-
1
-
-
84956898060
-
-
Torino: Giappichelli
-
In my opinion the notion of legal positivism has a much broader scope than what is currently assumed, because it includes all the conceptions that presuppose a certain concept of positive law, a concept according to which: i) law is always and integrally an human product; ii) this product is radically contingent, in the sense that its connection with morals, which could even be considered as 'necessary' for certain legal systems (this is the case of our current western legal systems) regards values that are always context-bound, that is, values which can never be objectively justified. From this point of view, there is a mutually exclusive opposition between natural law and legal positivism (opposition which amounts to an opposition between ethical objectivism and ethical relativism): both could be defined putting the sign of negation before the opposite one (positivist or naturalist). It is important to remark that, according to this definition, even legal realism (and Dworkin's theory) is a form of positivism. For this kind of definition of legal positivism, see my book Conoscenza giuridica e concetto di diritto positivo. Lezioni di filosofia del diritto (Torino: Giappichelli, 1993), pp. 105-108.
-
(1993)
Conoscenza Giuridica e Concetto di Diritto Positivo. Lezioni di Filosofia del Diritto
, pp. 105-108
-
-
-
2
-
-
0041118661
-
-
Italian. transl. Torino: Einaudi, (3rd edn)
-
A classical formulation of this thesis is given by Kelsen: according to Kelsen, legal science's function does not consist in attributing values or in expressing evaluations, but rather, in a description of its own object, description which is performed leaving values out of consideration. See H. Kelsen, Reine Rechtslehre, Italian. transl. (Torino: Einaudi, 1975 (3rd edn)), p. 84. According to another leading figure in legal positivism, Hart, the separation, internal to the domain of discourses referring to positive law, between conceptual analyses and evaluations, represents one of the five meanings usually given to the notion of legal positivism. See H.L.A. Hart, 'Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals', Harvard Law Review I (1958), pp. 593 ff. A very influential statement of this thesis, in Italian analytical positivism, is that given by Bobbio. According to Bobbio, compliance with the value-freedom principle constitutes one of legal positivism's three aspects. See N. Bobbio, Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico (Milano: Ed. di Comunitá, 1972), pp. 105-107.
-
(1975)
Reine Rechtslehre
, pp. 84
-
-
Kelsen, H.1
-
3
-
-
0000580092
-
Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals
-
A classical formulation of this thesis is given by Kelsen: according to Kelsen, legal science's function does not consist in attributing values or in expressing evaluations, but rather, in a description of its own object, description which is performed leaving values out of consideration. See H. Kelsen, Reine Rechtslehre, Italian. transl. (Torino: Einaudi, 1975 (3rd edn)), p. 84. According to another leading figure in legal positivism, Hart, the separation, internal to the domain of discourses referring to positive law, between conceptual analyses and evaluations, represents one of the five meanings usually given to the notion of legal positivism. See H.L.A. Hart, 'Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals', Harvard Law Review I (1958), pp. 593 ff. A very influential statement of this thesis, in Italian analytical positivism, is that given by Bobbio. According to Bobbio, compliance with the value-freedom principle constitutes one of legal positivism's three aspects. See N. Bobbio, Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico (Milano: Ed. di Comunitá, 1972), pp. 105-107.
-
(1958)
Harvard Law Review
, vol.1
-
-
Hart, H.L.A.1
-
4
-
-
0042195039
-
-
Milano: Ed. di Comunitá
-
A classical formulation of this thesis is given by Kelsen: according to Kelsen, legal science's function does not consist in attributing values or in expressing evaluations, but rather, in a description of its own object, description which is performed leaving values out of consideration. See H. Kelsen, Reine Rechtslehre, Italian. transl. (Torino: Einaudi, 1975 (3rd edn)), p. 84. According to another leading figure in legal positivism, Hart, the separation, internal to the domain of discourses referring to positive law, between conceptual analyses and evaluations, represents one of the five meanings usually given to the notion of legal positivism. See H.L.A. Hart, 'Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals', Harvard Law Review I (1958), pp. 593 ff. A very influential statement of this thesis, in Italian analytical positivism, is that given by Bobbio. According to Bobbio, compliance with the value-freedom principle constitutes one of legal positivism's three aspects. See N. Bobbio, Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico (Milano: Ed. di Comunitá, 1972), pp. 105-107.
-
(1972)
Giusnaturalismo e Positivismo Giuridico
, pp. 105-107
-
-
Bobbio, N.1
-
6
-
-
4243816994
-
Farewell to 'Legal Positivism': The Separation Thesis Unravelling
-
R.P. George (ed.) Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
I borrow this expression from K. Füsser, 'Farewell to 'Legal Positivism': the Separation Thesis Unravelling', in R.P. George (ed.) The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), pp. 119-62.
-
(1996)
The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism
, pp. 119-162
-
-
Füsser, K.1
-
7
-
-
0043197195
-
-
Torino: Giappichelli
-
See on this point Celano, who thinks that to accept the 'great division' logically implies refusing any place for value-judgments inside social sciences. See B. Celano, Dialettica della giustificazione pratica. Saggio sulla legge di Hume (Torino: Giappichelli, 1994), p. 49.
-
(1994)
Dialettica della Giustificazione Pratica. Saggio sulla Legge di Hume
, pp. 49
-
-
Celano, B.1
-
8
-
-
0004121291
-
-
London: Stevens & Sons Limited
-
This kind of conviction is expressed very clearly by Ross, when he says that the 'descriptive terminology' that is used in the doctrinal study of law "has nothing to do with moral approval or condemnation" of a given legal system's rules. See A. Ross, On Law and Justice (London: Stevens & Sons Limited, 1958), pp. 31-32.
-
(1958)
On Law and Justice
, pp. 31-32
-
-
Ross, A.1
-
10
-
-
0041694282
-
Produzione di norme a mezzo di norme
-
ed. by L. Gianformaggio and E. Lecaldano Bari: Laterza
-
This distinction is drawn by R. Guastini, 'Produzione di norme a mezzo di norme', in Etica e diritto, ed. by L. Gianformaggio and E. Lecaldano (Bari: Laterza, 1986), pp. 175, 186-87. have criticized this distinction in my 'Legal Analogy Between Interpretive Arguments and Productive Arguments', in Legal Knowledge and Analogy, ed. by P. Nerhot (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991), pp. 165-82.
-
(1986)
Etica e Diritto
, pp. 175
-
-
Guastini, R.1
-
11
-
-
0042195028
-
Legal Analogy between Interpretive Arguments and Productive Arguments
-
Dordrecht: Kluwer
-
This distinction is drawn by R. Guastini, 'Produzione di norme a mezzo di norme', in Etica e diritto, ed. by L. Gianformaggio and E. Lecaldano (Bari: Laterza, 1986), pp. 175, 186-87. have criticized this distinction in my 'Legal Analogy Between Interpretive Arguments and Productive Arguments', in Legal Knowledge and Analogy, ed. by P. Nerhot (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991), pp. 165-82.
-
(1991)
Legal Knowledge and Analogy
, pp. 165-182
-
-
Nerhot, P.1
-
12
-
-
84936068266
-
-
London: Fontana Press
-
Dworkin, anyway, points outs very clearly the need for sharply distinguishing 'ethical claims' and 'mere reports of taste' in legal domain. See R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (London: Fontana Press, 1986), p. 81. For a much broader distinction, epistemologically grounded, between objective and subjective value-judgments, see H. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (Cambridge Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 156.
-
(1986)
Law's Empire
, pp. 81
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
13
-
-
0004235120
-
-
Cambridge Mass.: Cambridge University Press
-
Dworkin, anyway, points outs very clearly the need for sharply distinguishing 'ethical claims' and 'mere reports of taste' in legal domain. See R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (London: Fontana Press, 1986), p. 81. For a much broader distinction, epistemologically grounded, between objective and subjective value-judgments, see H. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (Cambridge Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 156.
-
(1981)
Reason, Truth and History
, pp. 156
-
-
Putnam, H.1
-
15
-
-
0004235120
-
-
supra n. 9
-
Putnam exposes and criticizes this epistemological conception in many places; but see particularly H. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (supra n. 9), pp. 49-50.
-
Reason, Truth and History
, pp. 49-50
-
-
Putnam, H.1
-
16
-
-
0042195011
-
Determinacy, Objectivity, and Authority
-
ed. by A. Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
In recent years, for instance, there has developed a very interesting debate on which is the most feasible way to work out a concept of objectivity for legal practices that could represent a viable alternative to both strong objectivist positions, too much compromised with metaphysical realism, and subjectivist positions, which share relativistic or conventionalist premises. Among these attempts, see particularly J. Coleman & B. Leiter, 'Determinacy, Objectivity, and Authority', in Law and Interpretation: Essays in Legal Philosophy, ed. by A. Marmor (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), pp. 203-78, and N. Stavropoulos, Objectivity in Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996).
-
(1995)
Law and Interpretation: Essays in Legal Philosophy
, pp. 203-278
-
-
Coleman, J.1
Leiter, B.2
-
17
-
-
0041694283
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
In recent years, for instance, there has developed a very interesting debate on which is the most feasible way to work out a concept of objectivity for legal practices that could represent a viable alternative to both strong objectivist positions, too much compromised with metaphysical realism, and subjectivist positions, which share relativistic or conventionalist premises. Among these attempts, see particularly J. Coleman & B. Leiter, 'Determinacy, Objectivity, and Authority', in Law and Interpretation: Essays in Legal Philosophy, ed. by A. Marmor (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), pp. 203-78, and N. Stavropoulos, Objectivity in Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996).
-
(1996)
Objectivity in Law
-
-
Stavropoulos, N.1
-
18
-
-
0042696105
-
-
note
-
I can only make reference here to my recent book Conoscenza giuridica e concetto di diritto positivo (supra n. 1) and to my new book Costruttivismo e teorie del diritto (Torino: Giappichelli), which will be published later in this year.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
0042696123
-
-
See footnote 1 above
-
See footnote 1 above.
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
0004043301
-
-
New York: Harcourt, Brace & World
-
E. Nagel, The Structure of Science (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1961), p. 494.
-
(1961)
The Structure of Science
, pp. 494
-
-
Nagel, E.1
-
21
-
-
0043197194
-
Theoretical Language, Evaluations and Prescriptions: A Post-Empiricist Approach
-
ed. by C. Faralli and E. Pattaro, Milano: Giuffré
-
I borrow this configuration of characterizing value-judgments from D. Zolo, 'Theoretical Language, Evaluations and Prescriptions: A Post-Empiricist Approach', in Reason in Law, ed. by C. Faralli and E. Pattaro, Vol. II (Milano: Giuffré, 1988), pp. 376-77.
-
(1988)
Reason in Law
, vol.2
, pp. 376-377
-
-
Zolo, D.1
-
23
-
-
0038948337
-
-
supra n. 3
-
For the ambiguity of this thesis, see H.L.A. Hart, 'Positivism and the Separation Between Law and Morals' (supra n. 3), pp. 593 ff. See also P. Greenawalt, 'Too Thin and Too Rich: Distinguishing Features of Legal Positivism', in The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism (supra n. 4), pp. 11-12.
-
Positivism and the Separation between Law and Morals
-
-
Hart, H.L.A.1
-
24
-
-
0043197137
-
Too Thin and Too Rich: Distinguishing Features of Legal Positivism
-
supra n. 4
-
For the ambiguity of this thesis, see H.L.A. Hart, 'Positivism and the Separation Between Law and Morals' (supra n. 3), pp. 593 ff. See also P. Greenawalt, 'Too Thin and Too Rich: Distinguishing Features of Legal Positivism', in The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism (supra n. 4), pp. 11-12.
-
The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal Positivism
, pp. 11-12
-
-
Greenawalt, P.1
-
27
-
-
0042768838
-
Ragion pratica e diritto naturale: Una difesa analitica del giusnaturalismo
-
This seems to me the opinion of F. Viola, 'Ragion pratica e diritto naturale: una difesa analitica del giusnaturalismo', in Ragion pratica 1 (1993): 61-81.
-
(1993)
Ragion Pratica
, vol.1
, pp. 61-81
-
-
Viola, F.1
-
28
-
-
0041144904
-
-
London: Edward Arnold
-
See, for instance, the ideas exposed by N. MacCormick, H.L.A. Hart (London: Edward Arnold, 1981), pp. 160-61, and 'Natural Law and the Separation of Law and Morals', in Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays, ed. by R.P. George (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 129-31 ; and by J. Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain. Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), p. 211.
-
(1981)
H.L.A. Hart
, pp. 160-161
-
-
MacCormick, N.1
-
29
-
-
0041694295
-
Natural Law and the Separation of Law and Morals
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
See, for instance, the ideas exposed by N. MacCormick, H.L.A. Hart (London: Edward Arnold, 1981), pp. 160-61, and 'Natural Law and the Separation of Law and Morals', in Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays, ed. by R.P. George (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 129-31 ; and by J. Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain. Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), p. 211.
-
(1992)
Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays
, pp. 129-131
-
-
George, R.P.1
-
30
-
-
0003472868
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
See, for instance, the ideas exposed by N. MacCormick, H.L.A. Hart (London: Edward Arnold, 1981), pp. 160-61, and 'Natural Law and the Separation of Law and Morals', in Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays, ed. by R.P. George (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 129-31 ; and by J. Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain. Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), p. 211.
-
(1994)
Ethics in the Public Domain. Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics
, pp. 211
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
34
-
-
0043197199
-
-
in his book Torino: Giappichelli
-
This is one of the main theses of F. Viola, in his book Il diritto come pratica sociale (Torino: Giappichelli, 1990).
-
(1990)
Il Diritto Come Pratica Sociale
-
-
Viola, F.1
-
35
-
-
0043270059
-
Intention in Interpretation
-
supra n. 17
-
J. Raz, 'Intention in Interpretation', in The Autonomy of Law (supra n. 17), pp. 260-61.
-
The Autonomy of Law
, pp. 260-261
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
42
-
-
0043197212
-
-
Ibid., p. 23. A similar position is expressed by A. Marmor, Interpretation and Legal Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 55-57.
-
Inclusive Legal Positivism
, pp. 23
-
-
-
43
-
-
0009328199
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Ibid., p. 23. A similar position is expressed by A. Marmor, Interpretation and Legal Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 55-57.
-
(1992)
Interpretation and Legal Theory
, pp. 55-57
-
-
Marmor, A.1
-
47
-
-
0042696103
-
The Ideal and the Actual of Law and Society
-
J. Tasioulas (ed.) Aldershot: Dartmouth Publishing Co, Section iv
-
N. MacCormick, The Ideal and the Actual of Law and Society', in J. Tasioulas (ed.) Law, Values and Social Practices (Aldershot: Dartmouth Publishing Co, 1997), pp. 15-37, Section iv.
-
(1997)
Law, Values and Social Practices
, pp. 15-37
-
-
MacCormick, N.1
-
49
-
-
0041694286
-
Taking the "Rights Thesis" Seriously
-
N. MacCormick, Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
This way of handling the matter is clearer in a previous paper, in which he explicitly speaks of a distinction between 'description' and 'criticism' of positive law. See N. MacCormick, 'Taking the "Rights Thesis" Seriously', in N. MacCormick, Legal Right and Social Democracy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), p. 140.
-
(1982)
Legal Right and Social Democracy
, pp. 140
-
-
MacCormick, N.1
-
50
-
-
0009325742
-
Natural Law and the Separation between Law and Morals
-
ed. by R.P. George Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
N. MacCormick, 'Natural Law and the Separation Between Law and Morals', in Natural Law Theory, ed. by R.P. George (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), p. 113.
-
(1992)
Natural Law Theory
, pp. 113
-
-
MacCormick, N.1
-
53
-
-
0009445978
-
Interpretation and Methodology in Legal Theory
-
ed. by A. Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
T. Perry, 'Interpretation and Methodology in Legal Theory', in Law and Interpretation. Essays in Legal Philosophy, ed. by A. Marmor (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), pp. 122-23.
-
(1995)
Law and Interpretation. Essays in Legal Philosophy
, pp. 122-123
-
-
Perry, T.1
-
56
-
-
0004072810
-
-
Oxford: Blackwell
-
For an exposition and a criticism of this image, and for the use of this metaphor in analysing it, see the already classical book of R. Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980).
-
(1980)
Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature
-
-
Rorty, R.1
-
57
-
-
0042195027
-
-
ed. and intro. by J. Conant Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
-
H. Putnam, Realism with a Human Face, ed. and intro. by J. Conant (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990), p. 150. A similar position, which tracks down the sources of 'facts/values' dichotomy in the mistaken alternative between 'strong cognitivism' in epistemology and 'non cognitivism' about values, is stressed by J. McDowell, 'Non-Cognitivism and Rule Following', in Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule, ed. by J. Holtzmann and C. Leich (London: Routledge & Kegan, 1981), pp. 141-42. For an analysis which tries to apply these ideas in the legal domain, see my 'Normative Coherence and Epistemological Presuppositions of Justification', in Law, Interpretation and Reality: Essays in Epistemology, Hermeneutics and Jurisprudence, ed. P. Nerhot (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990), pp. 439-42.
-
(1990)
Realism with a Human Face
, pp. 150
-
-
Putnam, H.1
-
58
-
-
85068201368
-
Non-Cognitivism and Rule Following
-
ed. by J. Holtzmann and C. Leich London: Routledge & Kegan
-
H. Putnam, Realism with a Human Face, ed. and intro. by J. Conant (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990), p. 150. A similar position, which tracks down the sources of 'facts/values' dichotomy in the mistaken alternative between 'strong cognitivism' in epistemology and 'non cognitivism' about values, is stressed by J. McDowell, 'Non-Cognitivism and Rule Following', in Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule, ed. by J. Holtzmann and C. Leich (London: Routledge & Kegan, 1981), pp. 141-42. For an analysis which tries to apply these ideas in the legal domain, see my 'Normative Coherence and Epistemological Presuppositions of Justification', in Law, Interpretation and Reality: Essays in Epistemology, Hermeneutics and Jurisprudence, ed. P. Nerhot (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990), pp. 439-42.
-
(1981)
Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule
, pp. 141-142
-
-
McDowell, J.1
-
59
-
-
0042696115
-
Normative Coherence and Epistemological Presuppositions of Justification
-
Dordrecht: Kluwer
-
H. Putnam, Realism with a Human Face, ed. and intro. by J. Conant (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990), p. 150. A similar position, which tracks down the sources of 'facts/values' dichotomy in the mistaken alternative between 'strong cognitivism' in epistemology and 'non cognitivism' about values, is stressed by J. McDowell, 'Non-Cognitivism and Rule Following', in Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule, ed. by J. Holtzmann and C. Leich (London: Routledge & Kegan, 1981), pp. 141-42. For an analysis which tries to apply these ideas in the legal domain, see my 'Normative Coherence and Epistemological Presuppositions of Justification', in Law, Interpretation and Reality: Essays in Epistemology, Hermeneutics and Jurisprudence, ed. P. Nerhot (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990), pp. 439-42.
-
(1990)
Law, Interpretation and Reality: Essays in Epistemology, Hermeneutics and Jurisprudence
, pp. 439-442
-
-
Nerhot, P.1
-
60
-
-
0042195017
-
-
supra n. 1
-
See again my book Conoscenza giuridica e concetto di diritto positivo (supra n. 1), pp. 187-228, and my more recent essay 'La science juridique entre descriptivisme et constructivisme', in Théorie du droit et science, ed. by P. Amselek (Paris: PUF, 1994), pp. 281-91.
-
Conoscenza Giuridica e Concetto di Diritto Positivo
, pp. 187-228
-
-
-
61
-
-
85012446954
-
La science juridique entre descriptivisme et constructivisme
-
Paris: PUF
-
See again my book Conoscenza giuridica e concetto di diritto positivo (supra n. 1), pp. 187-228, and my more recent essay 'La science juridique entre descriptivisme et constructivisme', in Théorie du droit et science, ed. by P. Amselek (Paris: PUF, 1994), pp. 281-91.
-
(1994)
Théorie du Droit et Science
, pp. 281-291
-
-
Amselek, P.1
-
62
-
-
0004120857
-
-
La Salle, Illinois: Open Court
-
Good examples of the kind of constructivism that I defend here can be considered, among others, the works of Putnam (see, for instance, H. Putnam, The Many Faces of Realism (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1987)), Goodman (see N. Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett, 1978)), Hesse (M. Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1980)), and Knorr Cetina (K. D. Knorr Cetina, The Manufacture of Knowledge (Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1981)).
-
(1987)
The Many Faces of Realism
-
-
Putnam, H.1
-
63
-
-
0003939914
-
-
Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett
-
Good examples of the kind of constructivism that I defend here can be considered, among others, the works of Putnam (see, for instance, H. Putnam, The Many Faces of Realism (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1987)), Goodman (see N. Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett, 1978)), Hesse (M. Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1980)), and Knorr Cetina (K. D. Knorr Cetina, The Manufacture of Knowledge (Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1981)).
-
(1978)
Ways of Worldmaking
-
-
Goodman, N.1
-
64
-
-
0003839588
-
-
Brighton: Harvester Press
-
Good examples of the kind of constructivism that I defend here can be considered, among others, the works of Putnam (see, for instance, H. Putnam, The Many Faces of Realism (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1987)), Goodman (see N. Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett, 1978)), Hesse (M. Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1980)), and Knorr Cetina (K. D. Knorr Cetina, The Manufacture of Knowledge (Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1981)).
-
(1980)
Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science
-
-
Hesse, M.1
-
65
-
-
0003764788
-
-
Oxford: Pergamon Press
-
Good examples of the kind of constructivism that I defend here can be considered, among others, the works of Putnam (see, for instance, H. Putnam, The Many Faces of Realism (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1987)), Goodman (see N. Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett, 1978)), Hesse (M. Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions in the Philosophy of Science (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1980)), and Knorr Cetina (K. D. Knorr Cetina, The Manufacture of Knowledge (Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1981)).
-
(1981)
The Manufacture of Knowledge
-
-
Cetina, K.D.K.1
-
67
-
-
0004235120
-
-
supra n. 9
-
See H. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (supra n. 9), p. 231. See also, in a similar vein, N. Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (supra n. 49), p. 17.
-
Reason, Truth and History
, pp. 231
-
-
Putnam, H.1
-
68
-
-
0003939914
-
-
supra n. 49
-
See H. Putnam, Reason, Truth and History (supra n. 9), p. 231. See also, in a similar vein, N. Goodman, Ways of Worldmaking (supra n. 49), p. 17.
-
Ways of Worldmaking
, pp. 17
-
-
Goodman, N.1
-
69
-
-
0009425079
-
On the Reasons for Indeterminacy of Translation
-
One of the most classical versions of this thesis is offered by Quine. See, for instance, W.V.O. Quine, 'On the Reasons for Indeterminacy of Translation', The Journal of Philosophy 61 (1970): 179.
-
(1970)
The Journal of Philosophy
, vol.61
, pp. 179
-
-
Quine, W.V.O.1
-
70
-
-
24444456034
-
-
supra n. 49
-
See, for this suggestion, at a general epistemological level, M. Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions (supra n. 49), pp. 133 ff., 188 ff., 193 ff.; and, with specific reference to human sciences, D. Thomas, Naturalism and Social Science: A Post-Empiricist Philosophy of Social Science (Cambridge: Cambridge Univer- sity Press, 1979), pp. 126-27.
-
Revolutions and Reconstructions
-
-
Hesse, M.1
-
71
-
-
0040257385
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-sity Press
-
See, for this suggestion, at a general epistemological level, M. Hesse, Revolutions and Reconstructions (supra n. 49), pp. 133 ff., 188 ff., 193 ff.; and, with specific reference to human sciences, D. Thomas, Naturalism and Social Science: A Post-Empiricist Philosophy of Social Science (Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-sity Press, 1979), pp. 126-27.
-
(1979)
Naturalism and Social Science: A Post-Empiricist Philosophy of Social Science
, pp. 126-127
-
-
Thomas, D.1
-
74
-
-
0003981612
-
-
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
-
Quite obvious here is the great debt that this approach to legal value-judgments owes to Dworkin. As a matter of fact, many central points of my work are deeply influenced by Dworkin's thinking. Here there are some examples. Firstly, my idea that understanding a given positive law requires an ethical appreciation of its values is closely connected with dworkinian aesthetic hypothesis (see R. Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 149-53). Secondly, my distinction between different kinds of (cognitive and creative) value-judgments is very close to the dworkinian distinction between 'interpreting while creating' and 'creating while interpreting' (ibid., p. 158). Thirdly, my suggestion on value-judgments as criteria of theory-choice in the legal domain resembles the way in which Dworkin conceives the underdetermination of raw behavioral data by the ascription of values (see R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (supra n. 9), p. 52)). There are, however, many important points in which I disagree remarkably with Dworkin. Apart from Dworkin's frequent lack of analytical rigour and from his reticence in highlighting his epistemological and semantical presuppositions, what doesn't convince me, speaking generally, is, among other things, Dworkin's choice of the participant's point of view as the correct stance for the legal theorist (ibid., p. 147). The fact is that Dworkin, after all, ends by accepting the very thesis of traditional positivists that he has so heavily criticized: I am referring to the thesis which equates ethical value- judgments expressed in legal practices with judgments produced invariably from the inside of the practice and possessing always a practical character. To sum up, for Dworkin to express an ethical value-judgment, in the context of a legal system, amounts to justifying its acceptance or rejection from a moral point of view or at least to justify some specific decision taken on the basis of its rules or principles.
-
(1985)
A Matter of Principle
, pp. 149-153
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
75
-
-
85022418750
-
-
Quite obvious here is the great debt that this approach to legal value- judgments owes to Dworkin. As a matter of fact, many central points of my work are deeply influenced by Dworkin's thinking. Here there are some examples. Firstly, my idea that understanding a given positive law requires an ethical appreciation of its values is closely connected with dworkinian aesthetic hypothesis (see R. Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 149-53). Secondly, my distinction between different kinds of (cognitive and creative) value-judgments is very close to the dworkinian distinction between 'interpreting while creating' and 'creating while interpreting' (ibid., p. 158). Thirdly, my suggestion on value-judgments as criteria of theory-choice in the legal domain resembles the way in which Dworkin conceives the underdetermination of raw behavioral data by the ascription of values (see R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (supra n. 9), p. 52)). There are, however, many important points in which I disagree remarkably with Dworkin. Apart from Dworkin's frequent lack of analytical rigour and from his reticence in highlighting his epistemological and semantical presuppositions, what doesn't convince me, speaking generally, is, among other things, Dworkin's choice of the participant's point of view as the correct stance for the legal theorist (ibid., p. 147). The fact is that Dworkin, after all, ends by accepting the very thesis of traditional positivists that he has so heavily criticized: I am referring to the thesis which equates ethical value- judgments expressed in legal practices with judgments produced invariably from the inside of the practice and possessing always a practical character. To sum up, for Dworkin to express an ethical value-judgment, in the context of a legal system, amounts to justifying its acceptance or rejection from a moral point of view or at least to justify some specific decision taken on the basis of its rules or principles.
-
A Matter of Principle
, pp. 158
-
-
-
76
-
-
84936068266
-
-
supra n. 9
-
Quite obvious here is the great debt that this approach to legal value- judgments owes to Dworkin. As a matter of fact, many central points of my work are deeply influenced by Dworkin's thinking. Here there are some examples. Firstly, my idea that understanding a given positive law requires an ethical appreciation of its values is closely connected with dworkinian aesthetic hypothesis (see R. Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 149-53). Secondly, my distinction between different kinds of (cognitive and creative) value-judgments is very close to the dworkinian distinction between 'interpreting while creating' and 'creating while interpreting' (ibid., p. 158). Thirdly, my suggestion on value-judgments as criteria of theory-choice in the legal domain resembles the way in which Dworkin conceives the underdetermination of raw behavioral data by the ascription of values (see R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (supra n. 9), p. 52)). There are, however, many important points in which I disagree remarkably with Dworkin. Apart from Dworkin's frequent lack of analytical rigour and from his reticence in highlighting his epistemological and semantical presuppositions, what doesn't convince me, speaking generally, is, among other things, Dworkin's choice of the participant's point of view as the correct stance for the legal theorist (ibid., p. 147). The fact is that Dworkin, after all, ends by accepting the very thesis of traditional positivists that he has so heavily criticized: I am referring to the thesis which equates ethical value- judgments expressed in legal practices with judgments produced invariably from the inside of the practice and possessing always a practical character. To sum up, for Dworkin to express an ethical value-judgment, in the context of a legal system, amounts to justifying its acceptance or rejection from a moral point of view or at least to justify some specific decision taken on the basis of its rules or principles.
-
Law's Empire
, pp. 52
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
77
-
-
0004166519
-
-
Quite obvious here is the great debt that this approach to legal value- judgments owes to Dworkin. As a matter of fact, many central points of my work are deeply influenced by Dworkin's thinking. Here there are some examples. Firstly, my idea that understanding a given positive law requires an ethical appreciation of its values is closely connected with dworkinian aesthetic hypothesis (see R. Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 149-53). Secondly, my distinction between different kinds of (cognitive and creative) value-judgments is very close to the dworkinian distinction between 'interpreting while creating' and 'creating while interpreting' (ibid., p. 158). Thirdly, my suggestion on value-judgments as criteria of theory-choice in the legal domain resembles the way in which Dworkin conceives the underdetermination of raw behavioral data by the ascription of values (see R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (supra n. 9), p. 52)). There are, however, many important points in which I disagree remarkably with Dworkin. Apart from Dworkin's frequent lack of analytical rigour and from his reticence in highlighting his epistemological and semantical presuppositions, what doesn't convince me, speaking generally, is, among other things, Dworkin's choice of the participant's point of view as the correct stance for the legal theorist (ibid., p. 147). The fact is that Dworkin, after all, ends by accepting the very thesis of traditional positivists that he has so heavily criticized: I am referring to the thesis which equates ethical value-judgments expressed in legal practices with judgments produced invariably from the inside of the practice and possessing always a practical character. To sum up, for Dworkin to express an ethical value-judgment, in the context of a legal system, amounts to justifying its acceptance or rejection from a moral point of view or at least to justify some specific decision taken on the basis of its rules or principles.
-
Law's Empire
, pp. 147
-
-
|