메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 28, Issue 3, 1997, Pages 417-437

Whewell on the ultimate problem of philosophy

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0031232166     PISSN: 00393681     EISSN: 18792510     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1016/S0039-3681(96)00028-3     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (11)

References (49)
  • 1
    • 0004274568 scopus 로고
    • are to the Second Edition Facimile London, reprinted by Johnson Reprint Company New York
    • 1 All references to the Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences (PIS) are to the Second Edition Facimile (London, 1847) reprinted by Johnson Reprint Company (New York, 1967).
    • (1847) Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences (PIS)
  • 2
    • 0003398691 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • 2 M. Fisch (1991) William Whewell, Philosopher of Science (Oxford: Oxford University Press); L. Snyder (1994) 'It's All Necessarily So: William Whewell on Scientific Truth', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 25, 785-807; R. E. Butts (1965) 'Necessary Truth in Whewell's Theory of Science', American Philosophical Quarterly 2,161-181; K. Ducasse (1951) 'Whewell's Philosophy of Scientific Discovery, Parts I and II', Philosophical Review 60, 46-59, 213-234.
    • (1991) William Whewell, Philosopher of Science
    • Fisch, M.1
  • 3
    • 0000965830 scopus 로고
    • It's all necessarily so: William whewell on scientific truth
    • 2 M. Fisch (1991) William Whewell, Philosopher of Science (Oxford: Oxford University Press); L. Snyder (1994) 'It's All Necessarily So: William Whewell on Scientific Truth', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 25, 785-807; R. E. Butts (1965) 'Necessary Truth in Whewell's Theory of Science', American Philosophical Quarterly 2,161-181; K. Ducasse (1951) 'Whewell's Philosophy of Scientific Discovery, Parts I and II', Philosophical Review 60, 46-59, 213-234.
    • (1994) Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , vol.25 , pp. 785-807
    • Snyder, L.1
  • 4
    • 0010816283 scopus 로고
    • Necessary truth in whewell's theory of science
    • 2 M. Fisch (1991) William Whewell, Philosopher of Science (Oxford: Oxford University Press); L. Snyder (1994) 'It's All Necessarily So: William Whewell on Scientific Truth', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 25, 785-807; R. E. Butts (1965) 'Necessary Truth in Whewell's Theory of Science', American Philosophical Quarterly 2,161-181; K. Ducasse (1951) 'Whewell's Philosophy of Scientific Discovery, Parts I and II', Philosophical Review 60, 46-59, 213-234.
    • (1965) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.2 , pp. 161-181
    • Butts, R.E.1
  • 5
    • 0010819472 scopus 로고
    • Whewell's philosophy of scientific discovery, parts I and II
    • 2 M. Fisch (1991) William Whewell, Philosopher of Science (Oxford: Oxford University Press); L. Snyder (1994) 'It's All Necessarily So: William Whewell on Scientific Truth', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 25, 785-807; R. E. Butts (1965) 'Necessary Truth in Whewell's Theory of Science', American Philosophical Quarterly 2,161-181; K. Ducasse (1951) 'Whewell's Philosophy of Scientific Discovery, Parts I and II', Philosophical Review 60, 46-59, 213-234.
    • (1951) Philosophical Review , vol.60 , pp. 46-59
    • Ducasse, K.1
  • 6
    • 85033072979 scopus 로고
    • A letter to the author of prolegomena logica
    • 20 September. Reprinted as Chap. 28 London; reprint New York (1971)
    • 3 See W. Whewell (1852) 'A Letter to the Author of Prolegomena Logica', 20 September. Reprinted as Chap. 28 in Philosophy of Discovery (PD) (1860) (London; reprint New York) (1971).
    • (1852) Philosophy of Discovery (PD)
    • Whewell, W.1
  • 8
    • 85033091183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 5 In addition to the argument of the fundamental antithesis Whewell states explicitly that ideas as he conceives of them are not innate since they possess none of the attributes usually associated with innate ideas. They are not capable of direct or immediate reference regardless of the historical context and they are not considered to be perfect in their original condition. See PIS, p. 633.
    • PIS , pp. 633
  • 12
    • 0010933251 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge; quote taken from the 5th Edn
    • 9 (1837) The Mechanical Euclid (Cambridge); quote taken from the 5th Edn (1849), p. 32.
    • (1837) The Mechanical Euclid , pp. 32
  • 13
    • 85033074616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fisch, op. cit., note 2
    • 10 Fisch, op. cit., note 2.
  • 14
    • 85033076542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Butts, op. cit., note 2
    • 11 Butts, op. cit., note 2.
  • 15
    • 85033076074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Snyder, op. cit., note 2
    • 12 Snyder, op. cit., note 2.
  • 16
    • 85033085474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 13 See PIS, 1, p. 95.
    • PIS , vol.1 , pp. 95
  • 17
    • 85033098003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 2, p. 158
    • 14 Op. cit., note 2, p. 158.
  • 18
    • 85033088052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ducasse, op. cit., note 2
    • 15 Ducasse, op. cit., note 2.
  • 19
    • 85033075333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fisch, op. cit. note 2, p. 161
    • 16 See Fisch, op. cit. note 2, p. 161.
  • 20
    • 85033091226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., p. 162
    • 17 Op. cit., p. 162.
  • 21
    • 0003434048 scopus 로고
    • New Haven: Yale University Press
    • 18 There is even some question as to whether Kant himself was able to show this using only the deduction. For an excellent account of what the transcendental deduction does and does not establish see H. Allison (1983) Kant's Transcendental Idealism (New Haven: Yale University Press).
    • (1983) Kant's Transcendental Idealism
    • Allison, H.1
  • 22
    • 85033087662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 19 POD, p. 359, also quoted in Snyder, p. 796.
    • POD , pp. 359
  • 23
    • 85033085543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Snyder, op. cit., note 2, p. 798
    • 20 Snyder, op. cit., note 2, p. 798.
  • 24
    • 85033087018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., p. 785
    • 21 Op. cit., p. 785.
  • 25
    • 0010817678 scopus 로고
    • A letter to the author of prolegomena logica
    • H.L. Mansel Cambridge
    • 22 W. Whewell (1852) 'A Letter to the Author of Prolegomena Logica [H.L. Mansel] from the Author of History and Philosophy of Science' (Cambridge), p. 13.
    • (1852) History and Philosophy of Science , pp. 13
    • Whewell, W.1
  • 27
    • 85033072991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 24 Ironically, it was the attribution of psychologism to Kant that resulted in many of the criticisms of his transcendental philosophy. For Kant psychology involved securing the foundation of human knowledge on empirical laws of thought; transcendental philosophy consisted of an investigation of a priori conditions that make knowledge, including empirical psychology itself, possible.
  • 28
    • 85033076370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mansel, op. cit., note 22, pp. 16-17
    • 25 See letter to Mansel, op. cit., note 22, pp. 16-17.
  • 29
    • 0010816894 scopus 로고
    • Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, Reprinted Hackett, Indianapolis
    • 26 Reprinted in R. Butts (ed.) (1968) Whewell's Theory of Scientific Method (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press), pp. 54-75, especially pp. 60-61. Reprinted Hackett, Indianapolis (1991).
    • (1968) Whewell's Theory of Scientific Method , pp. 54-75
    • Butts, R.1
  • 31
    • 85033097030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 28 See PIS, 2.
    • PIS , vol.2
  • 32
    • 85033089970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 4 (Cambridge: Trinity College Library). To give an adequate treatment of this topic would require a separate paper; my intention here is just to stress its relevance to the fundamental antithesis and Whewell's psychologism in general.
  • 33
    • 0015635506 scopus 로고
    • The background of physiological psychology in natural philosophy
    • 30 R. Smith (1973) 'The Background of Physiological Psychology in Natural Philosophy'. History of Science xi, 75-123. Smith also refers to H. H. Price (1944) on this topic, 'Touch and Organic Sensation', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society xliv, i-xxx.
    • (1973) History of Science , vol.11 , pp. 75-123
    • Smith, R.1
  • 34
    • 0010945295 scopus 로고
    • Touch and organic sensation
    • 30 R. Smith (1973) 'The Background of Physiological Psychology in Natural Philosophy'. History of Science xi, 75-123. Smith also refers to H. H. Price (1944) on this topic, 'Touch and Organic Sensation', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society xliv, i-xxx.
    • (1944) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.44
    • Price, H.H.1
  • 35
    • 4243561238 scopus 로고
    • London, reprint Hildesheim (1974)
    • 31 E. Darwin (1794-1796) Zoonomia or the Laws of Organic Life, Vols 1 and 2 (London), reprint Hildesheim (1974); D. Hartley (1749) Various Conjectures on the Perception, Motion and Generation of Ideas, R. E. A. Palmer (trans.) (Los Angeles) London, 2 vols.; B. Rand (1923) 'Early Development of Hartley's Doctrine of Association', Psychological Review xxx, 306-320, reprint Hildesheim (1974).
    • (1794) Zoonomia or the Laws of Organic Life , vol.1-2
    • Darwin, E.1
  • 36
    • 85033076988 scopus 로고
    • R. E. A. Palmer (trans.) (Los Angeles) London, 2 vols
    • 31 E. Darwin (1794-1796) Zoonomia or the Laws of Organic Life, Vols 1 and 2 (London), reprint Hildesheim (1974); D. Hartley (1749) Various Conjectures on the Perception, Motion and Generation of Ideas, R. E. A. Palmer (trans.) (Los Angeles) London, 2 vols.; B. Rand (1923) 'Early Development of Hartley's Doctrine of Association', Psychological Review xxx, 306-320, reprint Hildesheim (1974).
    • (1749) Various Conjectures on the Perception, Motion and Generation of Ideas
    • Hartley, D.1
  • 37
    • 0010945296 scopus 로고
    • Early Development of Hartley's Doctrine of Association
    • reprint Hildesheim
    • 31 E. Darwin (1794-1796) Zoonomia or the Laws of Organic Life, Vols 1 and 2 (London), reprint Hildesheim (1974); D. Hartley (1749) Various Conjectures on the Perception, Motion and Generation of Ideas, R. E. A. Palmer (trans.) (Los Angeles) London, 2 vols.; B. Rand (1923) 'Early Development of Hartley's Doctrine of Association', Psychological Review xxx, 306-320, reprint Hildesheim (1974).
    • (1923) Psychological Review , vol.30 , pp. 306-320
    • Rand, B.1
  • 39
    • 0000355780 scopus 로고
    • On the nervous cycle which connects the voluntary muscles with the brain
    • reprinted in (1830)
    • 33 C. Bell (1830) 'On the Nervous Cycle which Connects the Voluntary Muscles with the Brain', Philosophical Transactions, 163-173, reprinted in (1830) The Nervous System of the Human Body. Embracing the Papers Delivered to the Royal Society on the Subject of Nerves (London), pp. 225-238; C. S. Sherrington (1898-1900) 'The Muscular Sense', in E. A. Schafer (ed.) Text-book of Physiology (Edinburgh), ii, pp. 1002-1025.
    • (1830) Philosophical Transactions , pp. 163-173
    • Bell, C.1
  • 41
    • 0002787463 scopus 로고
    • The muscular sense
    • E. A. Schafer (ed.) Edinburgh
    • 33 C. Bell (1830) 'On the Nervous Cycle which Connects the Voluntary Muscles with the Brain', Philosophical Transactions, 163-173, reprinted in (1830) The Nervous System of the Human Body. Embracing the Papers Delivered to the Royal Society on the Subject of Nerves (London), pp. 225-238; C. S. Sherrington (1898-1900) 'The Muscular Sense', in E. A. Schafer (ed.) Text-book of Physiology (Edinburgh), ii, pp. 1002-1025.
    • (1898) Text-book of Physiology , vol.2 , pp. 1002-1025
    • Sherrington, C.S.1
  • 44
    • 85033081785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 36 This is because there is no way of achieving the kind of independence required for the ideas to have a transcendental status similar to Kant's categories.
  • 45
    • 85033093522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 37 As Whewell remarks in PIS, 1, p. 110, 'Neither axioms not syllogisms are necessary for conviction; but they are necessary to display the conditions under which conviction becomes inevitable.'
    • PIS , vol.1 , pp. 110
    • Whewell1
  • 46
    • 85033086958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and reprinted in PIS
    • 38 In his 'Remarks on Mathematical Reasoning' Whewell claims that although the connections between axioms is the basis of our reasoning, the connection resides in our thoughts and cannot be made to follow as a logical result from any assumed form of words presented as a definition. These remarks were originally published as a supplement to the Fourth Edition of The Mechanical Euclid and reprinted in PIS, 2, pp. 595-623, especially p. 603.
    • Fourth Edition of The Mechanical Euclid , vol.2 , pp. 595-623
  • 47
    • 0026132914 scopus 로고
    • Whewell's developmental psychologism: A victorian account of scientific progress
    • 39 For a good account of Whewell's psychologism see J. Metcalf (1991) 'Whewell's Developmental Psychologism: A Victorian Account of Scientific Progress', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 22, 117-139.
    • (1991) Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , vol.22 , pp. 117-139
    • Metcalf, J.1
  • 48
    • 85033097776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 40 The psychologism differs dramatically from its 17th century counterpart in that its roots are not ultimately traceable to experience. When we look to the history of science it is simply a fact that we find truths that were not derived from experience and cannot be proven by appeal to experience. The conservation of matter and the causal principle are two examples. Experience can only teach by a limited number of examples and hence can never securely establish a universal proposition. Likewise, experience can only inform us that something is the case; it can never prove that it must be the case. What experience shows us is that there are necessary truths different from those that depend on contingent facts about the world, but it does not provide the foundation for their necessity.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.