메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 16, Issue 4, 1997, Pages 447-477

Legal theory and value judgments

Author keywords

Constructivism; Descriptivism value freedom principle; Legal knowledge; Value judgments

Indexed keywords


EID: 0031488076     PISSN: 01675249     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/3504984     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (11)

References (77)
  • 1
    • 84956898060 scopus 로고
    • Torino: Giappichelli
    • In my opinion the notion of legal positivism has a much broader scope than what is currently assumed, because it includes all the conceptions that presuppose a certain concept of positive law, a concept according to which: i) law is always and integrally an human product; ii) this product is radically contingent, in the sense that its connection with morals, which could even be considered as 'necessary' for certain legal systems (this is the case of our current western legal systems) regards values that are always context-bound, that is, values which can never be objectively justified. From this point of view, there is a mutually exclusive opposition between natural law and legal positivism (opposition which amounts to an opposition between ethical objectivism and ethical relativism): both could be defined putting the sign of negation before the opposite one (positivist or naturalist). It is important to remark that, according to this definition, even legal realism (and Dworkin's theory) is a form of positivism. For this kind of definition of legal positivism, see my book Conoscenza giuridica e concetto di diritto positivo. Lezioni di filosofia del diritto (Torino: Giappichelli, 1993), pp. 105-108.
    • (1993) Conoscenza Giuridica e Concetto di Diritto Positivo. Lezioni di Filosofia del Diritto , pp. 105-108
  • 2
    • 0041118661 scopus 로고
    • Italian. transl. Torino: Einaudi, (3rd edn)
    • A classical formulation of this thesis is given by Kelsen: according to Kelsen, legal science's function does not consist in attributing values or in expressing evaluations, but rather, in a description of its own object, description which is performed leaving values out of consideration. See H. Kelsen, Reine Rechtslehre, Italian. transl. (Torino: Einaudi, 1975 (3rd edn)), p. 84. According to another leading figure in legal positivism, Hart, the separation, internal to the domain of discourses referring to positive law, between conceptual analyses and evaluations, represents one of the five meanings usually given to the notion of legal positivism. See H.L.A. Hart, 'Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals', Harvard Law Review I (1958), pp. 593 ff. A very influential statement of this thesis, in Italian analytical positivism, is that given by Bobbio. According to Bobbio, compliance with the value-freedom principle constitutes one of legal positivism's three aspects. See N. Bobbio, Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico (Milano: Ed. di Comunitá, 1972), pp. 105-107.
    • (1975) Reine Rechtslehre , pp. 84
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 3
    • 0000580092 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals
    • A classical formulation of this thesis is given by Kelsen: according to Kelsen, legal science's function does not consist in attributing values or in expressing evaluations, but rather, in a description of its own object, description which is performed leaving values out of consideration. See H. Kelsen, Reine Rechtslehre, Italian. transl. (Torino: Einaudi, 1975 (3rd edn)), p. 84. According to another leading figure in legal positivism, Hart, the separation, internal to the domain of discourses referring to positive law, between conceptual analyses and evaluations, represents one of the five meanings usually given to the notion of legal positivism. See H.L.A. Hart, 'Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals', Harvard Law Review I (1958), pp. 593 ff. A very influential statement of this thesis, in Italian analytical positivism, is that given by Bobbio. According to Bobbio, compliance with the value-freedom principle constitutes one of legal positivism's three aspects. See N. Bobbio, Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico (Milano: Ed. di Comunitá, 1972), pp. 105-107.
    • (1958) Harvard Law Review , vol.1
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 4
    • 0042195039 scopus 로고
    • Milano: Ed. di Comunitá
    • A classical formulation of this thesis is given by Kelsen: according to Kelsen, legal science's function does not consist in attributing values or in expressing evaluations, but rather, in a description of its own object, description which is performed leaving values out of consideration. See H. Kelsen, Reine Rechtslehre, Italian. transl. (Torino: Einaudi, 1975 (3rd edn)), p. 84. According to another leading figure in legal positivism, Hart, the separation, internal to the domain of discourses referring to positive law, between conceptual analyses and evaluations, represents one of the five meanings usually given to the notion of legal positivism. See H.L.A. Hart, 'Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals', Harvard Law Review I (1958), pp. 593 ff. A very influential statement of this thesis, in Italian analytical positivism, is that given by Bobbio. According to Bobbio, compliance with the value-freedom principle constitutes one of legal positivism's three aspects. See N. Bobbio, Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico (Milano: Ed. di Comunitá, 1972), pp. 105-107.
    • (1972) Giusnaturalismo e Positivismo Giuridico , pp. 105-107
    • Bobbio, N.1
  • 6
    • 4243816994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Farewell to 'Legal Positivism': The Separation Thesis Unravelling
    • R.P. George (ed.) Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • I borrow this expression from K. Füsser, 'Farewell to 'Legal Positivism': the Separation Thesis Unravelling', in R.P. George (ed.) The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), pp. 119-62.
    • (1996) The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism , pp. 119-162
    • Füsser, K.1
  • 7
    • 0043197195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Torino: Giappichelli
    • See on this point Celano, who thinks that to accept the 'great division' logically implies refusing any place for value-judgments inside social sciences. See B. Celano, Dialettica della giustificazione pratica. Saggio sulla legge di Hume (Torino: Giappichelli, 1994), p. 49.
    • (1994) Dialettica della Giustificazione Pratica. Saggio sulla Legge di Hume , pp. 49
    • Celano, B.1
  • 8
    • 0004121291 scopus 로고
    • London: Stevens & Sons Limited
    • This kind of conviction is expressed very clearly by Ross, when he says that the 'descriptive terminology' that is used in the doctrinal study of law "has nothing to do with moral approval or condemnation" of a given legal system's rules. See A. Ross, On Law and Justice (London: Stevens & Sons Limited, 1958), pp. 31-32.
    • (1958) On Law and Justice , pp. 31-32
    • Ross, A.1
  • 10
    • 0041694282 scopus 로고
    • Produzione di norme a mezzo di norme
    • ed. by L. Gianformaggio and E. Lecaldano Bari: Laterza
    • This distinction is drawn by R. Guastini, 'Produzione di norme a mezzo di norme', in Etica e diritto, ed. by L. Gianformaggio and E. Lecaldano (Bari: Laterza, 1986), pp. 175, 186-87. have criticized this distinction in my 'Legal Analogy Between Interpretive Arguments and Productive Arguments', in Legal Knowledge and Analogy, ed. by P. Nerhot (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991), pp. 165-82.
    • (1986) Etica e Diritto , pp. 175
    • Guastini, R.1
  • 11
    • 0042195028 scopus 로고
    • Legal Analogy between Interpretive Arguments and Productive Arguments
    • Dordrecht: Kluwer
    • This distinction is drawn by R. Guastini, 'Produzione di norme a mezzo di norme', in Etica e diritto, ed. by L. Gianformaggio and E. Lecaldano (Bari: Laterza, 1986), pp. 175, 186-87. have criticized this distinction in my 'Legal Analogy Between Interpretive Arguments and Productive Arguments', in Legal Knowledge and Analogy, ed. by P. Nerhot (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991), pp. 165-82.
    • (1991) Legal Knowledge and Analogy , pp. 165-182
    • Nerhot, P.1
  • 12
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London: Fontana Press
    • Dworkin, anyway, points outs very clearly the need for sharply distinguishing 'ethical claims' and 'mere reports of taste' in legal domain. See R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (London: Fontana Press, 1986), p. 81. For a much broader distinction, epistemologically grounded, between objective and subjective value-judgments, see H. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (Cambridge Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 156.
    • (1986) Law's Empire , pp. 81
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 13
    • 0004235120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge Mass.: Cambridge University Press
    • Dworkin, anyway, points outs very clearly the need for sharply distinguishing 'ethical claims' and 'mere reports of taste' in legal domain. See R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (London: Fontana Press, 1986), p. 81. For a much broader distinction, epistemologically grounded, between objective and subjective value-judgments, see H. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (Cambridge Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 156.
    • (1981) Reason, Truth and History , pp. 156
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 15
    • 0004235120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra n. 9
    • Putnam exposes and criticizes this epistemological conception in many places; but see particularly H. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (supra n. 9), pp. 49-50.
    • Reason, Truth and History , pp. 49-50
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 16
    • 0042195011 scopus 로고
    • Determinacy, Objectivity, and Authority
    • ed. by A. Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • In recent years, for instance, there has developed a very interesting debate on which is the most feasible way to work out a concept of objectivity for legal practices that could represent a viable alternative to both strong objectivist positions, too much compromised with metaphysical realism, and subjectivist positions, which share relativistic or conventionalist premises. Among these attempts, see particularly J. Coleman & B. Leiter, 'Determinacy, Objectivity, and Authority', in Law and Interpretation: Essays in Legal Philosophy, ed. by A. Marmor (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), pp. 203-78, and N. Stavropoulos, Objectivity in Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996).
    • (1995) Law and Interpretation: Essays in Legal Philosophy , pp. 203-278
    • Coleman, J.1    Leiter, B.2
  • 17
    • 0041694283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • In recent years, for instance, there has developed a very interesting debate on which is the most feasible way to work out a concept of objectivity for legal practices that could represent a viable alternative to both strong objectivist positions, too much compromised with metaphysical realism, and subjectivist positions, which share relativistic or conventionalist premises. Among these attempts, see particularly J. Coleman & B. Leiter, 'Determinacy, Objectivity, and Authority', in Law and Interpretation: Essays in Legal Philosophy, ed. by A. Marmor (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), pp. 203-78, and N. Stavropoulos, Objectivity in Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996).
    • (1996) Objectivity in Law
    • Stavropoulos, N.1
  • 18
    • 0042696105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I can only make reference here to my recent book Conoscenza giuridica e concetto di diritto positivo (supra n. 1) and to my new book Costruttivismo e teorie del diritto (Torino: Giappichelli), which will be published later in this year.
  • 19
    • 0042696123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See footnote 1 above
    • See footnote 1 above.
  • 20
    • 0004043301 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harcourt, Brace & World
    • E. Nagel, The Structure of Science (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1961), p. 494.
    • (1961) The Structure of Science , pp. 494
    • Nagel, E.1
  • 21
    • 0043197194 scopus 로고
    • Theoretical Language, Evaluations and Prescriptions: A Post-Empiricist Approach
    • ed. by C. Faralli and E. Pattaro, Milano: Giuffré
    • I borrow this configuration of characterizing value-judgments from D. Zolo, 'Theoretical Language, Evaluations and Prescriptions: A Post-Empiricist Approach', in Reason in Law, ed. by C. Faralli and E. Pattaro, Vol. II (Milano: Giuffré, 1988), pp. 376-77.
    • (1988) Reason in Law , vol.2 , pp. 376-377
    • Zolo, D.1
  • 23
    • 0038948337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra n. 3
    • For the ambiguity of this thesis, see H.L.A. Hart, 'Positivism and the Separation Between Law and Morals' (supra n. 3), pp. 593 ff. See also P. Greenawalt, 'Too Thin and Too Rich: Distinguishing Features of Legal Positivism', in The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism (supra n. 4), pp. 11-12.
    • Positivism and the Separation between Law and Morals
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 24
    • 0043197137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Too Thin and Too Rich: Distinguishing Features of Legal Positivism
    • supra n. 4
    • For the ambiguity of this thesis, see H.L.A. Hart, 'Positivism and the Separation Between Law and Morals' (supra n. 3), pp. 593 ff. See also P. Greenawalt, 'Too Thin and Too Rich: Distinguishing Features of Legal Positivism', in The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism (supra n. 4), pp. 11-12.
    • The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism , pp. 11-12
    • Greenawalt, P.1
  • 27
    • 0042768838 scopus 로고
    • Ragion pratica e diritto naturale: Una difesa analitica del giusnaturalismo
    • This seems to me the opinion of F. Viola, 'Ragion pratica e diritto naturale: una difesa analitica del giusnaturalismo', in Ragion pratica 1 (1993): 61-81.
    • (1993) Ragion Pratica , vol.1 , pp. 61-81
    • Viola, F.1
  • 28
    • 0041144904 scopus 로고
    • London: Edward Arnold
    • See, for instance, the ideas exposed by N. MacCormick, H.L.A. Hart (London: Edward Arnold, 1981), pp. 160-61, and 'Natural Law and the Separation of Law and Morals', in Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays, ed. by R.P. George (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 129-31 ; and by J. Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain. Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), p. 211.
    • (1981) H.L.A. Hart , pp. 160-161
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 29
    • 0041694295 scopus 로고
    • Natural Law and the Separation of Law and Morals
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • See, for instance, the ideas exposed by N. MacCormick, H.L.A. Hart (London: Edward Arnold, 1981), pp. 160-61, and 'Natural Law and the Separation of Law and Morals', in Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays, ed. by R.P. George (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 129-31 ; and by J. Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain. Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), p. 211.
    • (1992) Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays , pp. 129-131
    • George, R.P.1
  • 30
    • 0003472868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • See, for instance, the ideas exposed by N. MacCormick, H.L.A. Hart (London: Edward Arnold, 1981), pp. 160-61, and 'Natural Law and the Separation of Law and Morals', in Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays, ed. by R.P. George (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 129-31 ; and by J. Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain. Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), p. 211.
    • (1994) Ethics in the Public Domain. Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics , pp. 211
    • Raz, J.1
  • 34
    • 0043197199 scopus 로고
    • in his book Torino: Giappichelli
    • This is one of the main theses of F. Viola, in his book Il diritto come pratica sociale (Torino: Giappichelli, 1990).
    • (1990) Il Diritto Come Pratica Sociale
    • Viola, F.1
  • 35
    • 0043270059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intention in Interpretation
    • supra n. 17
    • J. Raz, 'Intention in Interpretation', in The Autonomy of Law (supra n. 17), pp. 260-61.
    • The Autonomy of Law , pp. 260-261
    • Raz, J.1
  • 42
    • 0043197212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 23. A similar position is expressed by A. Marmor, Interpretation and Legal Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 55-57.
    • Inclusive Legal Positivism , pp. 23
  • 43
    • 0009328199 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Ibid., p. 23. A similar position is expressed by A. Marmor, Interpretation and Legal Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 55-57.
    • (1992) Interpretation and Legal Theory , pp. 55-57
    • Marmor, A.1
  • 47
    • 0042696103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Ideal and the Actual of Law and Society
    • J. Tasioulas (ed.) Aldershot: Dartmouth Publishing Co, Section iv
    • N. MacCormick, The Ideal and the Actual of Law and Society', in J. Tasioulas (ed.) Law, Values and Social Practices (Aldershot: Dartmouth Publishing Co, 1997), pp. 15-37, Section iv.
    • (1997) Law, Values and Social Practices , pp. 15-37
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 49
    • 0041694286 scopus 로고
    • Taking the "Rights Thesis" Seriously
    • N. MacCormick, Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • This way of handling the matter is clearer in a previous paper, in which he explicitly speaks of a distinction between 'description' and 'criticism' of positive law. See N. MacCormick, 'Taking the "Rights Thesis" Seriously', in N. MacCormick, Legal Right and Social Democracy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), p. 140.
    • (1982) Legal Right and Social Democracy , pp. 140
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 50
    • 0009325742 scopus 로고
    • Natural Law and the Separation between Law and Morals
    • ed. by R.P. George Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • N. MacCormick, 'Natural Law and the Separation Between Law and Morals', in Natural Law Theory, ed. by R.P. George (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), p. 113.
    • (1992) Natural Law Theory , pp. 113
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 53
    • 0009445978 scopus 로고
    • Interpretation and Methodology in Legal Theory
    • ed. by A. Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • T. Perry, 'Interpretation and Methodology in Legal Theory', in Law and Interpretation. Essays in Legal Philosophy, ed. by A. Marmor (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), pp. 122-23.
    • (1995) Law and Interpretation. Essays in Legal Philosophy , pp. 122-123
    • Perry, T.1
  • 56
    • 0004072810 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • For an exposition and a criticism of this image, and for the use of this metaphor in analysing it, see the already classical book of R. Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980).
    • (1980) Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 57
    • 0042195027 scopus 로고
    • ed. and intro. by J. Conant Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • H. Putnam, Realism with a Human Face, ed. and intro. by J. Conant (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990), p. 150. A similar position, which tracks down the sources of 'facts/values' dichotomy in the mistaken alternative between 'strong cognitivism' in epistemology and 'non cognitivism' about values, is stressed by J. McDowell, 'Non-Cognitivism and Rule Following', in Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule, ed. by J. Holtzmann and C. Leich (London: Routledge & Kegan, 1981), pp. 141-42. For an analysis which tries to apply these ideas in the legal domain, see my 'Normative Coherence and Epistemological Presuppositions of Justification', in Law, Interpretation and Reality: Essays in Epistemology, Hermeneutics and Jurisprudence, ed. P. Nerhot (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990), pp. 439-42.
    • (1990) Realism with a Human Face , pp. 150
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 58
    • 85068201368 scopus 로고
    • Non-Cognitivism and Rule Following
    • ed. by J. Holtzmann and C. Leich London: Routledge & Kegan
    • H. Putnam, Realism with a Human Face, ed. and intro. by J. Conant (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990), p. 150. A similar position, which tracks down the sources of 'facts/values' dichotomy in the mistaken alternative between 'strong cognitivism' in epistemology and 'non cognitivism' about values, is stressed by J. McDowell, 'Non-Cognitivism and Rule Following', in Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule, ed. by J. Holtzmann and C. Leich (London: Routledge & Kegan, 1981), pp. 141-42. For an analysis which tries to apply these ideas in the legal domain, see my 'Normative Coherence and Epistemological Presuppositions of Justification', in Law, Interpretation and Reality: Essays in Epistemology, Hermeneutics and Jurisprudence, ed. P. Nerhot (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990), pp. 439-42.
    • (1981) Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule , pp. 141-142
    • McDowell, J.1
  • 59
    • 0042696115 scopus 로고
    • Normative Coherence and Epistemological Presuppositions of Justification
    • Dordrecht: Kluwer
    • H. Putnam, Realism with a Human Face, ed. and intro. by J. Conant (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990), p. 150. A similar position, which tracks down the sources of 'facts/values' dichotomy in the mistaken alternative between 'strong cognitivism' in epistemology and 'non cognitivism' about values, is stressed by J. McDowell, 'Non-Cognitivism and Rule Following', in Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule, ed. by J. Holtzmann and C. Leich (London: Routledge & Kegan, 1981), pp. 141-42. For an analysis which tries to apply these ideas in the legal domain, see my 'Normative Coherence and Epistemological Presuppositions of Justification', in Law, Interpretation and Reality: Essays in Epistemology, Hermeneutics and Jurisprudence, ed. P. Nerhot (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990), pp. 439-42.
    • (1990) Law, Interpretation and Reality: Essays in Epistemology, Hermeneutics and Jurisprudence , pp. 439-442
    • Nerhot, P.1
  • 60
    • 0042195017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra n. 1
    • See again my book Conoscenza giuridica e concetto di diritto positivo (supra n. 1), pp. 187-228, and my more recent essay 'La science juridique entre descriptivisme et constructivisme', in Théorie du droit et science, ed. by P. Amselek (Paris: PUF, 1994), pp. 281-91.
    • Conoscenza Giuridica e Concetto di Diritto Positivo , pp. 187-228
  • 61
    • 85012446954 scopus 로고
    • La science juridique entre descriptivisme et constructivisme
    • Paris: PUF
    • See again my book Conoscenza giuridica e concetto di diritto positivo (supra n. 1), pp. 187-228, and my more recent essay 'La science juridique entre descriptivisme et constructivisme', in Théorie du droit et science, ed. by P. Amselek (Paris: PUF, 1994), pp. 281-91.
    • (1994) Théorie du Droit et Science , pp. 281-291
    • Amselek, P.1
  • 62
    • 0004120857 scopus 로고
    • La Salle, Illinois: Open Court
    • Good examples of the kind of constructivism that I defend here can be considered, among others, the works of Putnam (see, for instance, H. Putnam, The Many Faces of Realism (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1987)), Goodman (see N. Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett, 1978)), Hesse (M. Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1980)), and Knorr Cetina (K. D. Knorr Cetina, The Manufacture of Knowledge (Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1981)).
    • (1987) The Many Faces of Realism
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 63
    • 0003939914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett
    • Good examples of the kind of constructivism that I defend here can be considered, among others, the works of Putnam (see, for instance, H. Putnam, The Many Faces of Realism (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1987)), Goodman (see N. Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett, 1978)), Hesse (M. Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1980)), and Knorr Cetina (K. D. Knorr Cetina, The Manufacture of Knowledge (Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1981)).
    • (1978) Ways of Worldmaking
    • Goodman, N.1
  • 64
    • 0003839588 scopus 로고
    • Brighton: Harvester Press
    • Good examples of the kind of constructivism that I defend here can be considered, among others, the works of Putnam (see, for instance, H. Putnam, The Many Faces of Realism (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1987)), Goodman (see N. Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett, 1978)), Hesse (M. Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1980)), and Knorr Cetina (K. D. Knorr Cetina, The Manufacture of Knowledge (Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1981)).
    • (1980) Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science
    • Hesse, M.1
  • 65
    • 0003764788 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Pergamon Press
    • Good examples of the kind of constructivism that I defend here can be considered, among others, the works of Putnam (see, for instance, H. Putnam, The Many Faces of Realism (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1987)), Goodman (see N. Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett, 1978)), Hesse (M. Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1980)), and Knorr Cetina (K. D. Knorr Cetina, The Manufacture of Knowledge (Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1981)).
    • (1981) The Manufacture of Knowledge
    • Cetina, K.D.K.1
  • 67
    • 0004235120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra n. 9
    • See H. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (supra n. 9), p. 231. See also, in a similar vein, N. Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (supra n. 49), p. 17.
    • Reason, Truth and History , pp. 231
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 68
    • 0003939914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra n. 49
    • See H. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (supra n. 9), p. 231. See also, in a similar vein, N. Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (supra n. 49), p. 17.
    • Ways of Worldmaking , pp. 17
    • Goodman, N.1
  • 69
    • 0009425079 scopus 로고
    • On the Reasons for Indeterminacy of Translation
    • One of the most classical versions of this thesis is offered by Quine. See, for instance, W.V.O. Quine, 'On the Reasons for Indeterminacy of Translation', The Journal of Philosophy 61 (1970): 179.
    • (1970) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.61 , pp. 179
    • Quine, W.V.O.1
  • 70
    • 24444456034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra n. 49
    • See, for this suggestion, at a general epistemological level, M. Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions (supra n. 49), pp. 133 ff., 188 ff., 193 ff.; and, with specific reference to human sciences, D. Thomas, Naturalism and Social Science: A Post-Empiricist Philosophy of Social Science (Cambridge: Cambridge Univer- sity Press, 1979), pp. 126-27.
    • Revolutions and Reconstructions
    • Hesse, M.1
  • 71
    • 0040257385 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-sity Press
    • See, for this suggestion, at a general epistemological level, M. Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions (supra n. 49), pp. 133 ff., 188 ff., 193 ff.; and, with specific reference to human sciences, D. Thomas, Naturalism and Social Science: A Post-Empiricist Philosophy of Social Science (Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-sity Press, 1979), pp. 126-27.
    • (1979) Naturalism and Social Science: A Post-Empiricist Philosophy of Social Science , pp. 126-127
    • Thomas, D.1
  • 74
    • 0003981612 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Quite obvious here is the great debt that this approach to legal value-judgments owes to Dworkin. As a matter of fact, many central points of my work are deeply influenced by Dworkin's thinking. Here there are some examples. Firstly, my idea that understanding a given positive law requires an ethical appreciation of its values is closely connected with dworkinian aesthetic hypothesis (see R. Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 149-53). Secondly, my distinction between different kinds of (cognitive and creative) value-judgments is very close to the dworkinian distinction between 'interpreting while creating' and 'creating while interpreting' (ibid., p. 158). Thirdly, my suggestion on value-judgments as criteria of theory-choice in the legal domain resembles the way in which Dworkin conceives the underdetermination of raw behavioral data by the ascription of values (see R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (supra n. 9), p. 52)). There are, however, many important points in which I disagree remarkably with Dworkin. Apart from Dworkin's frequent lack of analytical rigour and from his reticence in highlighting his epistemological and semantical presuppositions, what doesn't convince me, speaking generally, is, among other things, Dworkin's choice of the participant's point of view as the correct stance for the legal theorist (ibid., p. 147). The fact is that Dworkin, after all, ends by accepting the very thesis of traditional positivists that he has so heavily criticized: I am referring to the thesis which equates ethical value- judgments expressed in legal practices with judgments produced invariably from the inside of the practice and possessing always a practical character. To sum up, for Dworkin to express an ethical value-judgment, in the context of a legal system, amounts to justifying its acceptance or rejection from a moral point of view or at least to justify some specific decision taken on the basis of its rules or principles.
    • (1985) A Matter of Principle , pp. 149-153
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 75
    • 85022418750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Quite obvious here is the great debt that this approach to legal value- judgments owes to Dworkin. As a matter of fact, many central points of my work are deeply influenced by Dworkin's thinking. Here there are some examples. Firstly, my idea that understanding a given positive law requires an ethical appreciation of its values is closely connected with dworkinian aesthetic hypothesis (see R. Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 149-53). Secondly, my distinction between different kinds of (cognitive and creative) value-judgments is very close to the dworkinian distinction between 'interpreting while creating' and 'creating while interpreting' (ibid., p. 158). Thirdly, my suggestion on value-judgments as criteria of theory-choice in the legal domain resembles the way in which Dworkin conceives the underdetermination of raw behavioral data by the ascription of values (see R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (supra n. 9), p. 52)). There are, however, many important points in which I disagree remarkably with Dworkin. Apart from Dworkin's frequent lack of analytical rigour and from his reticence in highlighting his epistemological and semantical presuppositions, what doesn't convince me, speaking generally, is, among other things, Dworkin's choice of the participant's point of view as the correct stance for the legal theorist (ibid., p. 147). The fact is that Dworkin, after all, ends by accepting the very thesis of traditional positivists that he has so heavily criticized: I am referring to the thesis which equates ethical value- judgments expressed in legal practices with judgments produced invariably from the inside of the practice and possessing always a practical character. To sum up, for Dworkin to express an ethical value-judgment, in the context of a legal system, amounts to justifying its acceptance or rejection from a moral point of view or at least to justify some specific decision taken on the basis of its rules or principles.
    • A Matter of Principle , pp. 158
  • 76
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra n. 9
    • Quite obvious here is the great debt that this approach to legal value- judgments owes to Dworkin. As a matter of fact, many central points of my work are deeply influenced by Dworkin's thinking. Here there are some examples. Firstly, my idea that understanding a given positive law requires an ethical appreciation of its values is closely connected with dworkinian aesthetic hypothesis (see R. Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 149-53). Secondly, my distinction between different kinds of (cognitive and creative) value-judgments is very close to the dworkinian distinction between 'interpreting while creating' and 'creating while interpreting' (ibid., p. 158). Thirdly, my suggestion on value-judgments as criteria of theory-choice in the legal domain resembles the way in which Dworkin conceives the underdetermination of raw behavioral data by the ascription of values (see R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (supra n. 9), p. 52)). There are, however, many important points in which I disagree remarkably with Dworkin. Apart from Dworkin's frequent lack of analytical rigour and from his reticence in highlighting his epistemological and semantical presuppositions, what doesn't convince me, speaking generally, is, among other things, Dworkin's choice of the participant's point of view as the correct stance for the legal theorist (ibid., p. 147). The fact is that Dworkin, after all, ends by accepting the very thesis of traditional positivists that he has so heavily criticized: I am referring to the thesis which equates ethical value- judgments expressed in legal practices with judgments produced invariably from the inside of the practice and possessing always a practical character. To sum up, for Dworkin to express an ethical value-judgment, in the context of a legal system, amounts to justifying its acceptance or rejection from a moral point of view or at least to justify some specific decision taken on the basis of its rules or principles.
    • Law's Empire , pp. 52
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 77
    • 0004166519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Quite obvious here is the great debt that this approach to legal value- judgments owes to Dworkin. As a matter of fact, many central points of my work are deeply influenced by Dworkin's thinking. Here there are some examples. Firstly, my idea that understanding a given positive law requires an ethical appreciation of its values is closely connected with dworkinian aesthetic hypothesis (see R. Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 149-53). Secondly, my distinction between different kinds of (cognitive and creative) value-judgments is very close to the dworkinian distinction between 'interpreting while creating' and 'creating while interpreting' (ibid., p. 158). Thirdly, my suggestion on value-judgments as criteria of theory-choice in the legal domain resembles the way in which Dworkin conceives the underdetermination of raw behavioral data by the ascription of values (see R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (supra n. 9), p. 52)). There are, however, many important points in which I disagree remarkably with Dworkin. Apart from Dworkin's frequent lack of analytical rigour and from his reticence in highlighting his epistemological and semantical presuppositions, what doesn't convince me, speaking generally, is, among other things, Dworkin's choice of the participant's point of view as the correct stance for the legal theorist (ibid., p. 147). The fact is that Dworkin, after all, ends by accepting the very thesis of traditional positivists that he has so heavily criticized: I am referring to the thesis which equates ethical value-judgments expressed in legal practices with judgments produced invariably from the inside of the practice and possessing always a practical character. To sum up, for Dworkin to express an ethical value-judgment, in the context of a legal system, amounts to justifying its acceptance or rejection from a moral point of view or at least to justify some specific decision taken on the basis of its rules or principles.
    • Law's Empire , pp. 147


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.