pollution example, the actual private loss of the residents can be mitigated by moving to alternative locations or taking other measures against pollution
    • 9 In the railroad's sparks example, the actual private loss of revenues on the abandoned cultivation can be mitigated by revenues from alternative cultivation or alternative use of the released inputs. See Coase, Social Cost (in note 7 above), p. 33. The externalized social cost is the loss that farmers would have suffered had they changed their activity. In the pollution example, the actual private loss of the residents can be mitigated by moving to alternative locations or taking other measures against pollution. Ibid, p. 4.
    • Social Cost , pp. 33
    • Coase1
  • 17
    • 0004320812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in note 7 above
    • 9 In the railroad's sparks example, the actual private loss of revenues on the abandoned cultivation can be mitigated by revenues from alternative cultivation or alternative use of the released inputs. See Coase, Social Cost (in note 7 above), p. 33. The externalized social cost is the loss that farmers would have suffered had they changed their activity. In the pollution example, the actual private loss of the residents can be mitigated by moving to alternative locations or taking other measures against pollution. Ibid, p. 4.
    • Social Cost , pp. 4
  • 18
    • 0011034396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One senses that Coase sees his life's work as an effort to combat the evil of Arthur Pigou. . . ." Schwab, above note 4, p. 1184
    • 10 One senses that Coase sees his life's work as an effort to combat the evil of Arthur Pigou. . . ." Schwab, above note 4, p. 1184.
  • 19
    • 0004320812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 7
    • 11 "A tax system which was confined to a tax on the producer for damage caused would tend to lead to unduly high costs being incurred for the prevention of damage." Coase, Social Cost, above note 7, p. 41. See also Coase, The Firm, the Market, and the Law, above note 7, p. 182.
    • Social Cost , pp. 41
    • Coase1
  • 20
    • 0003802548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 7
    • 11 "A tax system which was confined to a tax on the producer for damage caused would tend to lead to unduly high costs being incurred for the prevention of damage." Coase, Social Cost, above note 7, p. 41. See also Coase, The Firm, the Market, and the Law, above note 7, p. 182.
    • The Firm, the Market, and the Law , pp. 182
    • Coase1
  • 21
    • 0004320812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 7
    • 12 Coase, Social Cost, above note 7, p. 46.
    • Social Cost , pp. 46
    • Coase1
  • 22
    • 0043131535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 13 Ibid, p. 26. On the basis of this criticism Coase develops his laissez-faire message, which he contrasts with the Pigovian tradition of "Intervention by Public Authority," (Coase, The Firm, the Market and the Law, above note 7, pp. 20-27). Recently, it has been argued that Coase misunderstood Pigou or used him as a "straw man," and that "Pigou's view was thus much the same as that of Coase, although he was marginally less skeptical about the merits of state action." A. W. B. Simpson, "Coase v. Pigou Reexamined," 25 Journal of Legal Studies 53 (1996), p. 73. See Coase's reply. Ibid, p. 103, and Simpson's Addendum, Ibid, p. 99.
    • Social Cost , pp. 26
  • 23
    • 0043131535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 7
    • 13 Ibid, p. 26. On the basis of this criticism Coase develops his laissez-faire message, which he contrasts with the Pigovian tradition of "Intervention by Public Authority," (Coase, The Firm, the Market and the Law, above note 7, pp. 20-27). Recently, it has been argued that Coase misunderstood Pigou or used him as a "straw man," and that "Pigou's view was thus much the same as that of Coase, although he was marginally less skeptical about the merits of state action." A. W. B. Simpson, "Coase v. Pigou Reexamined," 25 Journal of Legal Studies 53 (1996), p. 73. See Coase's reply. Ibid, p. 103, and Simpson's Addendum, Ibid, p. 99.
    • The Firm, the Market and the Law , pp. 20-27
    • Coase1
  • 24
    • 0043131535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coase v. Pigou reexamined
    • 13 Ibid, p. 26. On the basis of this criticism Coase develops his laissez-faire message, which he contrasts with the Pigovian tradition of "Intervention by Public Authority," (Coase, The Firm, the Market and the Law, above note 7, pp. 20-27). Recently, it has been argued that Coase misunderstood Pigou or used him as a "straw man," and that "Pigou's view was thus much the same as that of Coase, although he was marginally less skeptical about the merits of state action." A. W. B. Simpson, "Coase v. Pigou Reexamined," 25 Journal of Legal Studies 53 (1996), p. 73. See Coase's reply. Ibid, p. 103, and Simpson's Addendum, Ibid, p. 99.
    • (1996) 25 Journal of Legal Studies , vol.53 , pp. 73
    • Simpson, A.W.B.1
  • 25
    • 0043131535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 13 Ibid, p. 26. On the basis of this criticism Coase develops his laissez-faire message, which he contrasts with the Pigovian tradition of "Intervention by Public Authority," (Coase, The Firm, the Market and the Law, above note 7, pp. 20-27). Recently, it has been argued that Coase misunderstood Pigou or used him as a "straw man," and that "Pigou's view was thus much the same as that of Coase, although he was marginally less skeptical about the merits of state action." A. W. B. Simpson, "Coase v. Pigou Reexamined," 25 Journal of Legal Studies 53 (1996), p. 73. See Coase's reply. Ibid, p. 103, and Simpson's Addendum, Ibid, p. 99.
    • 25 Journal of Legal Studies , pp. 103
    • Coase1
  • 26
    • 0043131535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 13 Ibid, p. 26. On the basis of this criticism Coase develops his laissez-faire message, which he contrasts with the Pigovian tradition of "Intervention by Public Authority," (Coase, The Firm, the Market and the Law, above note 7, pp. 20-27). Recently, it has been argued that Coase misunderstood Pigou or used him as a "straw man," and that "Pigou's view was thus much the same as that of Coase, although he was marginally less skeptical about the merits of state action." A. W. B. Simpson, "Coase v. Pigou Reexamined," 25 Journal of Legal Studies 53 (1996), p. 73. See Coase's reply. Ibid, p. 103, and Simpson's Addendum, Ibid, p. 99.
    • 25 Journal of Legal Studies , pp. 99
    • Simpson, S.1
  • 27
    • 0003047641 scopus 로고
    • The cost of Coase
    • 14 R. Cooter, "The Cost of Coase," 11 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1982), p. 8. Cooter analyzed the two examples used by Coase and reached the conclusion that the mitigated loss which equals externalized social cost is the fall in the rental value of the affected land. Ibid, p. 7. See also Schwab, above note 4, pp. 1186-1187.
    • (1982) 11 Journal of Legal Studies , vol.1 , pp. 8
    • Cooter, R.1
  • 28
    • 0011023255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Schwab, above note 4, pp. 1186-1187
    • 14 R. Cooter, "The Cost of Coase," 11 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1982), p. 8. Cooter analyzed the two examples used by Coase and reached the conclusion that the mitigated loss which equals externalized social cost is the fall in the rental value of the affected land. Ibid, p. 7. See also Schwab, above note 4, pp. 1186-1187.
    • 11 Journal of Legal Studies , pp. 7
  • 30
    • 0011028840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As sanctioned by Coase, above note 12. Simpson argues that Pigou held this view as well (see above note 13, pp. 70-71)
    • 16 As sanctioned by Coase, above note 12. Simpson argues that Pigou held this view as well (see above note 13, pp. 70-71).
  • 31
    • 34249669918 scopus 로고
    • Efficiency and justice in tort damages: The shortcomings of the pecuniary loss rule
    • 17 The branch of law that deals with such rights is the law of restitution or unjust enrichment. See W. Bishop and J. Sutton, "Efficiency and Justice in Tort Damages: The Shortcomings of the Pecuniary Loss Rule," 15 Journal of Legal Studies 347 (1986), pp. 348 and 350.
    • (1986) 15 Journal of Legal Studies , vol.347 , pp. 348
    • Bishop, W.1    Sutton, J.2
  • 32
    • 0010956152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Assuming, of course, that the interrupted activity generates rent, and that the interruption is not marginal. In the margin, price equals production costs and there is no rent
    • 18 Assuming, of course, that the interrupted activity generates rent, and that the interruption is not marginal. In the margin, price equals production costs and there is no rent.
  • 33
    • 0011000713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This result is contingent upon the net increase in the rent of other activities exceeding the net loss of consumer surplus in the process
    • 19 This result is contingent upon the net increase in the rent of other activities exceeding the net loss of consumer surplus in the process.
  • 34
    • 0001828988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Economic loss in tort
    • 20 See W. Bishop, "Economic Loss in Tort," 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1981); Bishop and Sutton, Pecuniary Loss Rule, above note 17; V. P. Goldberg, "Recovery for Economic Loss Following the Exxon Valdez Oil Spill," 23 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1994); Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 251-255; S. Shavell, Economic Analysis of Accident Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987) pp. 135-140.
    • (1981) 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies , vol.1
    • Bishop, W.1
  • 35
    • 0001828988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 17
    • 20 See W. Bishop, "Economic Loss in Tort," 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1981); Bishop and Sutton, Pecuniary Loss Rule, above note 17; V. P. Goldberg, "Recovery for Economic Loss Following the Exxon Valdez Oil Spill," 23 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1994); Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 251-255; S. Shavell, Economic Analysis of Accident Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987) pp. 135-140.
    • Pecuniary Loss Rule
    • Bishop1    Sutton2
  • 36
    • 0001828988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recovery for economic loss following the exxon valdez oil spill
    • 20 See W. Bishop, "Economic Loss in Tort," 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1981); Bishop and Sutton, Pecuniary Loss Rule, above note 17; V. P. Goldberg, "Recovery for Economic Loss Following the Exxon Valdez Oil Spill," 23 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1994); Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 251-255; S. Shavell, Economic Analysis of Accident Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987) pp. 135-140.
    • (1994) 23 Journal of Legal Studies , vol.1
    • Goldberg, V.P.1
  • 37
    • 0001828988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 4
    • 20 See W. Bishop, "Economic Loss in Tort," 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1981); Bishop and Sutton, Pecuniary Loss Rule, above note 17; V. P. Goldberg, "Recovery for Economic Loss Following the Exxon Valdez Oil Spill," 23 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1994); Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 251-255; S. Shavell, Economic Analysis of Accident Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987) pp. 135-140.
    • Economic Structure , pp. 251-255
    • Landes1    Posner2
  • 38
    • 0001828988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • 20 See W. Bishop, "Economic Loss in Tort," 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1981); Bishop and Sutton, Pecuniary Loss Rule, above note 17; V. P. Goldberg, "Recovery for Economic Loss Following the Exxon Valdez Oil Spill," 23 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1994); Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 251-255; S. Shavell, Economic Analysis of Accident Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987) pp. 135-140.
    • (1987) Economic Analysis of Accident Law , pp. 135-140
    • Shavell, S.1
  • 39
    • 0011044041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a comprehensive discussion of the exclusionary rule see B. Feldthusen, Economic Negligence, 3rd edition, (Carswell, Toronto, 1994). The rule is discussed below, in the third part of Section IV
    • 21 For a comprehensive discussion of the exclusionary rule see B. Feldthusen, Economic Negligence, 3rd edition, (Carswell, Toronto, 1994). The rule is discussed below, in the third part of Section IV.
  • 40
    • 0004325086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20
    • 22 See Bishop, Economic Loss, above note 20, pp. 4-7.
    • Economic Loss , pp. 4-7
    • Bishop1
  • 41
    • 0004304377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20
    • 23 Goldberg, Oil Spill, above note 20, pp. 24-34.
    • Oil Spill , pp. 24-34
    • Goldberg1
  • 42
    • 0010960512 scopus 로고
    • The economic loss problem: A comment on bishop
    • 24 Rizzo argued that the presence of excess capacity is itself an unexplained, inefficient, anomaly. See M. J. Rizzo, "The Economic Loss Problem: A Comment on Bishop," 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 197 (1982); M. J. Rizzo, "A Theory of Economic Loss in the Law of Torts," 11 Journal of Legal Studies 281 (1982). In my view, a state of excess capacity can be efficient and requires no explanation. Hotels rarely have 100-% vacancy, and retail stores may often be empty or half empty. Excess capacity is an anomaly only when it is inefficient, namely, when those inputs that are sometimes used and sometimes not have a better alternative use. In the absence of such alternative use nothing is wrong with excess capacity. In this regard see also Bishop, "Economic Loss: A Reply to Professor Rizzo," 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 207 (1982). See also D. Rabin, "Tort Recovery for Negligently Inflicted Economic Loss: A Reassessment," 37 Stanford Law Review 1513 (1985), p. 1536, note 72.
    • (1982) 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies , vol.197
    • Rizzo, M.J.1
  • 43
    • 0010960512 scopus 로고
    • A theory of economic loss in the law of torts
    • In my view, a state of excess capacity can be efficient and requires no explanation. Hotels rarely have 100-% vacancy, and retail stores may often be empty or half empty. Excess capacity is an anomaly only when it is inefficient, namely, when those inputs that are sometimes used and sometimes not have a better alternative use. In the absence of such alternative use nothing is wrong with excess capacity. In this regard see also
    • 24 Rizzo argued that the presence of excess capacity is itself an unexplained, inefficient, anomaly. See M. J. Rizzo, "The Economic Loss Problem: A Comment on Bishop," 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 197 (1982); M. J. Rizzo, "A Theory of Economic Loss in the Law of Torts," 11 Journal of Legal Studies 281 (1982). In my view, a state of excess capacity can be efficient and requires no explanation. Hotels rarely have 100-% vacancy, and retail stores may often be empty or half empty. Excess capacity is an anomaly only when it is inefficient, namely, when those inputs that are sometimes used and sometimes not have a better alternative use. In the absence of such alternative use nothing is wrong with excess capacity. In this regard see also Bishop, "Economic Loss: A Reply to Professor Rizzo," 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 207 (1982). See also D. Rabin, "Tort Recovery for Negligently Inflicted Economic Loss: A Reassessment," 37 Stanford Law Review 1513 (1985), p. 1536, note 72.
    • (1982) 11 Journal of Legal Studies , vol.281
  • 44
    • 27744512259 scopus 로고
    • Economic loss: A reply to professor rizzo
    • 24 Rizzo argued that the presence of excess capacity is itself an unexplained, inefficient, anomaly. See M. J. Rizzo, "The Economic Loss Problem: A Comment on Bishop," 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 197 (1982); M. J. Rizzo, "A Theory of Economic Loss in the Law of Torts," 11 Journal of Legal Studies 281 (1982). In my view, a state of excess capacity can be efficient and requires no explanation. Hotels rarely have 100-% vacancy, and retail stores may often be empty or half empty. Excess capacity is an anomaly only when it is inefficient, namely, when those inputs that are sometimes used and sometimes not have a better alternative use. In the absence of such alternative use nothing is wrong with excess capacity. In this regard see also Bishop, "Economic Loss: A Reply to Professor Rizzo," 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 207 (1982). See also D. Rabin, "Tort Recovery for Negligently Inflicted Economic Loss: A Reassessment," 37 Stanford Law Review 1513 (1985), p. 1536, note 72.
    • (1982) 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies , vol.207
    • Bishop1
  • 45
    • 0010960512 scopus 로고
    • Tort recovery for negligently inflicted economic loss: A reassessment
    • note 72
    • 24 Rizzo argued that the presence of excess capacity is itself an unexplained, inefficient, anomaly. See M. J. Rizzo, "The Economic Loss Problem: A Comment on Bishop," 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 197 (1982); M. J. Rizzo, "A Theory of Economic Loss in the Law of Torts," 11 Journal of Legal Studies 281 (1982). In my view, a state of excess capacity can be efficient and requires no explanation. Hotels rarely have 100-% vacancy, and retail stores may often be empty or half empty. Excess capacity is an anomaly only when it is inefficient, namely, when those inputs that are sometimes used and sometimes not have a better alternative use. In the absence of such alternative use nothing is wrong with excess capacity. In this regard see also Bishop, "Economic Loss: A Reply to Professor Rizzo," 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 207 (1982). See also D. Rabin, "Tort Recovery for Negligently Inflicted Economic Loss: A Reassessment," 37 Stanford Law Review 1513 (1985), p. 1536, note 72.
    • (1985) 37 Stanford Law Review , vol.1513 , pp. 1536
    • Rabin, D.1
  • 46
    • 0010990799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The process for generating alternative rent is a complex one, and so is its measurement. Sometimes additional inputs are transferred directly from the interrupted production to the production of substitutes. It may well be, however, that the additional inputs for the production of substitutes come from other lines of production, while inputs of the interrupted production are redeployed elsewhere
    • 25 The process for generating alternative rent is a complex one, and so is its measurement. Sometimes additional inputs are transferred directly from the interrupted production to the production of substitutes. It may well be, however, that the additional inputs for the production of substitutes come from other lines of production, while inputs of the interrupted production are redeployed elsewhere.
  • 47
    • 0004304377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20
    • 26 Furthermore, even when inputs of the interrupted production cannot be redeployed, the redeployment of other inputs may generate additional rent. Assume, for example, that inputs are transferred from other uses to repair a resource damaged by the loss-inflicting activity. If the rent on these inputs is increased as a result of their transfer, such increase is an offsetting gain. Goldberg's statement, that repairer's gains do not offset physical damage but merely restate them, should therefore be qualified in cases of increased rent. See Goldberg, Oil Spill, above note 20, pp. 34-35.
    • Oil Spill , pp. 34-35
    • Goldberg1
  • 48
    • 0004320116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20
    • 27 Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, p. 138.
    • Accident Law , pp. 138
    • Shavell1
  • 49
    • 0010960321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One example is interference with the contractual or precontractual relations of another producer in a way that transfers the gain from these relations from the interrupted producer to another producer
    • 28 One example is interference with the contractual or precontractual relations of another producer in a way that transfers the gain from these relations from the interrupted producer to another producer.
  • 50
    • 0011023048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rabin, above note 24. Yet, even when the whole gain is transferred from one producer to another, negative implications and side effects may cause additional losses that are not offset. Interference with contractual or precontractual relations, for example, undermines commercial certainty - a real social cost
    • 29 See Rabin, above note 24. Yet, even when the whole gain is transferred from one producer to another, negative implications and side effects may cause additional losses that are not offset. Interference with contractual or precontractual relations, for example, undermines commercial certainty - a real social cost.
  • 51
    • 0011034398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It should be noted that gains that offset the private loss of interrupted producers do not include the additional rent resulting from a rise in the price of product or service already produced. This additional rent comes at the expense of consumers who have to pay more for the product or service
    • 30 It should be noted that gains that offset the private loss of interrupted producers do not include the additional rent resulting from a rise in the price of product or service already produced. This additional rent comes at the expense of consumers who have to pay more for the product or service.
  • 52
    • 0004325086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20
    • 31 Bishop, Economic Loss, above note 20, pp. 5 and 12. See also Goldberg, Oil Spill, above note 20, p. 33. Of course, there are other factors that create or increase social cost in cases of interrupted production. Producers anticipating a rise in demand when other producers are interrupted tend to structure their production in a way that increases capacity inefficiently (Bishop, Ibid, p. 15). Social cost is also incurred when producers take measures to avoid a private loss that does not represent any social cost (Bishop, Ibid, p. 9). See below, note 45. See also Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 136-139. Another source of social cost is risk aversion. See Bishop, Ibid. p. 7. Yet, these added social costs do not weaken the conclusion that social cost, through their mitigation by gains of third parties, may be smaller than the private loss of interrupted producers.
    • Economic Loss , pp. 5
    • Bishop1
  • 53
    • 0004304377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20
    • 31 Bishop, Economic Loss, above note 20, pp. 5 and 12. See also Goldberg, Oil Spill, above note 20, p. 33. Of course, there are other factors that create or increase social cost in cases of interrupted production. Producers anticipating a rise in demand when other producers are interrupted tend to structure their production in a way that increases capacity inefficiently (Bishop, Ibid, p. 15). Social cost is also incurred when producers take measures to avoid a private loss that does not represent any social cost (Bishop, Ibid, p. 9). See below, note 45. See also Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 136-139. Another source of social cost is risk aversion. See Bishop, Ibid. p. 7. Yet, these added social costs do not weaken the conclusion that social cost, through their mitigation by gains of third parties, may be smaller than the private loss of interrupted producers.
    • Oil Spill , pp. 33
    • Goldberg1
  • 54
    • 0010997217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 31 Bishop, Economic Loss, above note 20, pp. 5 and 12. See also Goldberg, Oil Spill, above note 20, p. 33. Of course, there are other factors that create or increase social cost in cases of interrupted production. Producers anticipating a rise in demand when other producers are interrupted tend to structure their production in a way that increases capacity inefficiently (Bishop, Ibid, p. 15). Social cost is also incurred when producers take measures to avoid a private loss that does not represent any social cost (Bishop, Ibid, p. 9). See below, note 45. See also Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 136-139. Another source of social cost is risk aversion. See Bishop, Ibid. p. 7. Yet, these added social costs do not weaken the conclusion that social cost, through their mitigation by gains of third parties, may be smaller than the private loss of interrupted producers.
    • Oil Spill , pp. 15
    • Bishop1
  • 55
    • 0010997217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See below, note 45
    • 31 Bishop, Economic Loss, above note 20, pp. 5 and 12. See also Goldberg, Oil Spill, above note 20, p. 33. Of course, there are other factors that create or increase social cost in cases of interrupted production. Producers anticipating a rise in demand when other producers are interrupted tend to structure their production in a way that increases capacity inefficiently (Bishop, Ibid, p. 15). Social cost is also incurred when producers take measures to avoid a private loss that does not represent any social cost (Bishop, Ibid, p. 9). See below, note 45. See also Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 136-139. Another source of social cost is risk aversion. See Bishop, Ibid. p. 7. Yet, these added social costs do not weaken the conclusion that social cost, through their mitigation by gains of third parties, may be smaller than the private loss of interrupted producers.
    • Oil Spill , pp. 9
    • Bishop1
  • 56
    • 0004320116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20
    • 31 Bishop, Economic Loss, above note 20, pp. 5 and 12. See also Goldberg, Oil Spill, above note 20, p. 33. Of course, there are other factors that create or increase social cost in cases of interrupted production. Producers anticipating a rise in demand when other producers are interrupted tend to structure their production in a way that increases capacity inefficiently (Bishop, Ibid, p. 15). Social cost is also incurred when producers take measures to avoid a private loss that does not represent any social cost (Bishop, Ibid, p. 9). See below, note 45. See also Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 136-139. Another source of social cost is risk aversion. See Bishop, Ibid. p. 7. Yet, these added social costs do not weaken the conclusion that social cost, through their mitigation by gains of third parties, may be smaller than the private loss of interrupted producers.
    • Accident Law , pp. 136-139
    • Shavell1
  • 57
    • 0011042922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 31 Bishop, Economic Loss, above note 20, pp. 5 and 12. See also Goldberg, Oil Spill, above note 20, p. 33. Of course, there are other factors that create or increase social cost in cases of interrupted production. Producers anticipating a rise in demand when other producers are interrupted tend to structure their production in a way that increases capacity inefficiently (Bishop, Ibid, p. 15). Social cost is also incurred when producers take measures to avoid a private loss that does not represent any social cost (Bishop, Ibid, p. 9). See below, note 45. See also Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 136-139. Another source of social cost is risk aversion. See Bishop, Ibid. p. 7. Yet, these added social costs do not weaken the conclusion that social cost, through their mitigation by gains of third parties, may be smaller than the private loss of interrupted producers.
    • Accident Law , pp. 7
    • Bishop1
  • 58
    • 0010961494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the railroad's sparks example, an activity-related benefit is the welfare of those who use the trains, whereas in the pollution example, it is the welfare of those who consume the products of the polluting factory. 33 Marginal products and services whose price equals consumption value do not generate a consumer surplus
    • 32 In the railroad's sparks example, an activity-related benefit is the welfare of those who use the trains, whereas in the pollution example, it is the welfare of those who consume the products of the polluting factory. 33 Marginal products and services whose price equals consumption value do not generate a consumer surplus.
  • 59
    • 0011001232 scopus 로고
    • Coase theorem, competitive market and products liability law
    • Producers and service providers tend to disregard this consumer surplus whenever it does not affect their rent. For a similar reason I have argued, in the context of product liability, that the Coase Theorem is inapplicable to competitive markets, because victims in a competitive market cannot offer their consumer surplus to producers as a Coasean bribe. The non-transferability of producer surplus is a built-in transaction costs barrier in competitive markets
    • 34 Producers and service providers tend to disregard this consumer surplus whenever it does not affect their rent. For a similar reason I have argued, in the context of product liability, that the Coase Theorem is inapplicable to competitive markets, because victims in a competitive market cannot offer their consumer surplus to producers as a Coasean bribe. The non-transferability of producer surplus is a built-in transaction costs barrier in competitive markets. See I. Gilead, "Coase Theorem, Competitive Market and Products Liability Law," 20 Israel Law Review 39 (1985).
    • (1985) 20 Israel Law Review , vol.39
    • Gilead, I.1
  • 60
    • 84925927532 scopus 로고
    • Negligent misrepresentation: Economist's view
    • note
    • 35 Bishop discusses externalized benefits in the limited context of negligent misrepresentation. W. Bishop, "Negligent Misrepresentation: Economist's View," 96 Law Quarterly Review 360 (1980), pp. 365-366. He acknowledges that the production of information generates benefits to third parties, and that these benefits should be offset against the inflicted losses to avoid overdeterrence. Yet, Bishop explicitly argues that these benefits do not exist in "[m]uch of tort law," namely, in typical cases of negligence and nuisance (p. 365). I fail to see why not. As indicated, almost every product that is manufactured or any service that is provided generate consumer surplus. The tendency to understate the offsetting effect of activity-related benefits may be explained, however, by the elusiveness of consumer surplus. Consumer surplus is usually spread over a large group of mostly unidentified beneficiaries, and is often immeasurable because it represents subjective preferences. Another explanation, as many probably will argue, is that activity-related benefits are irrelevant and should be ignored because they represent pecuniary externalities and not technological externalities. As already indicated (above note I), it is customary to assume that pecuniary externalities, as opposed to technological ones, do not produce inefficiencies. It is true that activity-related benefits are a kind of pecuniary externality. Yet, pecuniary externalities may produce inefficiencies. Assume, for example, that at its marginal level a loss-inflicting activity enjoys no profit, that it inflicts a loss of 1, and that it produces net activity-related benefits of 2. The total effect of the activity in its margin is positive. Internalization of the inflicted loss to the injurer, however, will render this marginal level of activity unprofitable from his point of view and the activity will contract. This reduction in the level of the loss-inflicting activity is inefficient. Loss internalization here leads to overdeterrence because the injurer externalizes the activity-related benefit, and because the internalization system fails to offset this benefit against the private loss. Why, then, is it generally assumed that pecuniary externalities do not produce inefficiencies? The answer can be found in the different types of efficiency. Pecuniary externalities, unlike technological externalities, do not directly affect production and utility functions, and therefore do not produce productive or distributive inefficiencies (in productive efficiency the economy is on its production-possibility frontier; in distributive efficiency consumers cannot increase their aggregate welfare by swapping products and services). Yet the third type of efficiency, allocative efficiency, may be negatively affected by pecuniary externalities. As recognized in Baumol and Oates (above note 1, pp. 29-31) pecuniary externalities take the form of a movement along the utility-possibility frontier. Such movement may bring the economy to a point where it produces an inefficient combination of products and services. It is inefficient in the sense that a different combination at another point on the frontier could make all parties better off. Pecuniary externalities, in other words, may lead to an inefficient change of activity levels, and this is exactly what emerges from the above example. The analysis of the "double taxation" issue supports this contention. See below, note 48 and the accompanying text. The opposite argument, that advantages transmitted via the market are normally offset by corresponding disadvantages to others, is questionable and artificially narrows the definition of social cost.note See K. W. Kapp, "On the Nature and Significance of Social Cost," 12 Kyklos 334 (1969), reprinted in Externalities, above note 1, 3 p. 8. For various aspects of the distorting effect of pecuniary externalities see: Scitovski, above note 1; F. J. Anderson, "Pecuniary Externalities and Referent Groups in the Operation of the Price System," 40 Southern Economic Journal 442 (1974); L. H. Loong and R. Zeckhauser, "Pecuniary Externalities do Matter When Contingent Claims Markets are Incomplete," 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics 17 (1982); Y. K. Ng, "Rents and Pecuniary Externalities in Cost-benefit Analysis: Comment," 73 American Economic Review 1168 (1983); H. S. Esfahani and D. Mookherjee, "Productivity, Contracting Modes, and Developments," 46 Journal of Development Economics 203 (1995); and L. Makovski and J. M. Ostroy, "Appropriation and Efficiency: A Revision of the First Theorem of Welfare Economics," 85 American Economic Review 808 (1995).
    • (1980) 96 Law Quarterly Review , vol.360 , pp. 365-366
    • Bishop, W.1
  • 61
    • 84980122308 scopus 로고
    • On the nature and significance of social cost
    • 35 Bishop discusses externalized benefits in the limited context of negligent misrepresentation. W. Bishop, "Negligent Misrepresentation: Economist's View," 96 Law Quarterly Review 360 (1980), pp. 365-366. He acknowledges that the production of information generates benefits to third parties, and that these benefits should be offset against the inflicted losses to avoid overdeterrence. Yet, Bishop explicitly argues that these benefits do not exist in "[m]uch of tort law," namely, in typical cases of negligence and nuisance (p. 365). I fail to see why not. As indicated, almost every product that is manufactured or any service that is provided generate consumer surplus. The tendency to understate the offsetting effect of activity-related benefits may be explained, however, by the elusiveness of consumer surplus. Consumer surplus is usually spread over a large group of mostly unidentified beneficiaries, and is often immeasurable because it represents subjective preferences. Another explanation, as many probably will argue, is that activity-related benefits are irrelevant and should be ignored because they represent pecuniary externalities and not technological externalities. As already indicated (above note I), it is customary to assume that pecuniary externalities, as opposed to technological ones, do not produce inefficiencies. It is true that activity-related benefits are a kind of pecuniary externality. Yet, pecuniary externalities may produce inefficiencies. Assume, for example, that at its marginal level a loss-inflicting activity enjoys no profit, that it inflicts a loss of 1, and that it produces net activity-related benefits of 2. The total effect of the activity in its margin is positive. Internalization of the inflicted loss to the injurer, however, will render this marginal level of activity unprofitable from his point of view and the activity will contract. This reduction in the level of the loss-inflicting activity is inefficient. Loss internalization here leads to overdeterrence because the injurer externalizes the activity-related benefit, and because the internalization system fails to offset this benefit against the private loss. Why, then, is it generally assumed that pecuniary externalities do not produce inefficiencies? The answer can be found in the different types of efficiency. Pecuniary externalities, unlike technological externalities, do not directly affect production and utility functions, and therefore do not produce productive or distributive inefficiencies (in productive efficiency the economy is on its production-possibility frontier; in distributive efficiency consumers cannot increase their aggregate welfare by swapping products and services). Yet the third type of efficiency, allocative efficiency, may be negatively affected by pecuniary externalities. As recognized in Baumol and Oates (above note 1, pp. 29-31) pecuniary externalities take the form of a movement along the utility-possibility frontier. Such movement may bring the economy to a point where it produces an inefficient combination of products and services. It is inefficient in the sense that a different combination at another point on the frontier could make all parties better off. Pecuniary externalities, in other words, may lead to an inefficient change of activity levels, and this is exactly what emerges from the above example. The analysis of the "double taxation" issue supports this contention. See below, note 48 and the accompanying text. The opposite argument, that advantages transmitted via the market are normally offset by corresponding disadvantages to others, is questionable and artificially narrows the definition of social cost. See K. W. Kapp, "On the Nature and Significance of Social Cost," 12 Kyklos 334 (1969), reprinted in Externalities, above note 1, 3 p. 8. For various aspects of the distorting effect of pecuniary externalities see: Scitovski, above note 1; F. J. Anderson, "Pecuniary Externalities and Referent Groups in the Operation of the Price System," 40 Southern Economic Journal 442 (1974); L. H. Loong and R. Zeckhauser, "Pecuniary Externalities do Matter When Contingent Claims Markets are Incomplete," 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics 17 (1982); Y. K. Ng, "Rents and Pecuniary Externalities in Cost-benefit Analysis: Comment," 73 American Economic Review 1168 (1983); H. S. Esfahani and D. Mookherjee, "Productivity, Contracting Modes, and Developments," 46 Journal of Development Economics 203 (1995); and L. Makovski and J. M. Ostroy, "Appropriation and Efficiency: A Revision of the First Theorem of Welfare Economics," 85 American Economic Review 808 (1995).
    • (1969) 12 Kyklos , vol.334
    • Kapp, K.W.1
  • 62
    • 0010961493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 1, 3 For various aspects of the distorting effect of pecuniary externalities
    • 35 Bishop discusses externalized benefits in the limited context of negligent misrepresentation. W. Bishop, "Negligent Misrepresentation: Economist's View," 96 Law Quarterly Review 360 (1980), pp. 365-366. He acknowledges that the production of information generates benefits to third parties, and that these benefits should be offset against the inflicted losses to avoid overdeterrence. Yet, Bishop explicitly argues that these benefits do not exist in "[m]uch of tort law," namely, in typical cases of negligence and nuisance (p. 365). I fail to see why not. As indicated, almost every product that is manufactured or any service that is provided generate consumer surplus. The tendency to understate the offsetting effect of activity-related benefits may be explained, however, by the elusiveness of consumer surplus. Consumer surplus is usually spread over a large group of mostly unidentified beneficiaries, and is often immeasurable because it represents subjective preferences. Another explanation, as many probably will argue, is that activity-related benefits are irrelevant and should be ignored because they represent pecuniary externalities and not technological externalities. As already indicated (above note I), it is customary to assume that pecuniary externalities, as opposed to technological ones, do not produce inefficiencies. It is true that activity-related benefits are a kind of pecuniary externality. Yet, pecuniary externalities may produce inefficiencies. Assume, for example, that at its marginal level a loss-inflicting activity enjoys no profit, that it inflicts a loss of 1, and that it produces net activity-related benefits of 2. The total effect of the activity in its margin is positive. Internalization of the inflicted loss to the injurer, however, will render this marginal level of activity unprofitable from his point of view and the activity will contract. This reduction in the level of the loss-inflicting activity is inefficient. Loss internalization here leads to overdeterrence because the injurer externalizes the activity-related benefit, and because the internalization system fails to offset this benefit against the private loss. Why, then, is it generally assumed that pecuniary externalities do not produce inefficiencies? The answer can be found in the different types of efficiency. Pecuniary externalities, unlike technological externalities, do not directly affect production and utility functions, and therefore do not produce productive or distributive inefficiencies (in productive efficiency the economy is on its production-possibility frontier; in distributive efficiency consumers cannot increase their aggregate welfare by swapping products and services). Yet the third type of efficiency, allocative efficiency, may be negatively affected by pecuniary externalities. As recognized in Baumol and Oates (above note 1, pp. 29-31) pecuniary externalities take the form of a movement along the utility-possibility frontier. Such movement may bring the economy to a point where it produces an inefficient combination of products and services. It is inefficient in the sense that a different combination at another point on the frontier could make all parties better off. Pecuniary externalities, in other words, may lead to an inefficient change of activity levels, and this is exactly what emerges from the above example. The analysis of the "double taxation" issue supports this contention. See below, note 48 and the accompanying text. The opposite argument, that advantages transmitted via the market are normally offset by corresponding disadvantages to others, is questionable and artificially narrows the definition of social cost. See K. W. Kapp, "On the Nature and Significance of Social Cost," 12 Kyklos 334 (1969), reprinted in Externalities, above note 1, 3 p. 8. For various aspects of the distorting effect of pecuniary externalities see: Scitovski, above note 1; F. J. Anderson, "Pecuniary Externalities and Referent Groups in the Operation of the Price System," 40 Southern Economic Journal 442 (1974); L. H. Loong and R. Zeckhauser, "Pecuniary Externalities do Matter When Contingent Claims Markets are Incomplete," 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics 17 (1982); Y. K. Ng, "Rents and Pecuniary Externalities in Cost-benefit Analysis: Comment," 73 American Economic Review 1168 (1983); H. S. Esfahani and D. Mookherjee, "Productivity, Contracting Modes, and Developments," 46 Journal of Development Economics 203 (1995); and L. Makovski and J. M. Ostroy, "Appropriation and Efficiency: A Revision of the First Theorem of Welfare Economics," 85 American Economic Review 808 (1995).
    • Externalities , pp. 8
  • 63
    • 0010988057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 1
    • 35 Bishop discusses externalized benefits in the limited context of negligent misrepresentation. W. Bishop, "Negligent Misrepresentation: Economist's View," 96 Law Quarterly Review 360 (1980), pp. 365-366. He acknowledges that the production of information generates benefits to third parties, and that these benefits should be offset against the inflicted losses to avoid overdeterrence. Yet, Bishop explicitly argues that these benefits do not exist in "[m]uch of tort law," namely, in typical cases of negligence and nuisance (p. 365). I fail to see why not. As indicated, almost every product that is manufactured or any service that is provided generate consumer surplus. The tendency to understate the offsetting effect of activity-related benefits may be explained, however, by the elusiveness of consumer surplus. Consumer surplus is usually spread over a large group of mostly unidentified beneficiaries, and is often immeasurable because it represents subjective preferences. Another explanation, as many probably will argue, is that activity-related benefits are irrelevant and should be ignored because they represent pecuniary externalities and not technological externalities. As already indicated (above note I), it is customary to assume that pecuniary externalities, as opposed to technological ones, do not produce inefficiencies. It is true that activity-related benefits are a kind of pecuniary externality. Yet, pecuniary externalities may produce inefficiencies. Assume, for example, that at its marginal level a loss-inflicting activity enjoys no profit, that it inflicts a loss of 1, and that it produces net activity-related benefits of 2. The total effect of the activity in its margin is positive. Internalization of the inflicted loss to the injurer, however, will render this marginal level of activity unprofitable from his point of view and the activity will contract. This reduction in the level of the loss-inflicting activity is inefficient. Loss internalization here leads to overdeterrence because the injurer externalizes the activity-related benefit, and because the internalization system fails to offset this benefit against the private loss. Why, then, is it generally assumed that pecuniary externalities do not produce inefficiencies? The answer can be found in the different types of efficiency. Pecuniary externalities, unlike technological externalities, do not directly affect production and utility functions, and therefore do not produce productive or distributive inefficiencies (in productive efficiency the economy is on its production-possibility frontier; in distributive efficiency consumers cannot increase their aggregate welfare by swapping products and services). Yet the third type of efficiency, allocative efficiency, may be negatively affected by pecuniary externalities. As recognized in Baumol and Oates (above note 1, pp. 29-31) pecuniary externalities take the form of a movement along the utility-possibility frontier. Such movement may bring the economy to a point where it produces an inefficient combination of products and services. It is inefficient in the sense that a different combination at another point on the frontier could make all parties better off. Pecuniary externalities, in other words, may lead to an inefficient change of activity levels, and this is exactly what emerges from the above example. The analysis of the "double taxation" issue supports this contention. See below, note 48 and the accompanying text. The opposite argument, that advantages transmitted via the market are normally offset by corresponding disadvantages to others, is questionable and artificially narrows the definition of social cost. See K. W. Kapp, "On the Nature and Significance of Social Cost," 12 Kyklos 334 (1969), reprinted in Externalities, above note 1, 3 p. 8. For various aspects of the distorting effect of pecuniary externalities see: Scitovski, above note 1; F. J. Anderson, "Pecuniary Externalities and Referent Groups in the Operation of the Price System," 40 Southern Economic Journal 442 (1974); L. H. Loong and R. Zeckhauser, "Pecuniary Externalities do Matter When Contingent Claims Markets are Incomplete," 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics 17 (1982); Y. K. Ng, "Rents and Pecuniary Externalities in Cost-benefit Analysis: Comment," 73 American Economic Review 1168 (1983); H. S. Esfahani and D. Mookherjee, "Productivity, Contracting Modes, and Developments," 46 Journal of Development Economics 203 (1995); and L. Makovski and J. M. Ostroy, "Appropriation and Efficiency: A Revision of the First Theorem of Welfare Economics," 85 American Economic Review 808 (1995).
    • Scitovski1
  • 64
    • 0010993881 scopus 로고
    • Pecuniary externalities and referent groups in the operation of the price system
    • 35 Bishop discusses externalized benefits in the limited context of negligent misrepresentation. W. Bishop, "Negligent Misrepresentation: Economist's View," 96 Law Quarterly Review 360 (1980), pp. 365-366. He acknowledges that the production of information generates benefits to third parties, and that these benefits should be offset against the inflicted losses to avoid overdeterrence. Yet, Bishop explicitly argues that these benefits do not exist in "[m]uch of tort law," namely, in typical cases of negligence and nuisance (p. 365). I fail to see why not. As indicated, almost every product that is manufactured or any service that is provided generate consumer surplus. The tendency to understate the offsetting effect of activity-related benefits may be explained, however, by the elusiveness of consumer surplus. Consumer surplus is usually spread over a large group of mostly unidentified beneficiaries, and is often immeasurable because it represents subjective preferences. Another explanation, as many probably will argue, is that activity-related benefits are irrelevant and should be ignored because they represent pecuniary externalities and not technological externalities. As already indicated (above note I), it is customary to assume that pecuniary externalities, as opposed to technological ones, do not produce inefficiencies. It is true that activity-related benefits are a kind of pecuniary externality. Yet, pecuniary externalities may produce inefficiencies. Assume, for example, that at its marginal level a loss-inflicting activity enjoys no profit, that it inflicts a loss of 1, and that it produces net activity-related benefits of 2. The total effect of the activity in its margin is positive. Internalization of the inflicted loss to the injurer, however, will render this marginal level of activity unprofitable from his point of view and the activity will contract. This reduction in the level of the loss-inflicting activity is inefficient. Loss internalization here leads to overdeterrence because the injurer externalizes the activity-related benefit, and because the internalization system fails to offset this benefit against the private loss. Why, then, is it generally assumed that pecuniary externalities do not produce inefficiencies? The answer can be found in the different types of efficiency. Pecuniary externalities, unlike technological externalities, do not directly affect production and utility functions, and therefore do not produce productive or distributive inefficiencies (in productive efficiency the economy is on its production-possibility frontier; in distributive efficiency consumers cannot increase their aggregate welfare by swapping products and services). Yet the third type of efficiency, allocative efficiency, may be negatively affected by pecuniary externalities. As recognized in Baumol and Oates (above note 1, pp. 29-31) pecuniary externalities take the form of a movement along the utility-possibility frontier. Such movement may bring the economy to a point where it produces an inefficient combination of products and services. It is inefficient in the sense that a different combination at another point on the frontier could make all parties better off. Pecuniary externalities, in other words, may lead to an inefficient change of activity levels, and this is exactly what emerges from the above example. The analysis of the "double taxation" issue supports this contention. See below, note 48 and the accompanying text. The opposite argument, that advantages transmitted via the market are normally offset by corresponding disadvantages to others, is questionable and artificially narrows the definition of social cost. See K. W. Kapp, "On the Nature and Significance of Social Cost," 12 Kyklos 334 (1969), reprinted in Externalities, above note 1, 3 p. 8. For various aspects of the distorting effect of pecuniary externalities see: Scitovski, above note 1; F. J. Anderson, "Pecuniary Externalities and Referent Groups in the Operation of the Price System," 40 Southern Economic Journal 442 (1974); L. H. Loong and R. Zeckhauser, "Pecuniary Externalities do Matter When Contingent Claims Markets are Incomplete," 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics 17 (1982); Y. K. Ng, "Rents and Pecuniary Externalities in Cost-benefit Analysis: Comment," 73 American Economic Review 1168 (1983); H. S. Esfahani and D. Mookherjee, "Productivity, Contracting Modes, and Developments," 46 Journal of Development Economics 203 (1995); and L. Makovski and J. M. Ostroy, "Appropriation and Efficiency: A Revision of the First Theorem of Welfare Economics," 85 American Economic Review 808 (1995).
    • (1974) 40 Southern Economic Journal , vol.442
    • Anderson, F.J.1
  • 65
    • 84962985471 scopus 로고
    • Pecuniary externalities do matter when contingent claims markets are incomplete
    • 35 Bishop discusses externalized benefits in the limited context of negligent misrepresentation. W. Bishop, "Negligent Misrepresentation: Economist's View," 96 Law Quarterly Review 360 (1980), pp. 365-366. He acknowledges that the production of information generates benefits to third parties, and that these benefits should be offset against the inflicted losses to avoid overdeterrence. Yet, Bishop explicitly argues that these benefits do not exist in "[m]uch of tort law," namely, in typical cases of negligence and nuisance (p. 365). I fail to see why not. As indicated, almost every product that is manufactured or any service that is provided generate consumer surplus. The tendency to understate the offsetting effect of activity-related benefits may be explained, however, by the elusiveness of consumer surplus. Consumer surplus is usually spread over a large group of mostly unidentified beneficiaries, and is often immeasurable because it represents subjective preferences. Another explanation, as many probably will argue, is that activity-related benefits are irrelevant and should be ignored because they represent pecuniary externalities and not technological externalities. As already indicated (above note I), it is customary to assume that pecuniary externalities, as opposed to technological ones, do not produce inefficiencies. It is true that activity-related benefits are a kind of pecuniary externality. Yet, pecuniary externalities may produce inefficiencies. Assume, for example, that at its marginal level a loss-inflicting activity enjoys no profit, that it inflicts a loss of 1, and that it produces net activity-related benefits of 2. The total effect of the activity in its margin is positive. Internalization of the inflicted loss to the injurer, however, will render this marginal level of activity unprofitable from his point of view and the activity will contract. This reduction in the level of the loss-inflicting activity is inefficient. Loss internalization here leads to overdeterrence because the injurer externalizes the activity-related benefit, and because the internalization system fails to offset this benefit against the private loss. Why, then, is it generally assumed that pecuniary externalities do not produce inefficiencies? The answer can be found in the different types of efficiency. Pecuniary externalities, unlike technological externalities, do not directly affect production and utility functions, and therefore do not produce productive or distributive inefficiencies (in productive efficiency the economy is on its production-possibility frontier; in distributive efficiency consumers cannot increase their aggregate welfare by swapping products and services). Yet the third type of efficiency, allocative efficiency, may be negatively affected by pecuniary externalities. As recognized in Baumol and Oates (above note 1, pp. 29-31) pecuniary externalities take the form of a movement along the utility-possibility frontier. Such movement may bring the economy to a point where it produces an inefficient combination of products and services. It is inefficient in the sense that a different combination at another point on the frontier could make all parties better off. Pecuniary externalities, in other words, may lead to an inefficient change of activity levels, and this is exactly what emerges from the above example. The analysis of the "double taxation" issue supports this contention. See below, note 48 and the accompanying text. The opposite argument, that advantages transmitted via the market are normally offset by corresponding disadvantages to others, is questionable and artificially narrows the definition of social cost. See K. W. Kapp, "On the Nature and Significance of Social Cost," 12 Kyklos 334 (1969), reprinted in Externalities, above note 1, 3 p. 8. For various aspects of the distorting effect of pecuniary externalities see: Scitovski, above note 1; F. J. Anderson, "Pecuniary Externalities and Referent Groups in the Operation of the Price System," 40 Southern Economic Journal 442 (1974); L. H. Loong and R. Zeckhauser, "Pecuniary Externalities do Matter When Contingent Claims Markets are Incomplete," 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics 17 (1982); Y. K. Ng, "Rents and Pecuniary Externalities in Cost-benefit Analysis: Comment," 73 American Economic Review 1168 (1983); H. S. Esfahani and D. Mookherjee, "Productivity, Contracting Modes, and Developments," 46 Journal of Development Economics 203 (1995); and L. Makovski and J. M. Ostroy, "Appropriation and Efficiency: A Revision of the First Theorem of Welfare Economics," 85 American Economic Review 808 (1995).
    • (1982) 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics , vol.17
    • Loong, L.H.1    Zeckhauser, R.2
  • 66
    • 0010955319 scopus 로고
    • Rents and pecuniary externalities in cost-benefit analysis: Comment
    • 35 Bishop discusses externalized benefits in the limited context of negligent misrepresentation. W. Bishop, "Negligent Misrepresentation: Economist's View," 96 Law Quarterly Review 360 (1980), pp. 365-366. He acknowledges that the production of information generates benefits to third parties, and that these benefits should be offset against the inflicted losses to avoid overdeterrence. Yet, Bishop explicitly argues that these benefits do not exist in "[m]uch of tort law," namely, in typical cases of negligence and nuisance (p. 365). I fail to see why not. As indicated, almost every product that is manufactured or any service that is provided generate consumer surplus. The tendency to understate the offsetting effect of activity-related benefits may be explained, however, by the elusiveness of consumer surplus. Consumer surplus is usually spread over a large group of mostly unidentified beneficiaries, and is often immeasurable because it represents subjective preferences. Another explanation, as many probably will argue, is that activity-related benefits are irrelevant and should be ignored because they represent pecuniary externalities and not technological externalities. As already indicated (above note I), it is customary to assume that pecuniary externalities, as opposed to technological ones, do not produce inefficiencies. It is true that activity-related benefits are a kind of pecuniary externality. Yet, pecuniary externalities may produce inefficiencies. Assume, for example, that at its marginal level a loss-inflicting activity enjoys no profit, that it inflicts a loss of 1, and that it produces net activity-related benefits of 2. The total effect of the activity in its margin is positive. Internalization of the inflicted loss to the injurer, however, will render this marginal level of activity unprofitable from his point of view and the activity will contract. This reduction in the level of the loss-inflicting activity is inefficient. Loss internalization here leads to overdeterrence because the injurer externalizes the activity-related benefit, and because the internalization system fails to offset this benefit against the private loss. Why, then, is it generally assumed that pecuniary externalities do not produce inefficiencies? The answer can be found in the different types of efficiency. Pecuniary externalities, unlike technological externalities, do not directly affect production and utility functions, and therefore do not produce productive or distributive inefficiencies (in productive efficiency the economy is on its production-possibility frontier; in distributive efficiency consumers cannot increase their aggregate welfare by swapping products and services). Yet the third type of efficiency, allocative efficiency, may be negatively affected by pecuniary externalities. As recognized in Baumol and Oates (above note 1, pp. 29-31) pecuniary externalities take the form of a movement along the utility-possibility frontier. Such movement may bring the economy to a point where it produces an inefficient combination of products and services. It is inefficient in the sense that a different combination at another point on the frontier could make all parties better off. Pecuniary externalities, in other words, may lead to an inefficient change of activity levels, and this is exactly what emerges from the above example. The analysis of the "double taxation" issue supports this contention. See below, note 48 and the accompanying text. The opposite argument, that advantages transmitted via the market are normally offset by corresponding disadvantages to others, is questionable and artificially narrows the definition of social cost. See K. W. Kapp, "On the Nature and Significance of Social Cost," 12 Kyklos 334 (1969), reprinted in Externalities, above note 1, 3 p. 8. For various aspects of the distorting effect of pecuniary externalities see: Scitovski, above note 1; F. J. Anderson, "Pecuniary Externalities and Referent Groups in the Operation of the Price System," 40 Southern Economic Journal 442 (1974); L. H. Loong and R. Zeckhauser, "Pecuniary Externalities do Matter When Contingent Claims Markets are Incomplete," 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics 17 (1982); Y. K. Ng, "Rents and Pecuniary Externalities in Cost-benefit Analysis: Comment," 73 American Economic Review 1168 (1983); H. S. Esfahani and D. Mookherjee, "Productivity, Contracting Modes, and Developments," 46 Journal of Development Economics 203 (1995); and L. Makovski and J. M. Ostroy, "Appropriation and Efficiency: A Revision of the First Theorem of Welfare Economics," 85 American Economic Review 808 (1995).
    • (1983) 73 American Economic Review , vol.1168
    • Ng, Y.K.1
  • 67
    • 0029546104 scopus 로고
    • Productivity, contracting modes, and developments
    • 35 Bishop discusses externalized benefits in the limited context of negligent misrepresentation. W. Bishop, "Negligent Misrepresentation: Economist's View," 96 Law Quarterly Review 360 (1980), pp. 365-366. He acknowledges that the production of information generates benefits to third parties, and that these benefits should be offset against the inflicted losses to avoid overdeterrence. Yet, Bishop explicitly argues that these benefits do not exist in "[m]uch of tort law," namely, in typical cases of negligence and nuisance (p. 365). I fail to see why not. As indicated, almost every product that is manufactured or any service that is provided generate consumer surplus. The tendency to understate the offsetting effect of activity-related benefits may be explained, however, by the elusiveness of consumer surplus. Consumer surplus is usually spread over a large group of mostly unidentified beneficiaries, and is often immeasurable because it represents subjective preferences. Another explanation, as many probably will argue, is that activity-related benefits are irrelevant and should be ignored because they represent pecuniary externalities and not technological externalities. As already indicated (above note I), it is customary to assume that pecuniary externalities, as opposed to technological ones, do not produce inefficiencies. It is true that activity-related benefits are a kind of pecuniary externality. Yet, pecuniary externalities may produce inefficiencies. Assume, for example, that at its marginal level a loss-inflicting activity enjoys no profit, that it inflicts a loss of 1, and that it produces net activity-related benefits of 2. The total effect of the activity in its margin is positive. Internalization of the inflicted loss to the injurer, however, will render this marginal level of activity unprofitable from his point of view and the activity will contract. This reduction in the level of the loss-inflicting activity is inefficient. Loss internalization here leads to overdeterrence because the injurer externalizes the activity-related benefit, and because the internalization system fails to offset this benefit against the private loss. Why, then, is it generally assumed that pecuniary externalities do not produce inefficiencies? The answer can be found in the different types of efficiency. Pecuniary externalities, unlike technological externalities, do not directly affect production and utility functions, and therefore do not produce productive or distributive inefficiencies (in productive efficiency the economy is on its production-possibility frontier; in distributive efficiency consumers cannot increase their aggregate welfare by swapping products and services). Yet the third type of efficiency, allocative efficiency, may be negatively affected by pecuniary externalities. As recognized in Baumol and Oates (above note 1, pp. 29-31) pecuniary externalities take the form of a movement along the utility-possibility frontier. Such movement may bring the economy to a point where it produces an inefficient combination of products and services. It is inefficient in the sense that a different combination at another point on the frontier could make all parties better off. Pecuniary externalities, in other words, may lead to an inefficient change of activity levels, and this is exactly what emerges from the above example. The analysis of the "double taxation" issue supports this contention. See below, note 48 and the accompanying text. The opposite argument, that advantages transmitted via the market are normally offset by corresponding disadvantages to others, is questionable and artificially narrows the definition of social cost. See K. W. Kapp, "On the Nature and Significance of Social Cost," 12 Kyklos 334 (1969), reprinted in Externalities, above note 1, 3 p. 8. For various aspects of the distorting effect of pecuniary externalities see: Scitovski, above note 1; F. J. Anderson, "Pecuniary Externalities and Referent Groups in the Operation of the Price System," 40 Southern Economic Journal 442 (1974); L. H. Loong and R. Zeckhauser, "Pecuniary Externalities do Matter When Contingent Claims Markets are Incomplete," 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics 17 (1982); Y. K. Ng, "Rents and Pecuniary Externalities in Cost-benefit Analysis: Comment," 73 American Economic Review 1168 (1983); H. S. Esfahani and D. Mookherjee, "Productivity, Contracting Modes, and Developments," 46 Journal of Development Economics 203 (1995); and L. Makovski and J. M. Ostroy, "Appropriation and Efficiency: A Revision of the First Theorem of Welfare Economics," 85 American Economic Review 808 (1995).
    • (1995) 46 Journal of Development Economics , vol.203
    • Esfahani, H.S.1    Mookherjee, D.2
  • 68
    • 0001741633 scopus 로고
    • Appropriation and efficiency: A revision of the first theorem of welfare economics
    • 35 Bishop discusses externalized benefits in the limited context of negligent misrepresentation. W. Bishop, "Negligent Misrepresentation: Economist's View," 96 Law Quarterly Review 360 (1980), pp. 365-366. He acknowledges that the production of information generates benefits to third parties, and that these benefits should be offset against the inflicted losses to avoid overdeterrence. Yet, Bishop explicitly argues that these benefits do not exist in "[m]uch of tort law," namely, in typical cases of negligence and nuisance (p. 365). I fail to see why not. As indicated, almost every product that is manufactured or any service that is provided generate consumer surplus. The tendency to understate the offsetting effect of activity-related benefits may be explained, however, by the elusiveness of consumer surplus. Consumer surplus is usually spread over a large group of mostly unidentified beneficiaries, and is often immeasurable because it represents subjective preferences. Another explanation, as many probably will argue, is that activity-related benefits are irrelevant and should be ignored because they represent pecuniary externalities and not technological externalities. As already indicated (above note I), it is customary to assume that pecuniary externalities, as opposed to technological ones, do not produce inefficiencies. It is true that activity-related benefits are a kind of pecuniary externality. Yet, pecuniary externalities may produce inefficiencies. Assume, for example, that at its marginal level a loss-inflicting activity enjoys no profit, that it inflicts a loss of 1, and that it produces net activity-related benefits of 2. The total effect of the activity in its margin is positive. Internalization of the inflicted loss to the injurer, however, will render this marginal level of activity unprofitable from his point of view and the activity will contract. This reduction in the level of the loss-inflicting activity is inefficient. Loss internalization here leads to overdeterrence because the injurer externalizes the activity-related benefit, and because the internalization system fails to offset this benefit against the private loss. Why, then, is it generally assumed that pecuniary externalities do not produce inefficiencies? The answer can be found in the different types of efficiency. Pecuniary externalities, unlike technological externalities, do not directly affect production and utility functions, and therefore do not produce productive or distributive inefficiencies (in productive efficiency the economy is on its production-possibility frontier; in distributive efficiency consumers cannot increase their aggregate welfare by swapping products and services). Yet the third type of efficiency, allocative efficiency, may be negatively affected by pecuniary externalities. As recognized in Baumol and Oates (above note 1, pp. 29-31) pecuniary externalities take the form of a movement along the utility-possibility frontier. Such movement may bring the economy to a point where it produces an inefficient combination of products and services. It is inefficient in the sense that a different combination at another point on the frontier could make all parties better off. Pecuniary externalities, in other words, may lead to an inefficient change of activity levels, and this is exactly what emerges from the above example. The analysis of the "double taxation" issue supports this contention. See below, note 48 and the accompanying text. The opposite argument, that advantages transmitted via the market are normally offset by corresponding disadvantages to others, is questionable and artificially narrows the definition of social cost. See K. W. Kapp, "On the Nature and Significance of Social Cost," 12 Kyklos 334 (1969), reprinted in Externalities, above note 1, 3 p. 8. For various aspects of the distorting effect of pecuniary externalities see: Scitovski, above note 1; F. J. Anderson, "Pecuniary Externalities and Referent Groups in the Operation of the Price System," 40 Southern Economic Journal 442 (1974); L. H. Loong and R. Zeckhauser, "Pecuniary Externalities do Matter When Contingent Claims Markets are Incomplete," 97 Quarterly Journal of Economics 17 (1982); Y. K. Ng, "Rents and Pecuniary Externalities in Cost-benefit Analysis: Comment," 73 American Economic Review 1168 (1983); H. S. Esfahani and D. Mookherjee, "Productivity, Contracting Modes, and Developments," 46 Journal of Development Economics 203 (1995); and L. Makovski and J. M. Ostroy, "Appropriation and Efficiency: A Revision of the First Theorem of Welfare Economics," 85 American Economic Review 808 (1995).
    • (1995) 85 American Economic Review , vol.808
    • Makovski, L.1    Ostroy, J.M.2
  • 69
    • 0011030141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • People must, to a certain extent, walk, commute, consume basic products, get medical treatment, and so on. The ability to mitigate these losses by moving to alternative activities is limited despite the prospect of road accidents, product-related accidents, or professional malpractice
    • 36 People must, to a certain extent, walk, commute, consume basic products, get medical treatment, and so on. The ability to mitigate these losses by moving to alternative activities is limited despite the prospect of road accidents, product-related accidents, or professional malpractice.
  • 70
    • 0004325086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20
    • 37 See Bishop, Economic Loss, above note 20, pp. 4-7; Bishop, Reply, above note 24, p. 208.
    • Economic Loss , pp. 4-7
    • Bishop1
  • 71
    • 0010993882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 24
    • 37 See Bishop, Economic Loss, above note 20, pp. 4-7; Bishop, Reply, above note 24, p. 208.
    • Reply , pp. 208
    • Bishop1
  • 72
    • 0010960099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Yet, the private loss may exceed the social cost of the destruction when the destroyed products or inputs are not marginal, namely, when their market price exceeds production costs
    • 38 Yet, the private loss may exceed the social cost of the destruction when the destroyed products or inputs are not marginal, namely, when their market price exceeds production costs.
  • 73
    • 0010955538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The market price of the repair may be offset by an increase in the rent of the repair services that would have otherwise been engaged in a less profitable activity. See above note 26
    • 39 The market price of the repair may be offset by an increase in the rent of the repair services that would have otherwise been engaged in a less profitable activity. See above note 26.
  • 74
  • 76
    • 0011001233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ". . . [T]he victim of a detrimental externality should face a zero charge: The victim should neither be taxed nor compensated for the damages absorbed." (Baumol and Oates, above note 1, p. 23) "To provide proper incentives to victims for defensive activities, neither compensation nor a tax is appropriate."
    • 42 ". . . [T]he victim of a detrimental externality should face a zero charge: The victim should neither be taxed nor compensated for the damages absorbed." (Baumol and Oates, above note 1, p. 23) "To provide proper incentives to victims for defensive activities, neither compensation nor a tax is appropriate." (Ibid, p. 25). For the argument that if injurers behave efficiently so will the victims, see Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 75-76.
  • 77
    • 0011023256 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the argument that if injurers behave efficiently so will the victims
    • 42 ". . . [T]he victim of a detrimental externality should face a zero charge: The victim should neither be taxed nor compensated for the damages absorbed." (Baumol and Oates, above note 1, p. 23) "To provide proper incentives to victims for defensive activities, neither compensation nor a tax is appropriate." (Ibid, p. 25). For the argument that if injurers behave efficiently so will the victims, see Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 75-76.
  • 78
    • 0004312419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 4
    • 42 ". . . [T]he victim of a detrimental externality should face a zero charge: The victim should neither be taxed nor compensated for the damages absorbed." (Baumol and Oates, above note 1, p. 23) "To provide proper incentives to victims for defensive activities, neither compensation nor a tax is appropriate." (Ibid, p. 25). For the argument that if injurers behave efficiently so will the victims, see Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 75-76.
    • Economic Structure , pp. 75-76
    • Landes1    Posner2
  • 79
    • 0004320812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 7
    • 43 Coase, Social Cost, above note 7, pp. 2, 13, and 41-42.
    • Social Cost , pp. 2
    • Coase1
  • 81
    • 0010960513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although victims may be considered the cause of their own loss by reason of engaging in activity that is susceptible to loss, they do not externalize this loss. They internalize it because they actually suffer it. There are, however, at least two possible types of situations in which victims and injurers can be considered joint generators of externalities. First, victims, like injurers, externalize loss they are unaware of. Second, to avoid a private loss, victims may use resources at a cost higher than the social cost of their loss
    • 45 Although victims may be considered the cause of their own loss by reason of engaging in activity that is susceptible to loss, they do not externalize this loss. They internalize it because they actually suffer it. There are, however, at least two possible types of situations in which victims and injurers can be considered joint generators of externalities. First, victims, like injurers, externalize loss they are unaware of. Second, to avoid a private loss, victims may use resources at a cost higher than the social cost of their loss.
  • 82
    • 0010956153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unless proper rules of mitigation deny an award of damages that would lead to such inefficiencies. It should be noted that these "second-stage" externalities are of a special kind. Their immediate cause is not the activity of the victims but rather the collective organs that impose taxes or liability on injurers
    • 46 Unless proper rules of mitigation deny an award of damages that would lead to such inefficiencies. It should be noted that these "second-stage" externalities are of a special kind. Their immediate cause is not the activity of the victims but rather the collective organs that impose taxes or liability on injurers.
  • 84
    • 0010960322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 7, It is illuminating to examine the "double taxation" complex from the perspective of pecuniary externalities discussed above, in note 35. Baumol has argued that Coase's mistake in his "double taxation" proposal originates in his failure to see that these "second-stage" externalities are pecuniary externalities and therefore should not be internalized (Baumol and Oates, above note 1, pp. 31-32). Yet, Baumol will probably agree with Coase's clarification that victims should only be taxed in the case of injurers' overdeterrence, and only in this case. In other words, he will agree that the "second-stage" pecuniary externalities should be internalized when injurers are overdeterred. This conclusion supports the contention that pecuniary externalities may lead to allocative inefficiency
    • 48 Coase, Social Cost, above note 7, p. 42. It is illuminating to examine the "double taxation" complex from the perspective of pecuniary externalities discussed above, in note 35. Baumol has argued that Coase's mistake in his "double taxation" proposal originates in his failure to see that these "second-stage" externalities are pecuniary externalities and therefore should not be internalized (Baumol and Oates, above note 1, pp. 31-32). Yet, Baumol will probably agree with Coase's clarification that victims should only be taxed in the case of injurers' overdeterrence, and only in this case. In other words, he will agree that the "second-stage" pecuniary externalities should be internalized when injurers are overdeterred. This conclusion supports the contention that pecuniary externalities may lead to allocative inefficiency.
    • Social Cost , pp. 42
    • Coase1
  • 85
    • 0011023049 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 42
    • 49 See Baumol and Oates, above note 42, and W. Baumol, "On Taxation and the Control of Externalities," 62 American Economic Review 307 (1972), p. 309. Coase agrees with Baumol's analysis and with the conclusion that internalization of externalized social cost to injurers is sufficient for optimal resource allocation (Coase, The Firm, the Market, and the Law, above note 7, pp. 181-182. In his article, "Unity in Tort, Contract, and Property: The Model of Precaution," 73 California Law Review 1 (1985), p. 4, Cooter states that ". . . [c]ompensation in its simplest form is inconsistent with double responsibility at the margin." Shavell argues along the same line that "optimal levels of activity will be reached only when victims bear their losses without being compensated, while injurers pay taxes equal to expected harm." (Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 29-30). As to Posner, see below, the first part of Section IV. Calabresi supported the same conclusion in a private conversation. It should be noted, however, that compensation does not necessarily produce inefficiencies. It may do so. See above note 3.
    • Baumol1    Oates2
  • 86
    • 0000578649 scopus 로고
    • On taxation and the control of externalities
    • Coase agrees with Baumol's analysis and with the conclusion that internalization of externalized social cost to injurers is sufficient for optimal resource allocation
    • 49 See Baumol and Oates, above note 42, and W. Baumol, "On Taxation and the Control of Externalities," 62 American Economic Review 307 (1972), p. 309. Coase agrees with Baumol's analysis and with the conclusion that internalization of externalized social cost to injurers is sufficient for optimal resource allocation (Coase, The Firm, the Market, and the Law, above note 7, pp. 181-182. In his article, "Unity in Tort, Contract, and Property: The Model of Precaution," 73 California Law Review 1 (1985), p. 4, Cooter states that ". . . [c]ompensation in its simplest form is inconsistent with double responsibility at the margin." Shavell argues along the same line that "optimal levels of activity will be reached only when victims bear their losses without being compensated, while injurers pay taxes equal to expected harm." (Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 29-30). As to Posner, see below, the first part of Section IV. Calabresi supported the same conclusion in a private conversation. It should be noted, however, that compensation does not necessarily produce inefficiencies. It may do so. See above note 3.
    • (1972) 62 American Economic Review , vol.307 , pp. 309
    • Baumol, W.1
  • 87
    • 0003802548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 7
    • 49 See Baumol and Oates, above note 42, and W. Baumol, "On Taxation and the Control of Externalities," 62 American Economic Review 307 (1972), p. 309. Coase agrees with Baumol's analysis and with the conclusion that internalization of externalized social cost to injurers is sufficient for optimal resource allocation (Coase, The Firm, the Market, and the Law, above note 7, pp. 181-182. In his article, "Unity in Tort, Contract, and Property: The Model of Precaution," 73 California Law Review 1 (1985), p. 4, Cooter states that ". . . [c]ompensation in its simplest form is inconsistent with double responsibility at the margin." Shavell argues along the same line that "optimal levels of activity will be reached only when victims bear their losses without being compensated, while injurers pay taxes equal to expected harm." (Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 29-30). As to Posner, see below, the first part of Section IV. Calabresi supported the same conclusion in a private conversation. It should be noted, however, that compensation does not necessarily produce inefficiencies. It may do so. See above note 3.
    • The Firm, the Market, and the Law , pp. 181-182
    • Coase1
  • 88
    • 67649349232 scopus 로고
    • Unity in tort, contract, and property: The model of precaution
    • Cooter states that ". . . [c]ompensation in its simplest form is inconsistent with double responsibility at the margin." Shavell argues along the same line that "optimal levels of activity will be reached only when victims bear their losses without being compensated, while injurers pay taxes equal to expected harm."
    • 49 See Baumol and Oates, above note 42, and W. Baumol, "On Taxation and the Control of Externalities," 62 American Economic Review 307 (1972), p. 309. Coase agrees with Baumol's analysis and with the conclusion that internalization of externalized social cost to injurers is sufficient for optimal resource allocation (Coase, The Firm, the Market, and the Law, above note 7, pp. 181-182. In his article, "Unity in Tort, Contract, and Property: The Model of Precaution," 73 California Law Review 1 (1985), p. 4, Cooter states that ". . . [c]ompensation in its simplest form is inconsistent with double responsibility at the margin." Shavell argues along the same line that "optimal levels of activity will be reached only when victims bear their losses without being compensated, while injurers pay taxes equal to expected harm." (Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 29-30). As to Posner, see below, the first part of Section IV. Calabresi supported the same conclusion in a private conversation. It should be noted, however, that compensation does not necessarily produce inefficiencies. It may do so. See above note 3.
    • (1985) 73 California Law Review , vol.1 , pp. 4
  • 89
    • 0011005674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20, As to Posner, see below, the first part of Section IV. Calabresi supported the same conclusion in a private conversation. It should be noted, however, that compensation does not necessarily produce inefficiencies. It may do so. See above note 3
    • 49 See Baumol and Oates, above note 42, and W. Baumol, "On Taxation and the Control of Externalities," 62 American Economic Review 307 (1972), p. 309. Coase agrees with Baumol's analysis and with the conclusion that internalization of externalized social cost to injurers is sufficient for optimal resource allocation (Coase, The Firm, the Market, and the Law, above note 7, pp. 181-182. In his article, "Unity in Tort, Contract, and Property: The Model of Precaution," 73 California Law Review 1 (1985), p. 4, Cooter states that ". . . [c]ompensation in its simplest form is inconsistent with double responsibility at the margin." Shavell argues along the same line that "optimal levels of activity will be reached only when victims bear their losses without being compensated, while injurers pay taxes equal to expected harm." (Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 29-30). As to Posner, see below, the first part of Section IV. Calabresi supported the same conclusion in a private conversation. It should be noted, however, that compensation does not necessarily produce inefficiencies. It may do so. See above note 3.
    • Accident Law , pp. 29-30
    • Shavell1
  • 90
    • 0011048663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To avoid these distorting effects, payments to victims should take the form of a lump sum that is conceived by victims as unrelated to their activity. It is hard to see, however, how damages for loss can be disassociated from the activity in which this loss is incurred
    • 50 To avoid these distorting effects, payments to victims should take the form of a lump sum that is conceived by victims as unrelated to their activity. It is hard to see, however, how damages for loss can be disassociated from the activity in which this loss is incurred.
  • 91
    • 0011001234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the case except when the rule of contributory negligence denies compensation
    • 51 This is the case except when the rule of contributory negligence denies compensation.
  • 92
    • 0346581482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Property rules versus liability rules: An economic analysis
    • L. Kaplow and S. Shavell implicitly assume that "harmful externalities" and the harm for which the injurer is liable are basically the same
    • 52 In their recent article "Property Rules versus Liability Rules: An Economic Analysis," 109 Harvard Law Review 715 (1996), p. 723, L. Kaplow and S. Shavell implicitly assume that "harmful externalities" and the harm for which the injurer is liable are basically the same.
    • (1996) 109 Harvard Law Review , vol.715 , pp. 723
  • 93
    • 0004312419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 4
    • 53 Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 85-88 and 96-107; R. A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law (Boston: Little Brown, 1992) pp. 163-167.
    • Economic Structure , pp. 85-88
    • Landes1    Posner2
  • 94
    • 0003774434 scopus 로고
    • Boston: Little Brown
    • 53 Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 85-88 and 96-107; R. A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law (Boston: Little Brown, 1992) pp. 163-167.
    • (1992) Economic Analysis of Law , pp. 163-167
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 95
    • 0004312419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cited previously in note 4, and 48-51
    • 54 Posner actually extends the Hand Formula to cases of nuisance that are governed by the rule of reasonable use, arguing that this rule is basically equivalent to the negligence rule. See Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, (cited previously in note 4), pp. 39 and 48-51.
    • Economic Structure , pp. 39
    • Landes1    Posner2
  • 97
    • 0004312275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 53
    • 56 Posner, Economic Analysis, above note 53, p. 176. See also S. G. Gilles, "Rule-Based Negligence and the Regulation of Activity Levels," 22 Journal of Legal Studies 319 (1992), p. 320.
    • Economic Analysis , pp. 176
    • Posner1
  • 98
    • 67949107133 scopus 로고
    • Rule-based negligence and the regulation of activity levels
    • 56 Posner, Economic Analysis, above note 53, p. 176. See also S. G. Gilles, "Rule-Based Negligence and the Regulation of Activity Levels," 22 Journal of Legal Studies 319 (1992), p. 320.
    • (1992) 22 Journal of Legal Studies , vol.319 , pp. 320
    • Gilles, S.G.1
  • 99
    • 0010954849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whenever prevention by reduction of activity level is less costly than increased care, B overstates private cost. Costs of prevention may be understated if the burden of increased care leads to a reduction in activity level as well, and such reduction imposes an extra cost on the injurer
    • 57 Whenever prevention by reduction of activity level is less costly than increased care, B overstates private cost. Costs of prevention may be understated if the burden of increased care leads to a reduction in activity level as well, and such reduction imposes an extra cost on the injurer.
  • 100
    • 0010961035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The preliminary requirement that internalization will take place only if B is lower than L (PL > B) may occasionally prevent internalization of loss that exceeds social cost. This, however, will happen only when B exceeds the social cost of prevention in the same way that L exceeds the social cost of the private loss. Moreover, when B does act to bar internalization of private loss that exceeds externalized social cost it also bars internalization of the social cost itself, and therefore may lead to the "overkill" of injurers' underdeterrence. B will also lead to injurers' underdeterrence when it screens efficient internalization by overstating the social cost of prevention
    • 58 The preliminary requirement that internalization will take place only if B is lower than L (PL > B) may occasionally prevent internalization of loss that exceeds social cost. This, however, will happen only when B exceeds the social cost of prevention in the same way that L exceeds the social cost of the private loss. Moreover, when B does act to bar internalization of private loss that exceeds externalized social cost it also bars internalization of the social cost itself, and therefore may lead to the "overkill" of injurers' underdeterrence. B will also lead to injurers' underdeterrence when it screens efficient internalization by overstating the social cost of prevention.
  • 101
    • 0004312275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 53
    • 59 See Posner, Economic Analysis, above note 53, pp. 175-180; Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 64-71.
    • Economic Analysis , pp. 175-180
    • Posner1
  • 102
    • 0004312419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 4
    • 59 See Posner, Economic Analysis, above note 53, pp. 175-180; Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 64-71.
    • Economic Structure , pp. 64-71
    • Landes1    Posner2
  • 103
    • 0010995527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is actually what Gilles has suggested with regard to B. Gilles, above note 56. It should be noted, however, that when activity levels and the welfare of third parties are integrated directly into L and B, the adjusted formula may deny internalization when the Hand Formula allows it. Liability under the adjusted formula, in other words, is not strict liability
    • 60 This is actually what Gilles has suggested with regard to B. Gilles, above note 56. It should be noted, however, that when activity levels and the welfare of third parties are integrated directly into L and B, the adjusted formula may deny internalization when the Hand Formula allows it. Liability under the adjusted formula, in other words, is not strict liability.
  • 104
    • 0011038662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The defense of contributory negligence, let us recall, also ignores activity levels
    • 61 The defense of contributory negligence, let us recall, also ignores activity levels.
  • 105
    • 0010988058 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strict liability, on the other hand, may improve internalization when the Hand Formula leads to underdeterrence because B, by ignoring activity levels, overstates the social cost of prevention
    • 62 Strict liability, on the other hand, may improve internalization when the Hand Formula leads to underdeterrence because B, by ignoring activity levels, overstates the social cost of prevention.
  • 106
    • 0004312275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 53
    • 63 See Economic Analysis, above note 53, p. 185, and Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, p. 68.
    • Economic Analysis , pp. 185
  • 107
    • 0004312419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 4
    • 63 See Economic Analysis, above note 53, p. 185, and Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, p. 68.
    • Economic Structure , pp. 68
    • Landes1    Posner2
  • 108
    • 0004312419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 4
    • 64 Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, p. 71. See also Gilles, above note 56, p. 320, summarizing Posner's approach to activity levels.
    • Economic Structure , pp. 71
    • Landes1    Posner2
  • 109
    • 0011048664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 56, summarizing Posner's approach to activity levels
    • 64 Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, p. 71. See also Gilles, above note 56, p. 320, summarizing Posner's approach to activity levels.
    • Gilles1
  • 110
    • 0003802548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 7
    • 65 Coase observed that proposals to design optimal systems of internalization "are the stuff that dreams are made of." (Coase, The Firm, the Market, and the Law, above note 7, p. 185). He also remarked that it would "require a detailed knowledge of individual preferences, and I am unable to imagine how the data needed for such a taxation system could be assembled. (Coase, Social Cost, above note 4, p. 41). Baumol too shares this view, acknowledging that "we do not know how to calculate the required taxes and subsidies and we do not know how to approximate them by trial and error." (Baumol, Control of Externalities, above note 50, p. 318).
    • The Firm, the Market, and the Law , pp. 185
    • Coase1
  • 111
    • 0004320812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 4
    • 65 Coase observed that proposals to design optimal systems of internalization "are the stuff that dreams are made of." (Coase, The Firm, the Market, and the Law, above note 7, p. 185). He also remarked that it would "require a detailed knowledge of individual preferences, and I am unable to imagine how the data needed for such a taxation system could be assembled. (Coase, Social Cost, above note 4, p. 41). Baumol too shares this view, acknowledging that "we do not know how to calculate the required taxes and subsidies and we do not know how to approximate them by trial and error." (Baumol, Control of Externalities, above note 50, p. 318).
    • Social Cost , pp. 41
    • Coase1
  • 112
    • 0011028841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 50
    • 65 Coase observed that proposals to design optimal systems of internalization "are the stuff that dreams are made of." (Coase, The Firm, the Market, and the Law, above note 7, p. 185). He also remarked that it would "require a detailed knowledge of individual preferences, and I am unable to imagine how the data needed for such a taxation system could be assembled. (Coase, Social Cost, above note 4, p. 41). Baumol too shares this view, acknowledging that "we do not know how to calculate the required taxes and subsidies and we do not know how to approximate them by trial and error." (Baumol, Control of Externalities, above note 50, p. 318).
    • Control of Externalities , pp. 318
    • Baumol1
  • 113
    • 0010955092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the text accompanying note 13 above
    • 66 See the text accompanying note 13 above.
  • 114
    • 0004312419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such an assumption is implicit in Posner's argument that positive externalities can be integrated into his negligence model without undermining it above note 4
    • 67 Such an assumption is implicit in Posner's argument that positive externalities can be integrated into his negligence model without undermining it (Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, p. 69).
    • Economic Structure , pp. 69
    • Landes1    Posner2
  • 115
    • 0011006425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As emphasized by Coase, above note 65
    • 68 As emphasized by Coase, above note 65.
  • 116
    • 0004312419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nor has Posner provided a satisfactory solution to another aspect of the Gap: the distorting effect of compensatory damages. Posner acknowledges that the award of damages to victims leads to their underdeterrence, and that tort law is unable to achieve optimal deterrence because it compensates victims. above note 4, following Shavell who argued that neither negligence nor strict liability can achieve optimal internalization
    • 69 Nor has Posner provided a satisfactory solution to another aspect of the Gap: the distorting effect of compensatory damages. Posner acknowledges that the award of damages to victims leads to their underdeterrence, and that tort law is unable to achieve optimal deterrence because it compensates victims. See Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 69-70, following Shavell who argued that neither negligence nor strict liability can achieve optimal internalization (Shavell, above note 20, pp. 29-30). Posner nevertheless supports the award of compensatory damages that are "at least as great as L in the Hand Formula" . . . "to give the victim an incentive to sue, which is essential to the maintenance of the tort system as an effective, credible deterrent to negligence." (Posner, Economic Analysis, above note 53, p. 191). This explanation is questionable. In many cases, much smaller awards will provide sufficient incentives to sue, and the smaller the award, the smaller the ensuing inefficiencies. Furthermore, when the loss is continuous, as in nuisance, victims are motivated to sue so as to prevent or reduce future loss, regardless of compensation or damages awards.
    • Economic Structure , pp. 69-70
    • Landes1    Posner2
  • 117
    • 0011005675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20, Posner nevertheless supports the award of compensatory damages that are "at least as great as L in the Hand Formula" . . . "to give the victim an incentive to sue, which is essential to the maintenance of the tort system as an effective, credible deterrent to negligence."
    • 69 Nor has Posner provided a satisfactory solution to another aspect of the Gap: the distorting effect of compensatory damages. Posner acknowledges that the award of damages to victims leads to their underdeterrence, and that tort law is unable to achieve optimal deterrence because it compensates victims. See Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 69-70, following Shavell who argued that neither negligence nor strict liability can achieve optimal internalization (Shavell, above note 20, pp. 29-30). Posner nevertheless supports the award of compensatory damages that are "at least as great as L in the Hand Formula" . . . "to give the victim an incentive to sue, which is essential to the maintenance of the tort system as an effective, credible deterrent to negligence." (Posner, Economic Analysis, above note 53, p. 191). This explanation is questionable. In many cases, much smaller awards will provide sufficient incentives to sue, and the smaller the award, the smaller the ensuing inefficiencies. Furthermore, when the loss is continuous, as in nuisance, victims are motivated to sue so as to prevent or reduce future loss, regardless of compensation or damages awards.
    • Shavell1
  • 118
    • 0004312275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 53, This explanation is questionable. In many cases, much smaller awards will provide sufficient incentives to sue, and the smaller the award, the smaller the ensuing inefficiencies. Furthermore, when the loss is continuous, as in nuisance, victims are motivated to sue so as to prevent or reduce future loss, regardless of compensation or damages awards
    • 69 Nor has Posner provided a satisfactory solution to another aspect of the Gap: the distorting effect of compensatory damages. Posner acknowledges that the award of damages to victims leads to their underdeterrence, and that tort law is unable to achieve optimal deterrence because it compensates victims. See Landes and Posner, Economic Structure, above note 4, pp. 69-70, following Shavell who argued that neither negligence nor strict liability can achieve optimal internalization (Shavell, above note 20, pp. 29-30). Posner nevertheless supports the award of compensatory damages that are "at least as great as L in the Hand Formula" . . . "to give the victim an incentive to sue, which is essential to the maintenance of the tort system as an effective, credible deterrent to negligence." (Posner, Economic Analysis, above note 53, p. 191). This explanation is questionable. In many cases, much smaller awards will provide sufficient incentives to sue, and the smaller the award, the smaller the ensuing inefficiencies. Furthermore, when the loss is continuous, as in nuisance, victims are motivated to sue so as to prevent or reduce future loss, regardless of compensation or damages awards.
    • Economic Analysis , pp. 191
  • 119
    • 0010955093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See above in the first part of Section II
    • 70 See above in the first part of Section II.
  • 120
    • 0010955320 scopus 로고
    • Efficiency of comparative negligence: A game theoretic analysis
    • On the debate as to whether comparative negligence is more efficient than contributory negligence or vice versa
    • 71 On the debate as to whether comparative negligence is more efficient than contributory negligence or vice versa see T. Y. Chung, "Efficiency of Comparative Negligence: A Game Theoretic Analysis," 22 Journal of Legal Studies 395 (1993); D. Orr, "The Superiority of Comparative Negligence: Another Vote," 20 Journal of Legal Studies 119 (1991). It is often argued that there is no difference between the outcomes under comparative negligence and contributory negligence because, under both rules, once injurers are induced to take due care, so will victims, knowing that otherwise they alone will incur the whole loss. See Posner, Economic Analysis, above note 4, pp. 169-172; Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 15-16. Yet, this line of reasoning is based on the assumption that the internalized private loss equals the social cost, so that injurers are not overdeterred. My point is that when private loss exceeds social cost, it seems that only comparative negligence can avoid overdeterrence of injurers. Assume, for example, that private loss is 100, that the social cost is 80 because the victim can reduce his expected private loss to 70 by investing 10, and that the injurer's only alternative is to prevent the loss of 100 by investing 90. By reducing damages to 80, comparative negligence can create the proper incentives for both parties: The victim will invest 10 to avoid the loss of 30, knowing that the injurer will not invest 90 to avoid damages of 80. In contrast, under contributory negligence, the victim will assume that the injurer will invest 90 to avoid loss and damages of 100 and, therefore, will have no incentives to mitigate a private loss that the injurer will prevent. To avoid this inefficiency, contributory negligence should be interpreted as denying liability even when the victim can prevent only a small fraction of his loss, but such an interpretation injects comparative aspects into the "all or nothing" defense.
    • (1993) 22 Journal of Legal Studies , vol.395
    • Chung, T.Y.1
  • 121
    • 0010960514 scopus 로고
    • The superiority of comparative negligence: Another vote
    • It is often argued that there is no difference between the outcomes under comparative negligence and contributory negligence because, under both rules, once injurers are induced to take due care, so will victims, knowing that otherwise they alone will incur the whole loss
    • 71 On the debate as to whether comparative negligence is more efficient than contributory negligence or vice versa see T. Y. Chung, "Efficiency of Comparative Negligence: A Game Theoretic Analysis," 22 Journal of Legal Studies 395 (1993); D. Orr, "The Superiority of Comparative Negligence: Another Vote," 20 Journal of Legal Studies 119 (1991). It is often argued that there is no difference between the outcomes under comparative negligence and contributory negligence because, under both rules, once injurers are induced to take due care, so will victims, knowing that otherwise they alone will incur the whole loss. See Posner, Economic Analysis, above note 4, pp. 169-172; Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 15-16. Yet, this line of reasoning is based on the assumption that the internalized private loss equals the social cost, so that injurers are not overdeterred. My point is that when private loss exceeds social cost, it seems that only comparative negligence can avoid overdeterrence of injurers. Assume, for example, that private loss is 100, that the social cost is 80 because the victim can reduce his expected private loss to 70 by investing 10, and that the injurer's only alternative is to prevent the loss of 100 by investing 90. By reducing damages to 80, comparative negligence can create the proper incentives for both parties: The victim will invest 10 to avoid the loss of 30, knowing that the injurer will not invest 90 to avoid damages of 80. In contrast, under contributory negligence, the victim will assume that the injurer will invest 90 to avoid loss and damages of 100 and, therefore, will have no incentives to mitigate a private loss that the injurer will prevent. To avoid this inefficiency, contributory negligence should be interpreted as denying liability even when the victim can prevent only a small fraction of his loss, but such an interpretation injects comparative aspects into the "all or nothing" defense.
    • (1991) 20 Journal of Legal Studies , vol.119
    • Orr, D.1
  • 122
    • 0004312275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 4
    • 71 On the debate as to whether comparative negligence is more efficient than contributory negligence or vice versa see T. Y. Chung, "Efficiency of Comparative Negligence: A Game Theoretic Analysis," 22 Journal of Legal Studies 395 (1993); D. Orr, "The Superiority of Comparative Negligence: Another Vote," 20 Journal of Legal Studies 119 (1991). It is often argued that there is no difference between the outcomes under comparative negligence and contributory negligence because, under both rules, once injurers are induced to take due care, so will victims, knowing that otherwise they alone will incur the whole loss. See Posner, Economic Analysis, above note 4, pp. 169-172; Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 15-16. Yet, this line of reasoning is based on the assumption that the internalized private loss equals the social cost, so that injurers are not overdeterred. My point is that when private loss exceeds social cost, it seems that only comparative negligence can avoid overdeterrence of injurers. Assume, for example, that private loss is 100, that the social cost is 80 because the victim can reduce his expected private loss to 70 by investing 10, and that the injurer's only alternative is to prevent the loss of 100 by investing 90. By reducing damages to 80, comparative negligence can create the proper incentives for both parties: The victim will invest 10 to avoid the loss of 30, knowing that the injurer will not invest 90 to avoid damages of 80. In contrast, under contributory negligence, the victim will assume that the injurer will invest 90 to avoid loss and damages of 100 and, therefore, will have no incentives to mitigate a private loss that the injurer will prevent. To avoid this inefficiency, contributory negligence should be interpreted as denying liability even when the victim can prevent only a small fraction of his loss, but such an interpretation injects comparative aspects into the "all or nothing" defense.
    • Economic Analysis , pp. 169-172
    • Posner1
  • 123
    • 0004320116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 71 On the debate as to whether comparative negligence is more efficient than contributory negligence or vice versa see T. Y. Chung, "Efficiency of Comparative Negligence: A Game Theoretic Analysis," 22 Journal of Legal Studies 395 (1993); D. Orr, "The Superiority of Comparative Negligence: Another Vote," 20 Journal of Legal Studies 119 (1991). It is often argued that there is no difference between the outcomes under comparative negligence and contributory negligence because, under both rules, once injurers are induced to take due care, so will victims, knowing that otherwise they alone will incur the whole loss. See Posner, Economic Analysis, above note 4, pp. 169-172; Shavell, Accident Law, above note 20, pp. 15-16. Yet, this line of reasoning is based on the assumption that the internalized private loss equals the social cost, so that injurers are not overdeterred. My point is that when private loss exceeds social cost, it seems that only comparative negligence can avoid overdeterrence of injurers. Assume, for example, that private loss is 100, that the social cost is 80 because the victim can reduce his expected private loss to 70 by investing 10, and that the injurer's only alternative is to prevent the loss of 100 by investing 90. By reducing damages to 80, comparative negligence can create the proper incentives for both parties: The victim will invest 10 to avoid the loss of 30, knowing that the injurer will not invest 90 to avoid damages of 80. In contrast, under contributory negligence, the victim will assume that the injurer will invest 90 to avoid loss and damages of 100 and, therefore, will have no incentives to mitigate a private loss that the injurer will prevent. To avoid this inefficiency, contributory negligence should be interpreted as denying liability even when the victim can prevent only a small fraction of his loss, but such an interpretation injects comparative aspects into the "all or nothing" defense.
    • Accident Law , pp. 15-16
    • Shavell1
  • 125
    • 0010954850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 73 Ibid, pp. 251-255; Bishop, Economic Loss, above note 20; and Goldberg, Oil Spill, above note 20.
    • Economic Structure , pp. 251-255
  • 126
    • 0004325086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20
    • 73 Ibid, pp. 251-255; Bishop, Economic Loss, above note 20; and Goldberg, Oil Spill, above note 20.
    • Economic Loss
    • Bishop1
  • 127
    • 0004304377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20
    • 73 Ibid, pp. 251-255; Bishop, Economic Loss, above note 20; and Goldberg, Oil Spill, above note 20.
    • Oil Spill
    • Goldberg1
  • 131
    • 0010988216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Above note 37 and accompanying text
    • 77 Above note 37 and accompanying text.
  • 132
    • 0004310911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 17, 360 Rabin, above note 24
    • 78 See Bishop and Sutton, Pecuniary Loss Rule, above note 17, pp. 360 and 355-361, and 367; Rabin, above note 24; Goldberg, Oil Spill, above note 20, pp. 24-34. Yet, trying to justify the exclusionary rule, Goldberg suggests that "it is likely that as the size of the class of indirect claimants increases, so too will the gap between the measured damages and the actual social harm" (p. 34). It is unclear, however, why and how the size of an affected group is related to the gap between private loss and social cost.
    • Pecuniary Loss Rule
    • Bishop1    Sutton2
  • 133
    • 0004304377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20, Yet, trying to justify the exclusionary rule, Goldberg suggests that "it is likely that as the size of the class of indirect claimants increases, so too will the gap between the measured damages and the actual social harm" (p. 34). It is unclear, however, why and how the size of an affected group is related to the gap between private loss and social cost
    • 78 See Bishop and Sutton, Pecuniary Loss Rule, above note 17, pp. 360 and 355-361, and 367; Rabin, above note 24; Goldberg, Oil Spill, above note 20, pp. 24-34. Yet, trying to justify the exclusionary rule, Goldberg suggests that "it is likely that as the size of the class of indirect claimants increases, so too will the gap between the measured damages and the actual social harm" (p. 34). It is unclear, however, why and how the size of an affected group is related to the gap between private loss and social cost.
    • Oil Spill , pp. 24-34
    • Goldberg1
  • 134
    • 0004346567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 21, these exceptions allow recovery in cases of "joint venture," namely, "where the use value of the damaged property is shared between the property owner and the relational loss plaintiff" (p. 244); in cases of "transferred loss," namely, where "the property owner is able to allocate to the plaintiff by contract the risk of property damage and consequential loss" (p. 253); and in the few cases where the economic loss is consequent on damage to a public resource (p. 259)
    • 79 According to Feldthusen, Economic Negligence, above note 21, these exceptions allow recovery in cases of "joint venture," namely, "where the use value of the damaged property is shared between the property owner and the relational loss plaintiff" (p. 244); in cases of "transferred loss," namely, where "the property owner is able to allocate to the plaintiff by contract the risk of property damage and consequential loss" (p. 253); and in the few cases where the economic loss is consequent on damage to a public resource (p. 259).
    • Economic Negligence
    • Feldthusen1
  • 135
    • 0010961496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 21, Feldthusen's fourth category, product defect economic loss, will not be discussed here because such loss is internalized under the laws of contract and sale
    • 80 Feldthusen, Economic Negligence, above note 21, pp. 2-3 and 132-133. Feldthusen's fourth category, product defect economic loss, will not be discussed here because such loss is internalized under the laws of contract and sale. See Ibid, pp. 171-205.
    • Economic Negligence , pp. 2-3
    • Feldthusen1
  • 136
    • 0011006426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 80 Feldthusen, Economic Negligence, above note 21, pp. 2-3 and 132-133. Feldthusen's fourth category, product defect economic loss, will not be discussed here because such loss is internalized under the laws of contract and sale. See Ibid, pp. 171-205.
    • Economic Negligence , pp. 171-205
  • 137
    • 0004325086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 20, Bishop estimated that, normally, misrepresentation causes some social cost, which is lower than private loss
    • 81 See Bishop, Economic Loss, above note 20, p. 28. Bishop estimated that, normally, misrepresentation causes some social cost, which is lower than private loss.
    • Economic Loss , pp. 28
    • Bishop1
  • 138
    • 0004346567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 21. The leading case is Caparo Industries plc v. Dickman [1990] 1 All E. R. 568
    • 82 Feldthusen, Economic Negligence, above note 21, pp. 37-52 and 131-132. The leading case is Caparo Industries plc v. Dickman [1990] 1 All E. R. 568.
    • Economic Negligence , pp. 37-52
    • Feldthusen1
  • 139
    • 67949088823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • above note 35
    • 83 Bishop argued that common law rules concerning misrepresentation may be justified by the criterion of economic efficiency. Bishop, Misrepresentation, above note 35. Although this argument seems to contradict the above conclusion, this is not so. Bishop's analysis was based on the assumption that losses in negligent misrepresentation "represent real costs to society" (p. 379). As indicated in note 82 above, Bishop later acknowledged that these losses do not normally overlap the social cost.
    • Misrepresentation
    • Bishop1
  • 140
    • 0011030143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Transportation and the manufacture of products, for example, are activities that inflict significant damage and losses other than purely economic ones. Obviously, they also generate significant activity-related benefits. The exclusionary rule, however, is unable to offset these benefits against significant losses that are not purely economic
    • 84 Transportation and the manufacture of products, for example, are activities that inflict significant damage and losses other than purely economic ones. Obviously, they also generate significant activity-related benefits. The exclusionary rule, however, is unable to offset these benefits against significant losses that are not purely economic.
  • 141
    • 0011038663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For other explanations see above note 35
    • 85 For other explanations see above note 35.
  • 142
    • 0011001236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See above note 65 and the accompanying text
    • 86 See above note 65 and the accompanying text.
  • 143
    • 0010955094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See above note 13 and accompanying text
    • 87 See above note 13 and accompanying text.
  • 146
    • 0004310911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When, for example, each victim in a large group of victims suffers an insignificant private loss, the total loss may be substantial, but internalization will not take place because victims lack incentives to sue or are even unaware of their loss. This is why the loss of consumer surplus, which is a social cost, is usually not internalized by tort law. For consumer surplus as an ingredient of social cost above note 17
    • 90 When, for example, each victim in a large group of victims suffers an insignificant private loss, the total loss may be substantial, but internalization will not take place because victims lack incentives to sue or are even unaware of their loss. This is why the loss of consumer surplus, which is a social cost, is usually not internalized by tort law. For consumer surplus as an ingredient of social cost see Bishop and Sutton, Pecuniary Loss Rule, above note 17, pp. 353-354.
    • Pecuniary Loss Rule , pp. 353-354
    • Bishop1    Sutton2
  • 147
    • 0010956154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strict liability, for example, is justified with regard to activities that inflict physical damage while generating limited welfare for third parties. In the absence of significant loss-related gains and activity-related benefits, and provided that the victims' ability to mitigate their loss is limited, private loss basically corresponds with externalized social cost, and strict liability is required for effective internalization. In contrast, liability should be restrained, for example, in the context of tort-related injuries resulting from prescription drugs, where activity-related benefits are large, or with regard to cases where pecuniary losses of interrupted activities are offset by loss-related gains of other activities
    • 91 Strict liability, for example, is justified with regard to activities that inflict physical damage while generating limited welfare for third parties. In the absence of significant loss-related gains and activity-related benefits, and provided that the victims' ability to mitigate their loss is limited, private loss basically corresponds with externalized social cost, and strict liability is required for effective internalization. In contrast, liability should be restrained, for example, in the context of tort-related injuries resulting from prescription drugs, where activity-related benefits are large, or with regard to cases where pecuniary losses of interrupted activities are offset by loss-related gains of other activities.
  • 148
    • 0010961036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • G. T. Schwartz distinguishes between "positive" economic writings in support of the tort law internalization system, and "negative" analysts claiming that tort law has gone much too far. above note 6
    • 92 G. T. Schwartz distinguishes between "positive" economic writings in support of the tort law internalization system, and "negative" analysts claiming that tort law has gone much too far. Schwartz, above note 6, pp. 380-381.
    • Schwartz1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.