메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 29, Issue 3, 1997, Pages 323-342

At odds with themselves: David Hume's skeptical citizens

(1)  Chabot, Dana a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0031286631     PISSN: 00323497     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/3235310     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (4)

References (57)
  • 1
    • 0010923838 scopus 로고
    • London: Jonathan Cape
    • 1. Salman Rushdie, East, West (London: Jonathan Cape, 1994), p. 209.
    • (1994) East, West , pp. 209
    • Rushdie, S.1
  • 2
    • 0010923487 scopus 로고
    • ed. Clarence Page Evanston: Northwestern University Press
    • 2. Leanita McClain, A Foot in Each World, ed. Clarence Page (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1986), p. 14.
    • (1986) A Foot in Each World , pp. 14
    • McClain, L.1
  • 3
    • 0000028289 scopus 로고
    • Disjunction and Ambivalence in Citizens' Political Outlooks
    • ed. George Marcus and Russell Hanson University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press
    • 3. Jennifer Hochschild, "Disjunction and Ambivalence in Citizens' Political Outlooks," in Reconsidering the Democratic Public, ed. George Marcus and Russell Hanson (University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1993), p. 206.
    • (1993) Reconsidering the Democratic Public , pp. 206
    • Hochschild, J.1
  • 4
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press, 225. Rawls qualifies this later when he says that in some cases "reasons given explicitly in terms of comprehensive doctrines" may be permitted in discussions involving "funda" mental political matters," and he acknowledges that "the limits imposed by public reason" do not apply in cases where nonfundamental questions are in dispute (pp. 214, 247)
    • 4. John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), pp. 224, 225. Rawls qualifies this later when he says that in some cases "reasons given explicitly in terms of comprehensive doctrines" may be permitted in discussions involving "funda" mental political matters," and he acknowledges that "the limits imposed by public reason" do not apply in cases where nonfundamental questions are in dispute (pp. 214, 247). I take the term "bracketing" from Michael Sandel's review of Political Liberalism in the Harvard Law Review (1994): 1765-94.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism , pp. 224
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 5
    • 0010874913 scopus 로고
    • 4. John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), pp. 224, 225. Rawls qualifies this later when he says that in some cases "reasons given explicitly in terms of comprehensive doctrines" may be permitted in discussions involving "funda" mental political matters," and he acknowledges that "the limits imposed by public reason" do not apply in cases where nonfundamental questions are in dispute (pp. 214, 247). I take the term "bracketing" from Michael Sandel's review of Political Liberalism in the Harvard Law Review (1994): 1765-94.
    • (1994) Political Liberalism in the Harvard Law Review , pp. 1765-1794
    • Sandel's, M.1
  • 7
    • 84935626607 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism and the Art of Separation
    • 6. Michael Walzer, Liberalism and the Art of Separation," Political Theory, 12 (1984): 325.
    • (1984) Political Theory , vol.12 , pp. 325
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 8
    • 0002805552 scopus 로고
    • Undemocratic Education
    • ed. Nancy Rosenblum Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • 7. Amy Gutmann, "Undemocratic Education," Liberalism and the Moral Life, ed. Nancy Rosenblum (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989), p. 77.
    • (1989) Liberalism and the Moral Life , pp. 77
    • Gutmann, A.1
  • 9
    • 0003925898 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press, 54
    • 8. Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), pp. 53, 54.
    • (1990) Liberal Virtues , pp. 53
    • Macedo, S.1
  • 10
    • 84937310738 scopus 로고
    • Difference, Dilemmas, and the Politics of Home
    • These do not exhaust the possibilities. Bonnie Honig argues that civic strain should be turned against the social structure that produces it
    • 9. These do not exhaust the possibilities. Bonnie Honig argues that civic strain should be turned against the social structure that produces it ["Difference, Dilemmas, and the Politics of Home," Social Research, 61 (1994): 563-97]. Brian Walker argues that the experience of civic strain calls for a revised, postmodern conception of toleration ["John Rawls, Mikhail Bakhtin, and the Praxis of Toleration," Political Theory, 23 (1995): 101-27].
    • (1994) Social Research , vol.61 , pp. 563-597
  • 11
    • 84970775452 scopus 로고
    • John Rawls, Mikhail Bakhtin, and the Praxis of Toleration
    • Brian Walker argues that the experience of civic strain calls for a revised, postmodern conception of toleration
    • 9. These do not exhaust the possibilities. Bonnie Honig argues that civic strain should be turned against the social structure that produces it ["Difference, Dilemmas, and the Politics of Home," Social Research, 61 (1994): 563-97]. Brian Walker argues that the experience of civic strain calls for a revised, postmodern conception of toleration ["John Rawls, Mikhail Bakhtin, and the Praxis of Toleration," Political Theory, 23 (1995): 101-27].
    • (1995) Political Theory , vol.23 , pp. 101-127
  • 12
    • 0003475194 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press, links Hume's skepticism with political conservatism
    • 10. Donald Livingston, Hume's Philosophy of Common Life (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), p. 310, links Hume's skepticism with political conservatism. For a similar view see David Miller, Philosophy and Ideology in Hume's Political Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), p. 191, and Sheldon Wolin, "Hume and Conservatism," in Hume: A Re-Evaluation, ed. Donald Livingston and James King (New York: Fordham University Press, 1976), pp. 239-56. Duncan Forbes, Hume's Philosophical Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975) and David Wootton, "David Hume, 'The Historian,'" in The Cambridge Companion to Hume, ed. David Norton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 281-312, argue that Hume was both a defender of the post-1688 Whig establishment and an internal (or skeptical) critic of its intellectual foundations.
    • (1984) Hume's Philosophy of Common Life , pp. 310
    • Livingston, D.1
  • 13
    • 0003918640 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • 10. Donald Livingston, Hume's Philosophy of Common Life (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), p. 310, links Hume's skepticism with political conservatism. For a similar view see David Miller, Philosophy and Ideology in Hume's Political Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), p. 191, and Sheldon Wolin, "Hume and Conservatism," in Hume: A Re-Evaluation, ed. Donald Livingston and James King (New York: Fordham University Press, 1976), pp. 239-56. Duncan Forbes, Hume's Philosophical Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975) and David Wootton, "David Hume, 'The Historian,'" in The Cambridge Companion to Hume, ed. David Norton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 281-312, argue that Hume was both a defender of the post-1688 Whig establishment and an internal (or skeptical) critic of its intellectual foundations.
    • (1981) Philosophy and Ideology in Hume's Political Thought , pp. 191
    • Miller, D.1
  • 14
    • 0010804692 scopus 로고
    • Hume and conservatism
    • ed. Donald Livingston and James King New York: Fordham University Press
    • 10. Donald Livingston, Hume's Philosophy of Common Life (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), p. 310, links Hume's skepticism with political conservatism. For a similar view see David Miller, Philosophy and Ideology in Hume's Political Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), p. 191, and Sheldon Wolin, "Hume and Conservatism," in Hume: A Re-Evaluation, ed. Donald Livingston and James King (New York: Fordham University Press, 1976), pp. 239-56. Duncan Forbes, Hume's Philosophical Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975) and David Wootton, "David Hume, 'The Historian,'" in The Cambridge Companion to Hume, ed. David Norton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 281-312, argue that Hume was both a defender of the post-1688 Whig establishment and an internal (or skeptical) critic of its intellectual foundations.
    • (1976) Hume: A Re-evaluation , pp. 239-256
    • Wolin, S.1
  • 15
    • 0004195953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • 10. Donald Livingston, Hume's Philosophy of Common Life (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), p. 310, links Hume's skepticism with political conservatism. For a similar view see David Miller, Philosophy and Ideology in Hume's Political Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), p. 191, and Sheldon Wolin, "Hume and Conservatism," in Hume: A Re-Evaluation, ed. Donald Livingston and James King (New York: Fordham University Press, 1976), pp. 239-56. Duncan Forbes, Hume's Philosophical Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975) and David Wootton, "David Hume, 'The Historian,'" in The Cambridge Companion to Hume, ed. David Norton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 281-312, argue that Hume was both a defender of the post-1688 Whig establishment and an internal (or skeptical) critic of its intellectual foundations.
    • (1975) Hume's Philosophical Politics
    • Forbes, D.1
  • 16
    • 0010923839 scopus 로고
    • David Hume, 'The Historian,'
    • ed. David Norton Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, argue that Hume was both a defender of the post-1688 Whig establishment and an internal (or skeptical) critic of its intellectual foundations
    • 10. Donald Livingston, Hume's Philosophy of Common Life (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), p. 310, links Hume's skepticism with political conservatism. For a similar view see David Miller, Philosophy and Ideology in Hume's Political Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), p. 191, and Sheldon Wolin, "Hume and Conservatism," in Hume: A Re-Evaluation, ed. Donald Livingston and James King (New York: Fordham University Press, 1976), pp. 239-56. Duncan Forbes, Hume's Philosophical Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975) and David Wootton, "David Hume, 'The Historian,'" in The Cambridge Companion to Hume, ed. David Norton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 281-312, argue that Hume was both a defender of the post-1688 Whig establishment and an internal (or skeptical) critic of its intellectual foundations.
    • (1993) The Cambridge Companion to Hume , pp. 281-312
    • Wootton, D.1
  • 17
    • 0003441843 scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press, Norton has accepted Norman Kemp Smith's identification of Hume as a nonskeptical moralist
    • 11. David Norton, David Hume: Common-Sense Moralist, Sceptical Metaphysician (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1982), p. 43. Norton has accepted Norman Kemp Smith's identification of Hume as a nonskeptical moralist (The Philosophy of David Hume [London: MacMillan, 1960], p. 155) but quarrels with Smith's characterization of him as a naturalist. Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988), p. 293; Annette Baier, A Progress of Sentiments: Reflections on Hume's Treatise (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991), p. 285; and John Stewart, Opinion and Reform in Hume's Political Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), p. 194, also deny that skepticism was a major factor in Hume's moral theory.
    • (1982) David Hume: Common-sense Moralist, Sceptical Metaphysician , pp. 43
    • Norton, D.1
  • 18
    • 17544384343 scopus 로고
    • London: MacMillan, but quarrels with Smith's characterization of him as a naturalist
    • 11. David Norton, David Hume: Common-Sense Moralist, Sceptical Metaphysician (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1982), p. 43. Norton has accepted Norman Kemp Smith's identification of Hume as a nonskeptical moralist (The Philosophy of David Hume [London: MacMillan, 1960], p. 155) but quarrels with Smith's characterization of him as a naturalist. Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988), p. 293; Annette Baier, A Progress of Sentiments: Reflections on Hume's Treatise (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991), p. 285; and John Stewart, Opinion and Reform in Hume's Political Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), p. 194, also deny that skepticism was a major factor in Hume's moral theory.
    • (1960) The Philosophy of David Hume , pp. 155
  • 19
    • 0003392316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press
    • 11. David Norton, David Hume: Common-Sense Moralist, Sceptical Metaphysician (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1982), p. 43. Norton has accepted Norman Kemp Smith's identification of Hume as a nonskeptical moralist (The Philosophy of David Hume [London: MacMillan, 1960], p. 155) but quarrels with Smith's characterization of him as a naturalist. Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988), p. 293; Annette Baier, A Progress of Sentiments: Reflections on Hume's Treatise (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991), p. 285; and John Stewart, Opinion and Reform in Hume's Political Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), p. 194, also deny that skepticism was a major factor in Hume's moral theory.
    • (1988) Whose Justice? Which Rationality? , pp. 293
    • Macintyre, A.1
  • 20
    • 0010923840 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • 11. David Norton, David Hume: Common-Sense Moralist, Sceptical Metaphysician (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1982), p. 43. Norton has accepted Norman Kemp Smith's identification of Hume as a nonskeptical moralist (The Philosophy of David Hume [London: MacMillan, 1960], p. 155) but quarrels with Smith's characterization of him as a naturalist. Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988), p. 293; Annette Baier, A Progress of Sentiments: Reflections on Hume's Treatise (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991), p. 285; and John Stewart, Opinion and Reform in Hume's Political Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), p. 194, also deny that skepticism was a major factor in Hume's moral theory.
    • (1991) A Progress of Sentiments: Reflections on Hume's Treatise , pp. 285
    • Baier, A.1
  • 21
    • 0004183317 scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • 11. David Norton, David Hume: Common-Sense Moralist, Sceptical Metaphysician (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1982), p. 43. Norton has accepted Norman Kemp Smith's identification of Hume as a nonskeptical moralist (The Philosophy of David Hume [London: MacMillan, 1960], p. 155) but quarrels with Smith's characterization of him as a naturalist. Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988), p. 293; Annette Baier, A Progress of Sentiments: Reflections on Hume's Treatise (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991), p. 285; and John Stewart, Opinion and Reform in Hume's Political Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), p. 194, also deny that skepticism was a major factor in Hume's moral theory.
    • (1992) Opinion and Reform in Hume's Political Philosophy , pp. 194
    • Stewart, J.1
  • 22
    • 0010865075 scopus 로고
    • ed. P. H. Nidditch Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • 12. Hume, Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), p. 24, hereafter cited as EM. Hume's other major works will be cited as follows: (E) Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene Miller (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1985); (EU) Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975); (H) History of England, 6 volumes (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1983); (T) Treatise of Human Nature, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978).
    • (1975) Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals , pp. 24
  • 23
    • 0003970946 scopus 로고
    • ed. Eugene Miller Indianapolis: Liberty Press
    • 12. Hume, Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), p. 24, hereafter cited as EM. Hume's other major works will be cited as follows: (E) Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene Miller (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1985); (EU) Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975); (H) History of England, 6 volumes (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1983); (T) Treatise of Human Nature, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978).
    • (1985) (E) Essays Moral, Political, and Literary
  • 24
    • 0003553033 scopus 로고
    • ed. P. H. Nidditch Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • 12. Hume, Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), p. 24, hereafter cited as EM. Hume's other major works will be cited as follows: (E) Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene Miller (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1985); (EU) Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975); (H) History of England, 6 volumes (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1983); (T) Treatise of Human Nature, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978).
    • (1975) (Eu) Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding
  • 25
    • 0010931484 scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis: Liberty Press
    • 12. Hume, Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), p. 24, hereafter cited as EM. Hume's other major works will be cited as follows: (E) Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene Miller (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1985); (EU) Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975); (H) History of England, 6 volumes (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1983); (T) Treatise of Human Nature, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978).
    • (1983) (H) History of England , vol.6
  • 26
    • 79953481483 scopus 로고
    • ed. P. H. Nidditch Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • 12. Hume, Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), p. 24, hereafter cited as EM. Hume's other major works will be cited as follows: (E) Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene Miller (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1985); (EU) Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975); (H) History of England, 6 volumes (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1983); (T) Treatise of Human Nature, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978).
    • (1978) (T) Treatise of Human Nature
  • 28
    • 0010921787 scopus 로고
    • Letter to John Stewart (February, 1754), ed. J. Y. T. Grieg Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • 14. Letter to John Stewart (February, 1754), The Letters of David Hume, ed. J. Y. T. Grieg (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1932), volume 1: 186-87.
    • (1932) The Letters of David Hume , vol.1 , pp. 186-187
  • 31
    • 0003415047 scopus 로고
    • New Haven: Yale University Press
    • 17. See also John Danford, David Hume and the Problem of Reason: Recovering the Human Sciences (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1990), p. 161. A somewhat different statement of Hume's pluralism is offered by Albert Hirschman, The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism Before Its Triumph (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1977), p. 26.
    • (1990) Problem of Reason: Recovering the Human Sciences , pp. 161
    • Danford, J.1    Hume, D.2
  • 32
    • 0004061036 scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • 17. See also John Danford, David Hume and the Problem of Reason: Recovering the Human Sciences (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1990), p. 161. A somewhat different statement of Hume's pluralism is offered by Albert Hirschman, The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism Before Its Triumph (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1977), p. 26.
    • (1977) The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism Before Its Triumph , pp. 26
    • Hirschman, A.1
  • 37
    • 0004340034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 22. Baier, A Progress of Sentiments, p. 277. Nicholas Capaldi, Hume's Place in Moral Philosophy (New York: Peter Lang, 1989), pp. 21-22, makes a similar claim, arguing that Hume rejected the rationalist, or "I Think," model of reason in favor of a more action-oriented, "We Do" model of reason.
    • A Progress of Sentiments , pp. 277
  • 38
    • 0003634001 scopus 로고
    • New York: Peter Lang, makes a similar claim, arguing that Hume rejected the rationalist, or "I Think," model of reason in favor of a more action-oriented, "We Do" model of reason.
    • 22. Baier, A Progress of Sentiments, p. 277. Nicholas Capaldi, Hume's Place in Moral Philosophy (New York: Peter Lang, 1989), pp. 21-22, makes a similar claim, arguing that Hume rejected the rationalist, or "I Think," model of reason in favor of a more action-oriented, "We Do" model of reason.
    • (1989) Hume's Place in Moral Philosophy , pp. 21-22
    • Capaldi, N.1
  • 41
    • 4243450213 scopus 로고
    • "Hume, hermeneutics, and history: A 'sympathetic' account,"
    • As James Farr has observed, Hume used sympathy in the Treatise not as a synonym for 'pity,' 'empathy,' or 'fellow-feeling,' but to denote an active principle of communication. "To put it bluntly, our sympathizing with others is something we do or engage in, not something which simply happens to us" Note the resemblance between Fair's account of sympathy and Capaldi's discovery of an active "We Do" conception of reason in Hume's moral philosophy
    • 25. As James Farr has observed, Hume used sympathy in the Treatise not as a synonym for 'pity,' 'empathy,' or 'fellow-feeling,' but to denote an active principle of communication. "To put it bluntly, our sympathizing with others is something we do or engage in, not something which simply happens to us" ("Hume, Hermeneutics, and History: A 'Sympathetic' Account," History and Theory, 17 [1978]: 296). Note the resemblance between Fair's account of sympathy and Capaldi's discovery of an active "We Do" conception of reason in Hume's moral philosophy, Hume's Place in Moral Philosophy, pp. 195-235.
    • (1978) History and Theory , vol.17 , pp. 296
  • 42
    • 84880436245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 25. As James Farr has observed, Hume used sympathy in the Treatise not as a synonym for 'pity,' 'empathy,' or 'fellow-feeling,' but to denote an active principle of communication. "To put it bluntly, our sympathizing with others is something we do or engage in, not something which simply happens to us" ("Hume, Hermeneutics, and History: A 'Sympathetic' Account," History and Theory, 17 [1978]: 296). Note the resemblance between Fair's account of sympathy and Capaldi's discovery of an active "We Do" conception of reason in Hume's moral philosophy, Hume's Place in Moral Philosophy, pp. 195-235.
    • Hume's Place in Moral Philosophy , pp. 195-235
  • 43
    • 0010877920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "When men act in a faction, they are apt, without shame or remorse, to neglect all the ties of honour and morality, in order to serve their party"; especially, Hume added, when driven by a "determined sense of justice and equity" (E33). and "party-zeal" in
    • 26. "When men act in a faction, they are apt, without shame or remorse, to neglect all the ties of honour and morality, in order to serve their party"; especially, Hume added, when driven by a "determined sense of justice and equity" (E33). See also the discussion of "party-zealots" in That Politics May be Reduced to a Science (E 28) and "party-zeal" in Of the Original Contract (E 466).
    • That Politics May Be Reduced to A Science (E 28)
  • 44
    • 0010865079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 26. "When men act in a faction, they are apt, without shame or remorse, to neglect all the ties of honour and morality, in order to serve their party"; especially, Hume added, when driven by a "determined sense of justice and equity" (E33). See also the discussion of "party-zealots" in That Politics May be Reduced to a Science (E 28) and "party-zeal" in Of the Original Contract (E 466).
    • Of the Original Contract (E 466)
  • 45
    • 0010933578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 27. Unlike "artificial" virtues, which are "mere human contrivances for the good of society," natural virtues "have no dependance on the artifice and contrivance of men" (T 574, 577). Justice, promise-keeping, and modesty are examples of the former; benevolence, good humor, and "a due degree of pride" are examples of the latter (T 596).
  • 46
    • 85055311667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Forbes, Hume was trying "to give the established regime, the Revolution Settlement, the Hanoverian succession, the respectable intellectual foundation which, in the 'fashionable [Whig] system' it had not got"
    • 28. According to Forbes, Hume was trying "to give the established regime, the Revolution Settlement, the Hanoverian succession, the respectable intellectual foundation which, in the 'fashionable [Whig] system' it had not got" (Hume's Philosophical Politics, p. 91).
    • Hume's Philosophical Politics , pp. 91
  • 47
    • 84921367129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Livingston concedes that Hume's conservatism was not "a mindless disposition to preserve the established regime," but "a doctrine of limits, in particular a doctrine of the limits beyond which philosophical criticism of social and political order cannot go"
    • 29. Livingston concedes that Hume's conservatism was not "a mindless disposition to preserve the established regime," but "a doctrine of limits, in particular a doctrine of the limits beyond which philosophical criticism of social and political order cannot go" (Hume's Philosophy of Common Life, p. 308).
    • Hume's Philosophy of Common Life , pp. 308
  • 48
    • 85055311667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 30. Forbes, Hume's Philosophical Politics, pp. 224-27. Similarly, J. G. A. Pocock, "Hume and the American Revolution: The Dying Thoughts of a North Briton," Virtue, Commerce, and History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), maintains that Hume disconnected virtue from politics, seeing commerce and refinement in the arts as more critical factors in a modern state's political wellbeing.
    • Hume's Philosophical Politics , pp. 224-227
  • 49
    • 84899736130 scopus 로고
    • Hume and the American Revolution: The Dying Thoughts of a North Briton
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, maintains that Hume disconnected virtue from politics, seeing commerce and refinement in the arts as more critical factors in a modern state's political wellbeing.
    • 30. Forbes, Hume's Philosophical Politics, pp. 224-27. Similarly, J. G. A. Pocock, "Hume and the American Revolution: The Dying Thoughts of a North Briton," Virtue, Commerce, and History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), maintains that Hume disconnected virtue from politics, seeing commerce and refinement in the arts as more critical factors in a modern state's political wellbeing.
    • (1985) Virtue, Commerce, and History
    • Pocock, J.G.A.1
  • 50
    • 0010875726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 31. H 5:572. Contrast Hume's critical character sketches of Becket (H 1:306-334), Laud (H 5:222-229), Cromwell (H 6:95-96, 105-110), and Vane (H 6:180-182) with his laudatory remarks about Lucius Cary (H 5:416-417), Lawrence Hyde (H 6:163-165), William Temple (H 6:219-220), and Thomas Fairfax (H 5:449-450), all of whom managed to come to terms with the tension built into their country's constitution.
  • 53
  • 55
    • 0009320151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Duty Is a Four-Letter Word: Democratic Citizenship in the Liberal Polity
    • 36. Pamela Johnston Conover, Stephen Leonard, and Donald Searing, "Duty Is a Four-Letter Word: Democratic Citizenship in the Liberal Polity," in Reconsidering the Democratic Public, p. 166.
    • Reconsidering the Democratic Public , pp. 166
    • Conover, P.J.1    Leonard, S.2    Searing, D.3


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.