메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 16, Issue 5, 1997, Pages 507-528

Retributivism, consequentialism, and the intrinsic goodness of punishment

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0031530271     PISSN: 01675249     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/3505018     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (38)

References (73)
  • 1
    • 0041719912 scopus 로고
    • The Renaissance of Retribution - An Examination of Doing Justice
    • footnote omitted
    • "[R]etribution is suddenly being seen by thinkers of all political persuasions as perhaps the strongest ground, after all, upon which to base a system of punishment." Martin Gardner, "The Renaissance of Retribution - An Examination of Doing Justice," Wisc. L. Rev. (1976): 784 (footnote omitted). See also Robert Satter, Doing Justice: A Trial Judge at Work (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1990), pp. 170-171; James Q. Wilson & Richard Herrnstein, Crime and Human Nature (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1985), pp. 496-497; Jeffrey Leigh Sedgwick, "Reason, Anger, and Retribution," in Fred Baumann & Kenneth Jensen (eds.), Issues in Criminal Justice (Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 1989), p. 41; Michael Tonry and Norval Morris, "Sentencing Reform in America," in Gordon Hawkins & Franklin Zimring (eds.), The Pursuit of Criminal Justice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), pp. 254-255.
    • (1976) Wisc. L. Rev. , pp. 784
    • Gardner, M.1
  • 2
    • 0011497865 scopus 로고
    • New York: Simon and Schuster
    • "[R]etribution is suddenly being seen by thinkers of all political persuasions as perhaps the strongest ground, after all, upon which to base a system of punishment." Martin Gardner, "The Renaissance of Retribution - An Examination of Doing Justice," Wisc. L. Rev. (1976): 784 (footnote omitted). See also Robert Satter, Doing Justice: A Trial Judge at Work (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1990), pp. 170-171; James Q. Wilson & Richard Herrnstein, Crime and Human Nature (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1985), pp. 496-497; Jeffrey Leigh Sedgwick, "Reason, Anger, and Retribution," in Fred Baumann & Kenneth Jensen (eds.), Issues in Criminal Justice (Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 1989), p. 41; Michael Tonry and Norval Morris, "Sentencing Reform in America," in Gordon Hawkins & Franklin Zimring (eds.), The Pursuit of Criminal Justice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), pp. 254-255.
    • (1990) Doing Justice: A Trial Judge at Work , pp. 170-171
    • Satter, R.1
  • 3
    • 0003584369 scopus 로고
    • New York: Simon and Schuster
    • "[R]etribution is suddenly being seen by thinkers of all political persuasions as perhaps the strongest ground, after all, upon which to base a system of punishment." Martin Gardner, "The Renaissance of Retribution - An Examination of Doing Justice," Wisc. L. Rev. (1976): 784 (footnote omitted). See also Robert Satter, Doing Justice: A Trial Judge at Work (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1990), pp. 170-171; James Q. Wilson & Richard Herrnstein, Crime and Human Nature (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1985), pp. 496-497; Jeffrey Leigh Sedgwick, "Reason, Anger, and Retribution," in Fred Baumann & Kenneth Jensen (eds.), Issues in Criminal Justice (Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 1989), p. 41; Michael Tonry and Norval Morris, "Sentencing Reform in America," in Gordon Hawkins & Franklin Zimring (eds.), The Pursuit of Criminal Justice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), pp. 254-255.
    • (1985) Crime and Human Nature , pp. 496-497
    • Wilson, J.Q.1    Herrnstein, R.2
  • 4
    • 0347508234 scopus 로고
    • Reason, Anger, and Retribution
    • Fred Baumann & Kenneth Jensen (eds.), Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press
    • "[R]etribution is suddenly being seen by thinkers of all political persuasions as perhaps the strongest ground, after all, upon which to base a system of punishment." Martin Gardner, "The Renaissance of Retribution - An Examination of Doing Justice," Wisc. L. Rev. (1976): 784 (footnote omitted). See also Robert Satter, Doing Justice: A Trial Judge at Work (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1990), pp. 170-171; James Q. Wilson & Richard Herrnstein, Crime and Human Nature (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1985), pp. 496-497; Jeffrey Leigh Sedgwick, "Reason, Anger, and Retribution," in Fred Baumann & Kenneth Jensen (eds.), Issues in Criminal Justice (Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 1989), p. 41; Michael Tonry and Norval Morris, "Sentencing Reform in America," in Gordon Hawkins & Franklin Zimring (eds.), The Pursuit of Criminal Justice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), pp. 254-255.
    • (1989) Issues in Criminal Justice , pp. 41
    • Sedgwick, J.L.1
  • 5
    • 0346877784 scopus 로고
    • Sentencing Reform in America
    • Gordon Hawkins & Franklin Zimring (eds.), Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • "[R]etribution is suddenly being seen by thinkers of all political persuasions as perhaps the strongest ground, after all, upon which to base a system of punishment." Martin Gardner, "The Renaissance of Retribution - An Examination of Doing Justice," Wisc. L. Rev. (1976): 784 (footnote omitted). See also Robert Satter, Doing Justice: A Trial Judge at Work (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1990), pp. 170-171; James Q. Wilson & Richard Herrnstein, Crime and Human Nature (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1985), pp. 496-497; Jeffrey Leigh Sedgwick, "Reason, Anger, and Retribution," in Fred Baumann & Kenneth Jensen (eds.), Issues in Criminal Justice (Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 1989), p. 41; Michael Tonry and Norval Morris, "Sentencing Reform in America," in Gordon Hawkins & Franklin Zimring (eds.), The Pursuit of Criminal Justice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), pp. 254-255.
    • (1984) The Pursuit of Criminal Justice , pp. 254-255
    • Tonry, M.1    Morris, N.2
  • 6
    • 0041161623 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See, e.g., R.A. Duff, Trials and Punishments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. 195; Igor Primoratz, Justifying Legal Punishment (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International, 1989), p. 12; Nigel Walker, Why Punish? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 7; Lawrence Alexander, "The Doomsday Machine: Proportionality, Punishment, and Prevention," The Monist 63 (1980): 199; J.D. Mabbott, "Punishment," Mind 48 (1939): 152-167; H.J. McCloskey, "A Non-Utilitarian Approach to Punishment," Inquiry 8 (1965): 239-255; Jeffrie Murphy, "Three Mistakes About Retributivism," Analysis 31 (1971): 166-169; Lloyd Weinreb, "Desert, Punishment, and Criminal Responsibility," Law and Contemporary Problems 49 (1986): 47.
    • (1986) Trials and Punishments , pp. 195
    • Duff, R.A.1
  • 7
    • 0002338716 scopus 로고
    • Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International
    • See, e.g., R.A. Duff, Trials and Punishments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. 195; Igor Primoratz, Justifying Legal Punishment (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International, 1989), p. 12; Nigel Walker, Why Punish? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 7; Lawrence Alexander, "The Doomsday Machine: Proportionality, Punishment, and Prevention," The Monist 63 (1980): 199; J.D. Mabbott, "Punishment," Mind 48 (1939): 152-167; H.J. McCloskey, "A Non-Utilitarian Approach to Punishment," Inquiry 8 (1965): 239-255; Jeffrie Murphy, "Three Mistakes About Retributivism," Analysis 31 (1971): 166-169; Lloyd Weinreb, "Desert, Punishment, and Criminal Responsibility," Law and Contemporary Problems 49 (1986): 47.
    • (1989) Justifying Legal Punishment , pp. 12
    • Primoratz, I.1
  • 8
    • 0004241547 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See, e.g., R.A. Duff, Trials and Punishments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. 195; Igor Primoratz, Justifying Legal Punishment (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International, 1989), p. 12; Nigel Walker, Why Punish? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 7; Lawrence Alexander, "The Doomsday Machine: Proportionality, Punishment, and Prevention," The Monist 63 (1980): 199; J.D. Mabbott, "Punishment," Mind 48 (1939): 152-167; H.J. McCloskey, "A Non-Utilitarian Approach to Punishment," Inquiry 8 (1965): 239-255; Jeffrie Murphy, "Three Mistakes About Retributivism," Analysis 31 (1971): 166-169; Lloyd Weinreb, "Desert, Punishment, and Criminal Responsibility," Law and Contemporary Problems 49 (1986): 47.
    • (1991) Why Punish? , pp. 7
    • Walker, N.1
  • 9
    • 0041161565 scopus 로고
    • The Doomsday Machine: Proportionality, Punishment, and Prevention
    • See, e.g., R.A. Duff, Trials and Punishments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. 195; Igor Primoratz, Justifying Legal Punishment (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International, 1989), p. 12; Nigel Walker, Why Punish? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 7; Lawrence Alexander, "The Doomsday Machine: Proportionality, Punishment, and Prevention," The Monist 63 (1980): 199; J.D. Mabbott, "Punishment," Mind 48 (1939): 152-167; H.J. McCloskey, "A Non-Utilitarian Approach to Punishment," Inquiry 8 (1965): 239-255; Jeffrie Murphy, "Three Mistakes About Retributivism," Analysis 31 (1971): 166-169; Lloyd Weinreb, "Desert, Punishment, and Criminal Responsibility," Law and Contemporary Problems 49 (1986): 47.
    • (1980) The Monist , vol.63 , pp. 199
    • Alexander, L.1
  • 10
    • 0348138290 scopus 로고
    • Punishment
    • See, e.g., R.A. Duff, Trials and Punishments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. 195; Igor Primoratz, Justifying Legal Punishment (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International, 1989), p. 12; Nigel Walker, Why Punish? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 7; Lawrence Alexander, "The Doomsday Machine: Proportionality, Punishment, and Prevention," The Monist 63 (1980): 199; J.D. Mabbott, "Punishment," Mind 48 (1939): 152-167; H.J. McCloskey, "A Non-Utilitarian Approach to Punishment," Inquiry 8 (1965): 239-255; Jeffrie Murphy, "Three Mistakes About Retributivism," Analysis 31 (1971): 166-169; Lloyd Weinreb, "Desert, Punishment, and Criminal Responsibility," Law and Contemporary Problems 49 (1986): 47.
    • (1939) Mind , vol.48 , pp. 152-167
    • Mabbott, J.D.1
  • 11
    • 34248983996 scopus 로고
    • A Non-Utilitarian Approach to Punishment
    • See, e.g., R.A. Duff, Trials and Punishments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. 195; Igor Primoratz, Justifying Legal Punishment (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International, 1989), p. 12; Nigel Walker, Why Punish? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 7; Lawrence Alexander, "The Doomsday Machine: Proportionality, Punishment, and Prevention," The Monist 63 (1980): 199; J.D. Mabbott, "Punishment," Mind 48 (1939): 152-167; H.J. McCloskey, "A Non-Utilitarian Approach to Punishment," Inquiry 8 (1965): 239-255; Jeffrie Murphy, "Three Mistakes About Retributivism," Analysis 31 (1971): 166-169; Lloyd Weinreb, "Desert, Punishment, and Criminal Responsibility," Law and Contemporary Problems 49 (1986): 47.
    • (1965) Inquiry , vol.8 , pp. 239-255
    • McCloskey, H.J.1
  • 12
    • 84921543688 scopus 로고
    • Three Mistakes about Retributivism
    • See, e.g., R.A. Duff, Trials and Punishments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. 195; Igor Primoratz, Justifying Legal Punishment (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International, 1989), p. 12; Nigel Walker, Why Punish? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 7; Lawrence Alexander, "The Doomsday Machine: Proportionality, Punishment, and Prevention," The Monist 63 (1980): 199; J.D. Mabbott, "Punishment," Mind 48 (1939): 152-167; H.J. McCloskey, "A Non-Utilitarian Approach to Punishment," Inquiry 8 (1965): 239-255; Jeffrie Murphy, "Three Mistakes About Retributivism," Analysis 31 (1971): 166-169; Lloyd Weinreb, "Desert, Punishment, and Criminal Responsibility," Law and Contemporary Problems 49 (1986): 47.
    • (1971) Analysis , vol.31 , pp. 166-169
    • Murphy, J.1
  • 13
    • 84935170246 scopus 로고
    • Desert, Punishment, and Criminal Responsibility
    • See, e.g., R.A. Duff, Trials and Punishments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. 195; Igor Primoratz, Justifying Legal Punishment (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International, 1989), p. 12; Nigel Walker, Why Punish? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 7; Lawrence Alexander, "The Doomsday Machine: Proportionality, Punishment, and Prevention," The Monist 63 (1980): 199; J.D. Mabbott, "Punishment," Mind 48 (1939): 152-167; H.J. McCloskey, "A Non-Utilitarian Approach to Punishment," Inquiry 8 (1965): 239-255; Jeffrie Murphy, "Three Mistakes About Retributivism," Analysis 31 (1971): 166-169; Lloyd Weinreb, "Desert, Punishment, and Criminal Responsibility," Law and Contemporary Problems 49 (1986): 47.
    • (1986) Law and Contemporary Problems , vol.49 , pp. 47
    • Weinreb, L.1
  • 14
    • 0039974634 scopus 로고
    • Justifying Retributivism
    • Michael Moore, "Justifying Retributivism," Israel. L. Rev. 27 (1993): 15-49.
    • (1993) Israel. L. Rev. , vol.27 , pp. 15-49
    • Moore, M.1
  • 15
    • 0004244925 scopus 로고
    • New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • As H.L.A. Hart noted, "theories of punishment" is to some extent an unfortunate term "because theories of punishment are not theories in any normal sense. They are not, as scientific theories are, assertions or contentions as to what is or what is not the case . . . On the contrary, . . . [they] are moral claims as to what justifies the practice of punishment . . ." H.L.A. Hart, Punishment and Responsibility (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968), p. 72.
    • (1968) Punishment and Responsibility , pp. 72
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 16
    • 79551693894 scopus 로고
    • Some Thoughts about Retributivism
    • David Dolinko, Some Thoughts About Retributivism, Ethics 101 (1991): 537.
    • (1991) Ethics , vol.101 , pp. 537
    • Dolinko, D.1
  • 17
    • 0004143532 scopus 로고
    • Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall
    • Moore, supra note 3, p. 17. Deontological theories are more commonly defined as those that deny that the rightness of an action is always determined solely by the goodness of its (actual or expected) consequences. See William Frankena, Ethics (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1963), p. 14; Richard Brandt, Ethical Theory (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1959), pp. 354- 355. This definition and Moore's definition yield different results in certain cases. Consider, for example, ethical egoism - the theory that the right action for a person, at any moment, is whatever action is then open to him which will produce the greatest balance of good over evil for him. By the standard definition this is a consequentialist theory: it makes the rightness or wrongness of any given act a function of the goodness or badness of its consequences. Yet egoism enjoins on everyone, at all times, a norm that is "agent-relative" in Moore's sense - "addressed to each person individually at a particular time" and "not concerned with maximizing conformity" either to itself or to other norms "on other occasions." I do not believe that this problem affects the issues I wish to discuss, and I shall ignore it in what follows.
    • (1963) Ethics , pp. 14
    • Frankena, W.1
  • 18
    • 0004171296 scopus 로고
    • Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall
    • Moore, supra note 3, p. 17. Deontological theories are more commonly defined as those that deny that the rightness of an action is always determined solely by the goodness of its (actual or expected) consequences. See William Frankena, Ethics (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1963), p. 14; Richard Brandt, Ethical Theory (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1959), pp. 354-355. This definition and Moore's definition yield different results in certain cases. Consider, for example, ethical egoism - the theory that the right action for a person, at any moment, is whatever action is then open to him which will produce the greatest balance of good over evil for him. By the standard definition this is a consequentialist theory: it makes the rightness or wrongness of any given act a function of the goodness or badness of its consequences. Yet egoism enjoins on everyone, at all times, a norm that is "agent-relative" in Moore's sense - "addressed to each person individually at a particular time" and "not concerned with maximizing conformity" either to itself or to other norms "on other occasions." I do not believe that this problem affects the issues I wish to discuss, and I shall ignore it in what follows.
    • (1959) Ethical Theory , pp. 354-355
    • Brandt, R.1
  • 19
    • 0347508233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 18. For example, one might favor granting immunity to a guilty criminal in order to gain his help in prosecuting several others even more guilty.
  • 20
    • 0002368255 scopus 로고
    • The Moral Worth of Retribution
    • Ferdinand Schoeman (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Indeed, Moore himself formerly endorsed this assumption: Michael Moore, "The Moral Worth of Retribution," in Ferdinand Schoeman (ed.), Character, Responsibility, and the Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), p. 182.
    • (1987) Character, Responsibility, and the Emotions , pp. 182
    • Moore, M.1
  • 21
    • 0346247316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 19 (both emphases in original).
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 19 (both emphases in original).
  • 22
    • 0347508193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 23
    • 0041719691 scopus 로고
    • Can Retributivists Support Legal Punishment?
    • One writer, who presupposed that retributivists are not consequentialists, put forward this fallibility argument to contend that retributivists simply could not support any actual punishment institution. George Schedler, "Can Retributivists Support Legal Punishment?," The Monist 63 (1980): 185-199.
    • (1980) The Monist , vol.63 , pp. 185-199
    • Schedler, G.1
  • 24
    • 0347508099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 20.
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 20.
  • 25
    • 0348138258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 26
    • 0009386072 scopus 로고
    • The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect
    • Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • Philippa Foot, "The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect," in Virtues and Vices (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1978), p. 22.
    • (1978) Virtues and Vices , pp. 22
    • Foot, P.1
  • 27
    • 0346877740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (emphasis in original)
    • Id. (emphasis in original).
  • 28
    • 0347508194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 29
    • 0041010200 scopus 로고
    • Torture and the Balance of Evils
    • Elsewhere Moore has explained that norms are absolute if "they cannot be violated, whatever the consequences may be of not violating them on some occasion." Michael Moore, "Torture and the Balance of Evils," Israel. L. Rev. 23 (1989): 297-298. The norm prohibiting knowingly creating a high risk of death in order to profit from potential victims' ignorance of that risk would seem "absolute" in this sense - we would not permit it to be violated no matter how large the profit.
    • (1989) Israel. L. Rev. , vol.23 , pp. 297-298
    • Moore, M.1
  • 30
    • 0346877741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 20 n. 12
    • See Moore, supra note 3, at 20 n. 12.
  • 31
    • 0348138257 scopus 로고
    • The Doctrine of Double Effect: Problems of Interpretation
    • Foot, supra note 14, at 20
    • See, e.g., Foot, supra note 14, at 20; Nancy Davis, "The Doctrine of Double Effect: Problems of Interpretation," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 65 (1984): 108.
    • (1984) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.65 , pp. 108
    • Davis, N.1
  • 32
    • 0004207980 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), p. 179.
    • (1986) The View from Nowhere , pp. 179
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 33
    • 0024732716 scopus 로고
    • Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect
    • 1989.
    • In perhaps the most sophisticated recent defense of the DDE, Warren Quinn formulated the doctrine in a way that avoids asking whether the agent "intended" the ultimate harm. Warren Quinn, "Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Double Effect," Phil. & Pub. Affairs 18 (1989): 334-351 (1989). Quinn instead distinguished between harmful direct and indirect agency. Harmful direct agency - the disfavored, harder-to-justify sort - is "agency in which harm comes to some victims, at least in part, from the agent's deliberately involving them in something in order to further his purpose precisely by way of their being so involved." Id. at 343. (Quinn appears to add the further requirement that the agent must violate a negative or positive moral right of the victim. Id. at 346-347.) Suppose we said that agent-relative moral norms bind us absolutely only in prohibiting harmful direct agency. Perversely, this would seem to make mistaken punishment of the innocent, but not the actions of the wicked merchants, a violation of an absolute norm! For when fallible institutions of punishment inflict harm on wrongly-convicted innocents, what happens is that certain agents - those meting out the punishment - "deliberately involve [the innocents] in something" - namely, in the punishment (e.g., incarceration) - "in order to further [the punishers'] purpose" (be it retribution, deterrence, or reform) "precisely by way of their being so involved." (Additionally, the innocents' moral rights are violated when they are punished by mistake.) This is direct harmful agency. By contrast, since the wicked merchants don't actually care whether any consumers of the cooking oil even exist, they do not "deliberately involve" any such consumers in anything "in order to further [their] purpose precisely by way of [the consumers'] being so involved," and their harmful agency is indirect.
    • (1989) Phil. & Pub. Affairs , vol.18 , pp. 334-351
    • Quinn, W.1
  • 34
    • 0348138265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 17 (emphasis in original)
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 17 (emphasis in original).
  • 35
    • 0348138288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Moore himself suggests that the consequentialist-retributivist will recognize "other equally valuable" good-making factors. Id., at 19. And he objects to assuming that retributivists of whatever stripe are "monomaniacally focused on the achievement of retributive justice" to the exclusion of "other intrinsic goods." Id., at 34.
  • 36
    • 0347508191 scopus 로고
    • Id., at 15 (emphasis added) New York: Harcourt, Brace & World
    • Id., at 15 (emphasis added). Perhaps one could distinguish the claim that good effects of punishment, other than its being deserved, play a part in making it just in a given case from the claim that such good effects play a part in making punishment right in that case, and argue that a consequentialist-retributivist can John Hospers, Human Conduct (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1961), pp. 104-05. See also William Frankena, Ethics, supra note 6, pp. 63-67; Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1981), p. 414.
    • (1961) Human Conduct , pp. 104-105
    • Hospers, J.1
  • 37
    • 0004143533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 6
    • Id., at 15 (emphasis added). Perhaps one could distinguish the claim that good effects of punishment, other than its being deserved, play a part in making it just in a given case from the claim that such good effects play a part in making punishment right in that case, and argue that a consequentialist-retributivist can John Hospers, Human Conduct (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1961), pp. 104-05. See also William Frankena, Ethics, supra note 6, pp. 63-67; Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1981), p. 414.
    • Ethics , pp. 63-67
    • Frankena, W.1
  • 38
    • 0004071138 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Id., at 15 (emphasis added). Perhaps one could distinguish the claim that good effects of punishment, other than its being deserved, play a part in making it just in a given case from the claim that such good effects play a part in making punishment right in that case, and argue that a consequentialist-retributivist can John Hospers, Human Conduct (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1961), pp. 104-05. See also William Frankena, Ethics, supra note 6, pp. 63-67; Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1981), p. 414.
    • (1981) Philosophical Explanations , pp. 414
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 39
    • 0346247363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moore, supra note 3, p. 15
    • Moore, supra note 3, p. 15.
  • 40
    • 0041719886 scopus 로고
    • Patterson Smith 1929
    • For the intrinsic-good claim, see, e.g., A. C. Ewing, The Morality of Punishment p. 13 (Patterson Smith 1970) (1929) (retributivism "means that the punishment of the guilty is in itself something of value quite apart from the fact that it is a method of attaining other ends"); Robert Nozick, supra note 25, at 374 (1981) (presenting a retributive theory in which punishment "is seen as right or good in itself, apart from the further consequences to which it might lead");
    • (1970) The Morality of Punishment , pp. 13
    • Ewing, A.C.1
  • 41
    • 0346877747 scopus 로고
    • supra note 25, at 374
    • For the intrinsic-good claim, see, e.g., A. C. Ewing, The Morality of Punishment p. 13 (Patterson Smith 1970) (1929) (retributivism "means that the punishment of the guilty is in itself something of value quite apart from the fact that it is a method of attaining other ends"); Robert Nozick, supra note 25, at 374 (1981) (presenting a retributive theory in which punishment "is seen as right or good in itself, apart from the further consequences to which it might lead");
    • (1981)
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 42
    • 0041718600 scopus 로고
    • They Deserve to Suffer
    • Lawrence Davis, "They Deserve to Suffer," Analysis 32 (1972): 136-140, p. 136 ("hallmark" of retributivism is claim that "There is some intrinsic value in the suffering of the guilty"). For the desert claim, see, e.g., Igor Primoratz, supra note 2, p. 12 (for retributivism, "punishment is morally justified because it is just" and "is just because it is deserved by [the] offense"); H. J. McCloskey, supra note 2, p. 260 ("If the deserved punshment is inflicted, all we need do to justify it is to point out that the crime committed deserved and merited such punishment");
    • (1972) Analysis , vol.32 , pp. 136-140
    • Davis, L.1
  • 43
    • 84963012159 scopus 로고
    • Punishment and Desert
    • C.W.K. Mundle, "Punishment and Desert," Phil. Q. 4 (1954): 221 (one tenet of retributivism is that "the fact that a person has committed a moral offence provides a sufficient reason for his being made to suffer").
    • (1954) Phil. Q. , vol.4 , pp. 221
    • Mundle, C.W.K.1
  • 45
    • 0346877738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lawrence Davis, supra note 27, at 136-137
    • See Lawrence Davis, supra note 27, at 136-137.
  • 46
    • 0346877739 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 19 (emphasis in original deleted)
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 19 (emphasis in original deleted).
  • 47
    • 0347508203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. Constitution, Art. 1, §8, cl. 8
    • U.S. Constitution, Art. 1, §8, cl. 8.
  • 48
    • 0039122975 scopus 로고
    • John Ladd trans., Bobbs-Merrill
    • The locus classicus is Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysical Elements of Justice 100-102 (John Ladd trans., Bobbs-Merrill 1965), containing the celebrated claim that even a society about to dissolve itself must first execute "the last murderer remaining in prison . . . so that everyone will duly receive what his actions are worth and so that the bloodguilt thereof will not be fixed on the people." Id. at 102. Kant's devotion to this retributive thesis has, however, recently been questioned. See Sharon Byrd, "Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution," Law & Phil. 8 (1989): 151-200; Jeffrie Murphy, "Does Kant Have a Theory of Punishment?," Colum. L. Rev. 87 (1987): 509-532.
    • (1965) The Metaphysical Elements of Justice , pp. 100-102
    • Kant, I.1
  • 49
    • 0039122975 scopus 로고
    • Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution
    • The locus classicus is Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysical Elements of Justice 100-102 (John Ladd trans., Bobbs-Merrill 1965), containing the celebrated claim that even a society about to dissolve itself must first execute "the last murderer remaining in prison . . . so that everyone will duly receive what his actions are worth and so that the bloodguilt thereof will not be fixed on the people." Id. at 102. Kant's devotion to this retributive thesis has, however, recently been questioned. See Sharon Byrd, "Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution," Law & Phil. 8 (1989): 151-200; Jeffrie Murphy, "Does Kant Have a Theory of Punishment?," Colum. L. Rev. 87 (1987): 509-532.
    • (1989) Law & Phil. , vol.8 , pp. 151-200
    • Byrd, S.1
  • 50
    • 0039122975 scopus 로고
    • Does Kant Have a Theory of Punishment?
    • The locus classicus is Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysical Elements of Justice 100-102 (John Ladd trans., Bobbs-Merrill 1965), containing the celebrated claim that even a society about to dissolve itself must first execute "the last murderer remaining in prison . . . so that everyone will duly receive what his actions are worth and so that the bloodguilt thereof will not be fixed on the people." Id. at 102. Kant's devotion to this retributive thesis has, however, recently been questioned. See Sharon Byrd, "Kant's Theory of Punishment: Deterrence in its Threat, Retribution in its Execution," Law & Phil. 8 (1989): 151-200; Jeffrie Murphy, "Does Kant Have a Theory of Punishment?," Colum. L. Rev. 87 (1987): 509-532.
    • (1987) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.87 , pp. 509-532
    • Murphy, J.1
  • 51
    • 0348138263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 16
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 16.
  • 52
    • 0346247337 scopus 로고
    • The Defeat of Good and Evil
    • One list of commonly accepted examples of things that are intrinsically good includes "pleasure, happiness, love, knowledge, justice, beauty, proportion, good intention, and the exercise of virtue." Roderick Chisholm, "The Defeat of Good and Evil," Proc. & Addresses of the Am. Phil. Ass'n 42 (1968-69): 22. Chisholm adds that "What these terms refer to are not individuals or concrete things or substances. They are rather . . . states of affairs: there being happy individuals . . . ; there being individuals experiencing pleasure . . . ;" and the like. Id.
    • (1968) Proc. & Addresses of the Am. Phil. Ass'n , vol.42 , pp. 22
    • Chisholm, R.1
  • 53
    • 0000019569 scopus 로고
    • Theories of Intrinsic Value
    • Warren Quinn, "Theories of Intrinsic Value," Am. Phil. Q. 11 (1974): 123.
    • (1974) Am. Phil. Q. , vol.11 , pp. 123
    • Quinn, W.1
  • 54
    • 0346877743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The point is even clearer if, instead of happiness, we think of other plausible, though more disputable, candidates for the title "intrinsically good." One might well believe that the intensely pleasurable sensations accompanying orgasm are intrinsically good, without for a moment supposing that this suggests a duty to set up state institutions to dole out orgasms to people! Indeed, it's not merely that there is no duty on the state to set up such institutions. There is likewise no duty on any individual to provide others with orgasms whenever he or she is in a position to do so.
  • 55
    • 0347508197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Again, if one grants that the pleasure experienced in orgasm is intrinsically good, an even stronger case can be made for the conclusion in the text. For no one is likely to suppose we have even a prima facie reason to set up an official institution to provide people with orgasms.
  • 56
    • 44549088553 scopus 로고
    • Why Punish the Deserving?
    • Douglas Husak, "Why Punish the Deserving?," Noûs 26 (1992): 450-451.
    • (1992) Noûs , vol.26 , pp. 450-451
    • Husak, D.1
  • 57
    • 0347508196 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 15
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 15.
  • 58
    • 0348138261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moore, supra note 8, at 182
    • Moore, supra note 8, at 182.
  • 59
    • 0347508202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dolinko, supra note 5, at 544
    • Dolinko, supra note 5, at 544.
  • 61
    • 0347508198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dolinko, supra note 5, at 544
    • Dolinko, supra note 5, at 544.
  • 62
    • 0348138260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 63
    • 0346877745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 34
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 34.
  • 64
    • 0141598397 scopus 로고
    • Justice and Personal Desert
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • Joel Feinberg, "Justice and Personal Desert," in Doing and Deserving (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1970), p. 60.
    • (1970) Doing and Deserving , pp. 60
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 65
    • 0348138264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 34
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 34.
  • 66
    • 0347508201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (emphasis in original)
    • Id. (emphasis in original).
  • 67
    • 0348138259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "[W]hat is distinctively retributivist is the view that the guilty receiving their just deserts is an intrinsic good." Id., at 19
    • "[W]hat is distinctively retributivist is the view that the guilty receiving their just deserts is an intrinsic good." Id., at 19.
  • 68
    • 0042534349 scopus 로고
    • Do the Guilty Deserve Punishment?
    • For demonstrations of how difficult it can be to make the "forfeiture" notion work, see Richard Burgh, "Do the Guilty Deserve Punishment?," J. Phil. 77 (1982): 198-202; Warren Quinn, "The Right to Threaten and the Right to Punish," Phil. & Public Affairs 14 (1985): 331-334.
    • (1982) J. Phil. , vol.77 , pp. 198-202
    • Burgh, R.1
  • 69
    • 84928224456 scopus 로고
    • The Right to Threaten and the Right to Punish
    • For demonstrations of how difficult it can be to make the "forfeiture" notion work, see Richard Burgh, "Do the Guilty Deserve Punishment?," J. Phil. 77 (1982): 198-202; Warren Quinn, "The Right to Threaten and the Right to Punish," Phil. & Public Affairs 14 (1985): 331-334.
    • (1985) Phil. & Public Affairs , vol.14 , pp. 331-334
    • Quinn, W.1
  • 70
    • 0346877742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 19
    • Moore, supra note 3, at 19.
  • 71
    • 0347508199 scopus 로고
    • The Culture of Vengeance
    • April 9
    • See Dolinko, supra note 5, at 538. Consider, for example, New York state, which recently enacted a death-penalty law. A "thirst for retribution" played a prominent part "in New Yorkers' debate over reinstating the death penalty," and Dennis Vacco, the state's attorney general, has spoken in favor of retribution as a decisive consideration in favor of executing murderers. Scott Thomas, The Culture of Vengeance, Buffalo News, April 9, 1995, Buffalo Magazine, at 9 (available on LEXIS).
    • (1995) Buffalo News
    • Thomas, S.1
  • 72
    • 0347508195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • available on LEXIS
    • See Dolinko, supra note 5, at 538. Consider, for example, New York state, which recently enacted a death-penalty law. A "thirst for retribution" played a prominent part "in New Yorkers' debate over reinstating the death penalty," and Dennis Vacco, the state's attorney general, has spoken in favor of retribution as a decisive consideration in favor of executing murderers. Scott Thomas, The Culture of Vengeance, Buffalo News, April 9, 1995, Buffalo Magazine, at 9 (available on LEXIS).
    • Buffalo Magazine , pp. 9
  • 73
    • 0347508200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H.L.A. Hart, supra note 4, at 1
    • H.L.A. Hart, supra note 4, at 1.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.