메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 28, Issue 1, 1997, Pages 1-25

The sociophilosophy of folk psychology

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords

ARTICLE; HISTORY; PSYCHOLOGY; TRADITIONAL MEDICINE;

EID: 0031089256     PISSN: 00393681     EISSN: 18792510     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1016/S0039-3681(96)00012-X     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (29)

References (151)
  • 1
    • 84935940810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pragmatics in Science and Theory in Common Sense
    • Different writers prefer different labels. E.g., K. V. Wilkes opts for 'common-sense psychology', in order to avoid confusion with W. Wundt's Völkerpsychologie; R. Bogdan opts for 'psychofolklore'. I have also seen 'belief-desire psychology'. Nevertheless, 'folk psychology' has become entrenched, and I shall use it throughout this paper. See K. V. Wilkes, 'Pragmatics in Science and Theory in Common Sense', Inquiry 27 (1984), 339-361; R. J. Bogdan, 'The Folklore of the Mind', in R. J. Bogdan (ed.), Mind and Common Sense: Philosophical Essays on Commonsense Psychology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 1-14; K. V. Wilkes, 'The Long Past and the Short History', ibid., pp. 144-160.
    • (1984) Inquiry , vol.27 , pp. 339-361
    • Wilkes, K.V.1
  • 2
    • 84935940810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Folklore of the Mind
    • R. J. Bogdan (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Different writers prefer different labels. E.g., K. V. Wilkes opts for 'common-sense psychology', in order to avoid confusion with W. Wundt's Völkerpsychologie; R. Bogdan opts for 'psychofolklore'. I have also seen 'belief-desire psychology'. Nevertheless, 'folk psychology' has become entrenched, and I shall use it throughout this paper. See K. V. Wilkes, 'Pragmatics in Science and Theory in Common Sense', Inquiry 27 (1984), 339-361; R. J. Bogdan, 'The Folklore of the Mind', in R. J. Bogdan (ed.), Mind and Common Sense: Philosophical Essays on Commonsense Psychology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 1-14; K. V. Wilkes, 'The Long Past and the Short History', ibid., pp. 144-160.
    • (1991) Mind and Common Sense: Philosophical Essays on Commonsense Psychology , pp. 1-14
    • Bogdan, R.J.1
  • 3
    • 84935940810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Long Past and the Short History
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Different writers prefer different labels. E.g., K. V. Wilkes opts for 'common-sense psychology', in order to avoid confusion with W. Wundt's Völkerpsychologie; R. Bogdan opts for 'psychofolklore'. I have also seen 'belief-desire psychology'. Nevertheless, 'folk psychology' has become entrenched, and I shall use it throughout this paper. See K. V. Wilkes, 'Pragmatics in Science and Theory in Common Sense', Inquiry 27 (1984), 339-361; R. J. Bogdan, 'The Folklore of the Mind', in R. J. Bogdan (ed.), Mind and Common Sense: Philosophical Essays on Commonsense Psychology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 1-14; K. V. Wilkes, 'The Long Past and the Short History', ibid., pp. 144-160.
    • Mind and Common Sense: Philosophical Essays on Commonsense Psychology , pp. 144-160
    • Wilkes, K.V.1
  • 4
    • 0003433426 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • Collectivism is central in the sociology of scientific knowledge. See B. Barnes, T. S. Kuhn and Social Science (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982); D. Bloor, Knowledge and Social Imagery (London: Routledge, 1976), 'Durkheim and Mauss Revisited: Classification and the Sociology of Knowledge', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 13 (1982), 267-297, Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge (London: Macmillan, 1983) and Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming); H. M. Collins, Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice (London: Sage, 1985); S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); S. Shapin, A Social History of Truth: Gentility, Credibility, and Scientific Knowledge in Seventeenth-Century England (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994). Foucault's work can be read in the same collectivistic light. For an interpretation along this line, see M. Kusch, Foucault's Strata and Fields: An Investigation into Archaeological and Genealogical Science Studies (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991).
    • (1982) T. S. Kuhn and Social Science
    • Barnes, B.1
  • 5
    • 0003994619 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge
    • Collectivism is central in the sociology of scientific knowledge. See B. Barnes, T. S. Kuhn and Social Science (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982); D. Bloor, Knowledge and Social Imagery (London: Routledge, 1976), 'Durkheim and Mauss Revisited: Classification and the Sociology of Knowledge', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 13 (1982), 267-297, Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge (London: Macmillan, 1983) and Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming); H. M. Collins, Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice (London: Sage, 1985); S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); S. Shapin, A Social History of Truth: Gentility, Credibility, and Scientific Knowledge in Seventeenth-Century England (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994). Foucault's work can be read in the same collectivistic light. For an interpretation along this line, see M. Kusch, Foucault's Strata and Fields: An Investigation into Archaeological and Genealogical Science Studies (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991).
    • (1976) Knowledge and Social Imagery
    • Bloor, D.1
  • 6
    • 84925980121 scopus 로고
    • Durkheim and Mauss Revisited: Classification and the Sociology of Knowledge
    • Collectivism is central in the sociology of scientific knowledge. See B. Barnes, T. S. Kuhn and Social Science (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982); D. Bloor, Knowledge and Social Imagery (London: Routledge, 1976), 'Durkheim and Mauss Revisited: Classification and the Sociology of Knowledge', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 13 (1982), 267-297, Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge (London: Macmillan, 1983) and Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming); H. M. Collins, Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice (London: Sage, 1985); S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); S. Shapin, A Social History of Truth: Gentility, Credibility, and Scientific Knowledge in Seventeenth-Century England (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994). Foucault's work can be read in the same collectivistic light. For an interpretation along this line, see M. Kusch, Foucault's Strata and Fields: An Investigation into Archaeological and Genealogical Science Studies (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991).
    • (1982) Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , vol.13 , pp. 267-297
  • 7
    • 0003831728 scopus 로고
    • London: Macmillan
    • Collectivism is central in the sociology of scientific knowledge. See B. Barnes, T. S. Kuhn and Social Science (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982); D. Bloor, Knowledge and Social Imagery (London: Routledge, 1976), 'Durkheim and Mauss Revisited: Classification and the Sociology of Knowledge', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 13 (1982), 267-297, Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge (London: Macmillan, 1983) and Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming); H. M. Collins, Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice (London: Sage, 1985); S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); S. Shapin, A Social History of Truth: Gentility, Credibility, and Scientific Knowledge in Seventeenth-Century England (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994). Foucault's work can be read in the same collectivistic light. For an interpretation along this line, see M. Kusch, Foucault's Strata and Fields: An Investigation into Archaeological and Genealogical Science Studies (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991).
    • (1983) Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge
  • 8
    • 0003846259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • forthcoming
    • Collectivism is central in the sociology of scientific knowledge. See B. Barnes, T. S. Kuhn and Social Science (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982); D. Bloor, Knowledge and Social Imagery (London: Routledge, 1976), 'Durkheim and Mauss Revisited: Classification and the Sociology of Knowledge', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 13 (1982), 267-297, Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge (London: Macmillan, 1983) and Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming); H. M. Collins, Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice (London: Sage, 1985); S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); S. Shapin, A Social History of Truth: Gentility, Credibility, and Scientific Knowledge in Seventeenth-Century England (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994). Foucault's work can be read in the same collectivistic light. For an interpretation along this line, see M. Kusch, Foucault's Strata and Fields: An Investigation into Archaeological and Genealogical Science Studies (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991).
    • Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions
  • 9
    • 84936824364 scopus 로고
    • London: Sage
    • Collectivism is central in the sociology of scientific knowledge. See B. Barnes, T. S. Kuhn and Social Science (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982); D. Bloor, Knowledge and Social Imagery (London: Routledge, 1976), 'Durkheim and Mauss Revisited: Classification and the Sociology of Knowledge', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 13 (1982), 267-297, Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge (London: Macmillan, 1983) and Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming); H. M. Collins, Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice (London: Sage, 1985); S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); S. Shapin, A Social History of Truth: Gentility, Credibility, and Scientific Knowledge in Seventeenth-Century England (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994). Foucault's work can be read in the same collectivistic light. For an interpretation along this line, see M. Kusch, Foucault's Strata and Fields: An Investigation into Archaeological and Genealogical Science Studies (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991).
    • (1985) Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice
    • Collins, H.M.1
  • 10
    • 0003588221 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Collectivism is central in the sociology of scientific knowledge. See B. Barnes, T. S. Kuhn and Social Science (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982); D. Bloor, Knowledge and Social Imagery (London: Routledge, 1976), 'Durkheim and Mauss Revisited: Classification and the Sociology of Knowledge', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 13 (1982), 267-297, Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge (London: Macmillan, 1983) and Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming); H. M. Collins, Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice (London: Sage, 1985); S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); S. Shapin, A Social History of Truth: Gentility, Credibility, and Scientific Knowledge in Seventeenth-Century England (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994). Foucault's work can be read in the same collectivistic light. For an interpretation along this line, see M. Kusch, Foucault's Strata and Fields: An Investigation into Archaeological and Genealogical Science Studies (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991).
    • (1985) Leviathan and the Air-Pump
    • Shapin, S.1    Schaffer, S.2
  • 11
    • 0003757606 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Collectivism is central in the sociology of scientific knowledge. See B. Barnes, T. S. Kuhn and Social Science (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982); D. Bloor, Knowledge and Social Imagery (London: Routledge, 1976), 'Durkheim and Mauss Revisited: Classification and the Sociology of Knowledge', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 13 (1982), 267-297, Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge (London: Macmillan, 1983) and Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming); H. M. Collins, Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice (London: Sage, 1985); S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); S. Shapin, A Social History of Truth: Gentility, Credibility, and Scientific Knowledge in Seventeenth-Century England (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994). Foucault's work can be read in the same collectivistic light. For an interpretation along this line, see M. Kusch, Foucault's Strata and Fields: An Investigation into Archaeological and Genealogical Science Studies (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991).
    • (1994) A Social History of Truth: Gentility, Credibility, and Scientific Knowledge in Seventeenth-Century England
    • Shapin, S.1
  • 12
    • 0004151997 scopus 로고
    • Dordrecht: Kluwer
    • Collectivism is central in the sociology of scientific knowledge. See B. Barnes, T. S. Kuhn and Social Science (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982); D. Bloor, Knowledge and Social Imagery (London: Routledge, 1976), 'Durkheim and Mauss Revisited: Classification and the Sociology of Knowledge', Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 13 (1982), 267-297, Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge (London: Macmillan, 1983) and Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming); H. M. Collins, Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice (London: Sage, 1985); S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the Air-Pump (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985); S. Shapin, A Social History of Truth: Gentility, Credibility, and Scientific Knowledge in Seventeenth-Century England (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994). Foucault's work can be read in the same collectivistic light. For an interpretation along this line, see M. Kusch, Foucault's Strata and Fields: An Investigation into Archaeological and Genealogical Science Studies (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991).
    • (1991) Foucault's Strata and Fields: An Investigation into Archaeological and Genealogical Science Studies
    • Kusch, M.1
  • 13
    • 0009048989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sociophilosophy and the Sociology of Philosophical Knowledge
    • I. Niiniluoto (ed.), Helsinki: Acta Philosophica Fennica, forthcoming
    • For a more general discussion of sociophilosophy, see M. Kusch, 'Sociophilosophy and the Sociology of Philosophical Knowledge', in I. Niiniluoto (ed.), Methods of Philosophy and the History of Philosophy (Helsinki: Acta Philosophica Fennica, 1996, forthcoming).
    • (1996) Methods of Philosophy and the History of Philosophy
    • Kusch, M.1
  • 14
    • 84959584061 scopus 로고
    • "The Mind Is Its Own Place": Science and Solitude in Seventeenth-Century England
    • take this expression from S. Shapin, ' "The Mind Is Its Own Place": Science and Solitude in Seventeenth-Century England', Science in Context 4 (1990), 191-218. Cf. M. Kusch, 'Recluse, Interlocutor, Interrogator: Natural and Social Order in Turn-of-the-Century Psychological Research Schools', Isis 86 (1995), 419-39.
    • (1990) Science in Context , vol.4 , pp. 191-218
    • Shapin, S.1
  • 15
    • 84959584061 scopus 로고
    • Recluse, Interlocutor, Interrogator: Natural and Social Order in Turn-of-the-Century Psychological Research Schools
    • take this expression from S. Shapin, ' "The Mind Is Its Own Place": Science and Solitude in Seventeenth-Century England', Science in Context 4 (1990), 191-218. Cf. M. Kusch, 'Recluse, Interlocutor, Interrogator: Natural and Social Order in Turn-of-the-Century Psychological Research Schools', Isis 86 (1995), 419-39.
    • (1995) Isis , vol.86 , pp. 419-439
    • Kusch, M.1
  • 16
  • 17
    • 0003771786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • See J. Fodor, Psychosemantics (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987), pp. 132-133.
    • (1987) Psychosemantics , pp. 132-133
    • Fodor, J.1
  • 18
    • 0004283894 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, rev. edn
    • P. Churchland, Matter and Consciousness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, rev. edn, 1988), p. 59. Churchland's version of the theory theory goes back to W. Sellars, 'Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind', Science, Perception and Reality (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963), pp. 127-196. (The paper was first published in 1956.)
    • (1988) Matter and Consciousness , pp. 59
    • Churchland, P.1
  • 19
    • 0003349418 scopus 로고
    • Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind
    • London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, The paper was first published in 1956
    • P. Churchland, Matter and Consciousness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, rev. edn, 1988), p. 59. Churchland's version of the theory theory goes back to W. Sellars, 'Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind', Science, Perception and Reality (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963), pp. 127-196. (The paper was first published in 1956.)
    • (1963) Science, Perception and Reality , pp. 127-196
    • Sellars, W.1
  • 21
    • 0002088374 scopus 로고
    • How We Know Our Minds: The Illusion of First-person Knowledge of Intentionality
    • E.g. A. Gopnik, 'How We Know Our Minds: The Illusion of First-person Knowledge of Intentionality', Behavioural and Brain Sciences 16 (1993), 1-14. Precursors of this view include Dilthey and Skinner. See W. Dilthey, Der Aufbau der geschichtlichen Welt in den Geisteswissenschuften, Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. VII, G. Misch (ed.) (Leipzig and Berlin: Teubner, 1927), p. 87; B. F. Skinner, 'The Operational Analysis of Psychological Terms', in H. Feigl and M. Brodbeck (eds), Readings in the Philosophy of Science (New York, Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1953), pp. 585-595, here p. 593.
    • (1993) Behavioural and Brain Sciences , vol.16 , pp. 1-14
    • Gopnik, A.1
  • 22
    • 12844251192 scopus 로고
    • G. Misch (ed.) Leipzig and Berlin: Teubner
    • E.g. A. Gopnik, 'How We Know Our Minds: The Illusion of First-person Knowledge of Intentionality', Behavioural and Brain Sciences 16 (1993), 1-14. Precursors of this view include Dilthey and Skinner. See W. Dilthey, Der Aufbau der geschichtlichen Welt in den Geisteswissenschuften, Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. VII, G. Misch (ed.) (Leipzig and Berlin: Teubner, 1927), p. 87; B. F. Skinner, 'The Operational Analysis of Psychological Terms', in H. Feigl and M. Brodbeck (eds), Readings in the Philosophy of Science (New York, Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1953), pp. 585-595, here p. 593.
    • (1927) Der Aufbau der Geschichtlichen Welt in Den Geisteswissenschuften, Gesammelte Schriften , vol.7 , pp. 87
    • Dilthey, W.1
  • 23
    • 0345961987 scopus 로고
    • The Operational Analysis of Psychological Terms
    • H. Feigl and M. Brodbeck (eds), New York, Appleton-Century-Crofts, here p. 593
    • E.g. A. Gopnik, 'How We Know Our Minds: The Illusion of First-person Knowledge of Intentionality', Behavioural and Brain Sciences 16 (1993), 1-14. Precursors of this view include Dilthey and Skinner. See W. Dilthey, Der Aufbau der geschichtlichen Welt in den Geisteswissenschuften, Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. VII, G. Misch (ed.) (Leipzig and Berlin: Teubner, 1927), p. 87; B. F. Skinner, 'The Operational Analysis of Psychological Terms', in H. Feigl and M. Brodbeck (eds), Readings in the Philosophy of Science (New York, Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1953), pp. 585-595, here p. 593.
    • (1953) Readings in the Philosophy of Science , pp. 585-595
    • Skinner, B.F.1
  • 24
    • 85050833417 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 1
    • Wilkes, 'Pragmatics' (cf. note 1); A. I. Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology', Behavioural and Brain Sciences 16 (1993), 15-28.
    • Pragmatics
    • Wilkes1
  • 25
    • 0002783621 scopus 로고
    • The Psychology of Folk Psychology
    • Wilkes, 'Pragmatics' (cf. note 1); A. I. Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology', Behavioural and Brain Sciences 16 (1993), 15-28.
    • (1993) Behavioural and Brain Sciences , vol.16 , pp. 15-28
    • Goldman, A.I.1
  • 26
    • 0002517006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid. note 8
    • See Gopnik and Wellman, 'The theory theory' (ibid., note 8); P. L. Harris, 'Thinking by Children and Scientists: False Analogies and Neglected Similarities', Mapping the Mind, Hirschfeld and Gelman (eds) (cf. note 8), pp. 294-315; and S. A. Gelman, J. D. Coley and Gail M. Gottfried, 'Essentialist Beliefs in Children: The Acquisition of Concepts and Theories', ibid., pp. 341-365.
    • The Theory Theory
    • Gopnik1    Wellman2
  • 27
    • 0001615733 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thinking by Children and Scientists: False Analogies and Neglected Similarities
    • Hirschfeld and Gelman (eds) (cf. note 8)
    • See Gopnik and Wellman, 'The theory theory' (ibid., note 8); P. L. Harris, 'Thinking by Children and Scientists: False Analogies and Neglected Similarities', Mapping the Mind, Hirschfeld and Gelman (eds) (cf. note 8), pp. 294-315; and S. A. Gelman, J. D. Coley and Gail M. Gottfried, 'Essentialist Beliefs in Children: The Acquisition of Concepts and Theories', ibid., pp. 341-365.
    • Mapping the Mind , pp. 294-315
    • Harris, P.L.1
  • 28
    • 0001834602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Essentialist Beliefs in Children: The Acquisition of Concepts and Theories
    • See Gopnik and Wellman, 'The theory theory' (ibid., note 8); P. L. Harris, 'Thinking by Children and Scientists: False Analogies and Neglected Similarities', Mapping the Mind, Hirschfeld and Gelman (eds) (cf. note 8), pp. 294-315; and S. A. Gelman, J. D. Coley and Gail M. Gottfried, 'Essentialist Beliefs in Children: The Acquisition of Concepts and Theories', ibid., pp. 341-365.
    • Mapping the Mind , pp. 341-365
    • Gelman, S.A.1    Coley, J.D.2    Gottfried, G.M.3
  • 29
    • 0003626573 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge University Press
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1979) Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind
    • Churchland, P.M.1
  • 30
    • 0003791951 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1989) A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science
  • 31
    • 0347673447 scopus 로고
    • Folk psychology (2)
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1994) A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind , pp. 308-316
    • Guttenplan, S.1
  • 32
    • 0003958336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1995) The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain
  • 33
    • 0003958338 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1985) Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain
  • 34
    • 0003862320 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1983) From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief
    • Stich, S.P.1
  • 35
    • 0010160204 scopus 로고
    • Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology
    • J. D. Greenwood (ed.), Cambridge University Press
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1991) The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science , pp. 93-119
    • Ramsey, W.1    Stich, S.2    Garon, J.3
  • 36
    • 0028415673 scopus 로고
    • What is Folk Psychology?
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1994) Cognition , vol.50 , pp. 447-468
    • Ravenscroft, I.1
  • 37
    • 85030040904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.)
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • The Future of Folk Psychology
  • 38
    • 0542402708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • Reasons to Believe , pp. 70-92
    • Greenwood, J.D.1
  • 39
    • 79954826124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • Being Indiscrete , pp. 120-134
    • Heil, J.1
  • 40
    • 84889987655 scopus 로고
    • first published in
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1985) Folk Psychology Is Here to Stay , pp. 149-175
    • Woodward, J.1
  • 41
    • 0342768842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention , pp. 196-225
    • Backburn, S.1
  • 42
    • 0039514875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • The Autonomy of Folk Psychology , pp. 242-262
    • Margolis, J.1
  • 43
    • 0642287353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology , pp. 263-288
  • 44
    • 0004097907 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1992) The Rediscovery of the Mind , pp. 58-63
    • Searle, J.R.1
  • 45
    • 0342768842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • op. cit.
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288.
    • Losing Your Mind
    • Blackburn, S.1
  • 46
    • 0004052654 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1993) The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science
    • Dupré, J.1
  • 47
    • 0040376593 scopus 로고
    • Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1995) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.92 , pp. 401-429
    • Foss, J.E.1
  • 48
    • 0003065585 scopus 로고
    • Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1963) Review of Metaphysics , vol.17 , pp. 49-66
    • Feyerabend, P.1
  • 49
    • 0010600319 scopus 로고
    • Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories
    • This is of course the position for which the Churchlands and S. Stich are best known. See P. M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1979), A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), 'Folk psychology (2)', in S. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 308-316, The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995), and Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985); S. P. Stich, From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983); W. Ramsey, S. Stich and J. Garon, 'Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology', in J. D. Greenwood (ed.), The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science (Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 93-119. Stich's position has always been more guarded than the Churchland's. See especially his recent paper with I. Ravenscroft, 'What is Folk Psychology?', Cognition 50 (1994), 447-468. Many of the important criticisms of 'eliminativism' are collected in The Future of Folk Psychology, in Greenwood (ed.) (op. cit.): J. D. Greenwood, 'Reasons to Believe', pp. 70-92; J. Heil, 'Being Indiscrete', pp. 120-134; T. Horgan and J. Woodward, 'Folk Psychology is Here to Stay', pp. 149-175 (first published in 1985); S. Backburn, 'Losing Your Mind: Physics, Identify and Folk Burglar Prevention', pp. 196-225; J. Margolis, 'The Autonomy of Folk Psychology', pp. 242-262; R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology', pp. 263-288. See also J. R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 58-63. I am especially impressed by arguments to the effect that eliminativism presupposes an outdated, positivist view of scientific change. See, e.g. S. Blackburn, 'Losing Your Mind' (op. cit.); J. Dupré, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993); and J. E. Foss, 'Materialism, Reduction, Replacement, and the Place of Consciousness in Science', The Journal of Philosophy XCII (1995), 401-429. The eliminativist position was first influentially formulated by P. Feyerabend and R. Rorty. See P. Feyerabend, 'Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem', Review of Metaphysics 17 (1963), 49-66; R. Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics 19 (1965), 24-54.
    • (1965) Review of Metaphysics , vol.19 , pp. 24-54
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 50
    • 84986769223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Folk Psychology as Simulation
    • There are already several versions of this idea in circulation. Key early statements of this view are R. M. Gordon, 'Folk Psychology as Simulation', Mind and Language 1 (1986), 158-171; and A. I. Goldman, 'Interpretation Psychologized', Mind and Language 4 (1989), 161-185. Most of the recent debate over the simulation theory can be found in three anthologies: Mapping the Mind, Hirschfeld and Gelman (eds) (ibid., note 8); M. Davies and T. Stone (eds), Folk Psychology (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995). Mental Simulation (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995).
    • (1986) Mind and Language , vol.1 , pp. 158-171
    • Gordon, R.M.1
  • 51
    • 84986841203 scopus 로고
    • Interpretation Psychologized
    • There are already several versions of this idea in circulation. Key early statements of this view are R. M. Gordon, 'Folk Psychology as Simulation', Mind and Language 1 (1986), 158-171; and A. I. Goldman, 'Interpretation Psychologized', Mind and Language 4 (1989), 161-185. Most of the recent debate over the simulation theory can be found in three anthologies: Mapping the Mind, Hirschfeld and Gelman (eds) (ibid., note 8); M. Davies and T. Stone (eds), Folk Psychology (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995). Mental Simulation (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995).
    • (1989) Mind and Language , vol.4 , pp. 161-185
    • Goldman, A.I.1
  • 52
    • 84986769223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hirschfeld and Gelman (eds) (ibid., note 8)
    • There are already several versions of this idea in circulation. Key early statements of this view are R. M. Gordon, 'Folk Psychology as Simulation', Mind and Language 1 (1986), 158-171; and A. I. Goldman, 'Interpretation Psychologized', Mind and Language 4 (1989), 161-185. Most of the recent debate over the simulation theory can be found in three anthologies: Mapping the Mind, Hirschfeld and Gelman (eds) (ibid., note 8); M. Davies and T. Stone (eds), Folk Psychology (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995). Mental Simulation (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995).
    • Mapping the Mind
  • 53
    • 84986769223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • There are already several versions of this idea in circulation. Key early statements of this view are R. M. Gordon, 'Folk Psychology as Simulation', Mind and Language 1 (1986), 158-171; and A. I. Goldman, 'Interpretation Psychologized', Mind and Language 4 (1989), 161-185. Most of the recent debate over the simulation theory can be found in three anthologies: Mapping the Mind, Hirschfeld and Gelman (eds) (ibid., note 8); M. Davies and T. Stone (eds), Folk Psychology (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995). Mental Simulation (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995).
    • (1995) Folk Psychology
    • Davies, M.1    Stone, T.2
  • 54
    • 84986769223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • There are already several versions of this idea in circulation. Key early statements of this view are R. M. Gordon, 'Folk Psychology as Simulation', Mind and Language 1 (1986), 158-171; and A. I. Goldman, 'Interpretation Psychologized', Mind and Language 4 (1989), 161-185. Most of the recent debate over the simulation theory can be found in three anthologies: Mapping the Mind, Hirschfeld and Gelman (eds) (ibid., note 8); M. Davies and T. Stone (eds), Folk Psychology (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995). Mental Simulation (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995).
    • (1995) Mental Simulation
  • 55
    • 85030048766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unpublished
    • A point forcefully made by P. M. S. Hacker, 'Methodology in Philosophy of Psychology' (unpublished). Other Wittgensteinian criticisms of the theory theory include R. A. Sharpe, Making the Human Mind (London: Routledge, 1990); and R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology' (ibid., note 12). I hasten to acknowledge that there are similarities between my sociophilosophy of folk psychology and some of the Wittgensteinian construals. The main differences are that at least these Wittgensteinians lack a clear notion of social institution, and that they treat current linguistic use as sacrosant. In this sense they deserve the title of 'reactionaries' of contemporary philosophy. See S. Shanker, 'The Enduring Relevance of Wittgenstein's Remarks on Intentions', in J. Hyman (ed.), Investigating Psychology: Sciences of the Mind After Wittgenstein (London: Routledge, 1991), pp. 67-94, here p. 67. Cf. D. Bloor, 'Left and Right Wittgensteinians', in A. Pickering (ed.), Science as Practice and Culture (Chicago University Press, 1992), pp. 266-282.
    • Methodology in Philosophy of Psychology
    • Hacker, P.M.S.1
  • 56
    • 12844267393 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge
    • A point forcefully made by P. M. S. Hacker, 'Methodology in Philosophy of Psychology' (unpublished). Other Wittgensteinian criticisms of the theory theory include R. A. Sharpe, Making the Human Mind (London: Routledge, 1990); and R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology' (ibid., note 12). I hasten to acknowledge that there are similarities between my sociophilosophy of folk psychology and some of the Wittgensteinian construals. The main differences are that at least these Wittgensteinians lack a clear notion of social institution, and that they treat current linguistic use as sacrosant. In this sense they deserve the title of 'reactionaries' of contemporary philosophy. See S. Shanker, 'The Enduring Relevance of Wittgenstein's Remarks on Intentions', in J. Hyman (ed.), Investigating Psychology: Sciences of the Mind After Wittgenstein (London: Routledge, 1991), pp. 67-94, here p. 67. Cf. D. Bloor, 'Left and Right Wittgensteinians', in A. Pickering (ed.), Science as Practice and Culture (Chicago University Press, 1992), pp. 266-282.
    • (1990) Making the Human Mind
    • Sharpe, R.A.1
  • 57
    • 0642287353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid., note 12
    • A point forcefully made by P. M. S. Hacker, 'Methodology in Philosophy of Psychology' (unpublished). Other Wittgensteinian criticisms of the theory theory include R. A. Sharpe, Making the Human Mind (London: Routledge, 1990); and R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology' (ibid., note 12). I hasten to acknowledge that there are similarities between my sociophilosophy of folk psychology and some of the Wittgensteinian construals. The main differences are that at least these Wittgensteinians lack a clear notion of social institution, and that they treat current linguistic use as sacrosant. In this sense they deserve the title of 'reactionaries' of contemporary philosophy. See S. Shanker, 'The Enduring Relevance of Wittgenstein's Remarks on Intentions', in J. Hyman (ed.), Investigating Psychology: Sciences of the Mind After Wittgenstein (London: Routledge, 1991), pp. 67-94, here p. 67. Cf. D. Bloor, 'Left and Right Wittgensteinians', in A. Pickering (ed.), Science as Practice and Culture (Chicago University Press, 1992), pp. 266-282.
    • A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology
    • McDonough, R.1
  • 58
    • 85066258083 scopus 로고
    • The Enduring Relevance of Wittgenstein's Remarks on Intentions
    • J. Hyman (ed.), London: Routledge, here p. 67
    • A point forcefully made by P. M. S. Hacker, 'Methodology in Philosophy of Psychology' (unpublished). Other Wittgensteinian criticisms of the theory theory include R. A. Sharpe, Making the Human Mind (London: Routledge, 1990); and R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology' (ibid., note 12). I hasten to acknowledge that there are similarities between my sociophilosophy of folk psychology and some of the Wittgensteinian construals. The main differences are that at least these Wittgensteinians lack a clear notion of social institution, and that they treat current linguistic use as sacrosant. In this sense they deserve the title of 'reactionaries' of contemporary philosophy. See S. Shanker, 'The Enduring Relevance of Wittgenstein's Remarks on Intentions', in J. Hyman (ed.), Investigating Psychology: Sciences of the Mind After Wittgenstein (London: Routledge, 1991), pp. 67-94, here p. 67. Cf. D. Bloor, 'Left and Right Wittgensteinians', in A. Pickering (ed.), Science as Practice and Culture (Chicago University Press, 1992), pp. 266-282.
    • (1991) Investigating Psychology: Sciences of the Mind after Wittgenstein , pp. 67-94
    • Shanker, S.1
  • 59
    • 0010179807 scopus 로고
    • Left and Right Wittgensteinians
    • A. Pickering (ed.), Chicago University Press
    • A point forcefully made by P. M. S. Hacker, 'Methodology in Philosophy of Psychology' (unpublished). Other Wittgensteinian criticisms of the theory theory include R. A. Sharpe, Making the Human Mind (London: Routledge, 1990); and R. McDonough, 'A Culturalist Account of Folk Psychology' (ibid., note 12). I hasten to acknowledge that there are similarities between my sociophilosophy of folk psychology and some of the Wittgensteinian construals. The main differences are that at least these Wittgensteinians lack a clear notion of social institution, and that they treat current linguistic use as sacrosant. In this sense they deserve the title of 'reactionaries' of contemporary philosophy. See S. Shanker, 'The Enduring Relevance of Wittgenstein's Remarks on Intentions', in J. Hyman (ed.), Investigating Psychology: Sciences of the Mind After Wittgenstein (London: Routledge, 1991), pp. 67-94, here p. 67. Cf. D. Bloor, 'Left and Right Wittgensteinians', in A. Pickering (ed.), Science as Practice and Culture (Chicago University Press, 1992), pp. 266-282.
    • (1992) Science as Practice and Culture , pp. 266-282
    • Bloor, D.1
  • 60
    • 85050833417 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid., note 1
    • Wilkes, 'Pragmatics' (ibid., note 1); D. C. Dennett, 'Two Contrasts: Folk Craft Versus Folk Science, and Belief Versus Opinion', in The Future of Folk Psychology, Greenwood (ed.) (cf. note 12), pp. 135-148.
    • Pragmatics
    • Wilkes1
  • 61
    • 0010108977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two Contrasts: Folk Craft Versus Folk Science, and Belief Versus Opinion
    • Greenwood (ed.) (cf. note 12)
    • Wilkes, 'Pragmatics' (ibid., note 1); D. C. Dennett, 'Two Contrasts: Folk Craft Versus Folk Science, and Belief Versus Opinion', in The Future of Folk Psychology, Greenwood (ed.) (cf. note 12), pp. 135-148.
    • The Future of Folk Psychology , pp. 135-148
    • Dennett, D.C.1
  • 62
    • 0041134770 scopus 로고
    • Folk Psychology and Cognitive Architecture
    • For an exposition and criticism of the 'neo-Rylean' position, see F. Egan, 'Folk Psychology and Cognitive Architecture', Philosophy of Science 62 (1995), 179-196.
    • (1995) Philosophy of Science , vol.62 , pp. 179-196
    • Egan, F.1
  • 65
    • 79954826124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 12
    • This neologism is due to Heil, 'Being Indiscrete' (cf. note 12).
    • Being Indiscrete
    • Heil1
  • 66
    • 85030044283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the studies cited in note 2 above
    • See the studies cited in note 2 above.
  • 67
    • 0004246499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 12
    • A point frequently made by Paul Churchland. See, e.g., A Neurocomputational Perspective (cf. note 12), p. 2.
    • A Neurocomputational Perspective , pp. 2
  • 69
    • 0003771786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 6
    • Fodor, Psychosemantics (cf. note 6), p. 132; Churchland, A Neurocomputational Perspective (cf. note 12), passim.
    • Psychosemantics , pp. 132
    • Fodor1
  • 71
    • 85050833417 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 1
    • Wilkes, 'Pragmatics' (cf. note 1), p. 360.
    • Pragmatics , pp. 360
    • Wilkes1
  • 72
    • 0039580683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Question of Linguistic Idealism
    • In this section, I draw heavily on G. E. M. Anscombe, 'The Question of Linguistic Idealism', Acta Philosophica Fennica 28, 188 215; B. Barnes, 'Social Life as Bootstrapped Induction', Sociology 4 (1982), 524-545, The Nature of Power (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1988), Social Theory (forthcoming); D. Bloor, Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming), 'Idealism and the Social Character of Meaning' (unpublished), 'Idealism and the Sociology of Knowledge' (unpublished); J. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (London: Allen Lane, 1995); E. Lagerspetz, The Opposite Mirrors: An Essay on the Conventionalist Theory of Institutions (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995).
    • Acta Philosophica Fennica , vol.28 , pp. 188-215
    • Anscombe, G.E.M.1
  • 73
    • 84976929459 scopus 로고
    • Social Life as Bootstrapped Induction
    • In this section, I draw heavily on G. E. M. Anscombe, 'The Question of Linguistic Idealism', Acta Philosophica Fennica 28, 188 215; B. Barnes, 'Social Life as Bootstrapped Induction', Sociology 4 (1982), 524-545, The Nature of Power (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1988), Social Theory (forthcoming); D. Bloor, Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming), 'Idealism and the Social Character of Meaning' (unpublished), 'Idealism and the Sociology of Knowledge' (unpublished); J. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (London: Allen Lane, 1995); E. Lagerspetz, The Opposite Mirrors: An Essay on the Conventionalist Theory of Institutions (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995).
    • (1982) Sociology , vol.4 , pp. 524-545
    • Barnes, B.1
  • 74
    • 0003973625 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Polity Press, Social Theory (forthcoming)
    • In this section, I draw heavily on G. E. M. Anscombe, 'The Question of Linguistic Idealism', Acta Philosophica Fennica 28, 188 215; B. Barnes, 'Social Life as Bootstrapped Induction', Sociology 4 (1982), 524-545, The Nature of Power (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1988), Social Theory (forthcoming); D. Bloor, Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming), 'Idealism and the Social Character of Meaning' (unpublished), 'Idealism and the Sociology of Knowledge' (unpublished); J. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (London: Allen Lane, 1995); E. Lagerspetz, The Opposite Mirrors: An Essay on the Conventionalist Theory of Institutions (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995).
    • (1988) The Nature of Power
  • 75
    • 0003846259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • forthcoming
    • In this section, I draw heavily on G. E. M. Anscombe, 'The Question of Linguistic Idealism', Acta Philosophica Fennica 28, 188 215; B. Barnes, 'Social Life as Bootstrapped Induction', Sociology 4 (1982), 524-545, The Nature of Power (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1988), Social Theory (forthcoming); D. Bloor, Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming), 'Idealism and the Social Character of Meaning' (unpublished), 'Idealism and the Sociology of Knowledge' (unpublished); J. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (London: Allen Lane, 1995); E. Lagerspetz, The Opposite Mirrors: An Essay on the Conventionalist Theory of Institutions (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995).
    • Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions
    • Bloor, D.1
  • 76
    • 85030055245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unpublished
    • In this section, I draw heavily on G. E. M. Anscombe, 'The Question of Linguistic Idealism', Acta Philosophica Fennica 28, 188 215; B. Barnes, 'Social Life as Bootstrapped Induction', Sociology 4 (1982), 524-545, The Nature of Power (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1988), Social Theory (forthcoming); D. Bloor, Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming), 'Idealism and the Social Character of Meaning' (unpublished), 'Idealism and the Sociology of Knowledge' (unpublished); J. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (London: Allen Lane, 1995); E. Lagerspetz, The Opposite Mirrors: An Essay on the Conventionalist Theory of Institutions (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995).
    • Idealism and the Social Character of Meaning
  • 77
    • 4244081713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • unpublished
    • In this section, I draw heavily on G. E. M. Anscombe, 'The Question of Linguistic Idealism', Acta Philosophica Fennica 28, 188 215; B. Barnes, 'Social Life as Bootstrapped Induction', Sociology 4 (1982), 524-545, The Nature of Power (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1988), Social Theory (forthcoming); D. Bloor, Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming), 'Idealism and the Social Character of Meaning' (unpublished), 'Idealism and the Sociology of Knowledge' (unpublished); J. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (London: Allen Lane, 1995); E. Lagerspetz, The Opposite Mirrors: An Essay on the Conventionalist Theory of Institutions (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995).
    • Idealism and the Sociology of Knowledge
  • 78
    • 0004289648 scopus 로고
    • London: Allen Lane
    • In this section, I draw heavily on G. E. M. Anscombe, 'The Question of Linguistic Idealism', Acta Philosophica Fennica 28, 188 215; B. Barnes, 'Social Life as Bootstrapped Induction', Sociology 4 (1982), 524-545, The Nature of Power (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1988), Social Theory (forthcoming); D. Bloor, Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming), 'Idealism and the Social Character of Meaning' (unpublished), 'Idealism and the Sociology of Knowledge' (unpublished); J. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (London: Allen Lane, 1995); E. Lagerspetz, The Opposite Mirrors: An Essay on the Conventionalist Theory of Institutions (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995).
    • (1995) The Construction of Social Reality
    • Searle, J.1
  • 79
    • 0005960156 scopus 로고
    • Dordrecht: Kluwer
    • In this section, I draw heavily on G. E. M. Anscombe, 'The Question of Linguistic Idealism', Acta Philosophica Fennica 28, 188 215; B. Barnes, 'Social Life as Bootstrapped Induction', Sociology 4 (1982), 524-545, The Nature of Power (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1988), Social Theory (forthcoming); D. Bloor, Wittgenstein on Rules as Institutions (forthcoming), 'Idealism and the Social Character of Meaning' (unpublished), 'Idealism and the Sociology of Knowledge' (unpublished); J. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (London: Allen Lane, 1995); E. Lagerspetz, The Opposite Mirrors: An Essay on the Conventionalist Theory of Institutions (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1995).
    • (1995) The Opposite Mirrors: An Essay on the Conventionalist Theory of Institutions
    • Lagerspetz, E.1
  • 80
    • 0027640918 scopus 로고
    • Formal Semantics for Mutual Belief
    • The notion of mutual belief can be rendered precisely. See, e.g. M. Colombetti, 'Formal Semantics for Mutual Belief, Artificial Intelligence 62 (1993), 341-353.
    • (1993) Artificial Intelligence , vol.62 , pp. 341-353
    • Colombetti, M.1
  • 82
    • 0004328007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cf. note 25), Chap. 3
    • take this formulation from Barnes, Social Theory (cf. note 25), Chap. 3.
    • Social Theory
    • Barnes1
  • 83
    • 0039414272 scopus 로고
    • Is There an Independent Observation Language?
    • R. G. Colodny (ed.), Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press
    • No-one has emphasised this aspect of languages and theories more forcefully than Mary Hesse. See M. B. Hesse, 'Is There an Independent Observation Language?', in R. G. Colodny (ed.), The Nature and Function of Scientific Theories: Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1970), pp. 35-78, The Structure of Scientific Inference (London: Macmillan, 1974); M. A. Arbib and M. B. Hesse, The Construction of Reality (Cambridge University Press, 1986).
    • (1970) The Nature and Function of Scientific Theories: Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy , pp. 35-78
    • Hesse, M.B.1
  • 84
    • 0004201670 scopus 로고
    • London: Macmillan
    • No-one has emphasised this aspect of languages and theories more forcefully than Mary Hesse. See M. B. Hesse, 'Is There an Independent Observation Language?', in R. G. Colodny (ed.), The Nature and Function of Scientific Theories: Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1970), pp. 35-78, The Structure of Scientific Inference (London: Macmillan, 1974); M. A. Arbib and M. B. Hesse, The Construction of Reality (Cambridge University Press, 1986).
    • (1974) The Structure of Scientific Inference
  • 85
    • 0004112715 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge University Press
    • No-one has emphasised this aspect of languages and theories more forcefully than Mary Hesse. See M. B. Hesse, 'Is There an Independent Observation Language?', in R. G. Colodny (ed.), The Nature and Function of Scientific Theories: Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1970), pp. 35-78, The Structure of Scientific Inference (London: Macmillan, 1974); M. A. Arbib and M. B. Hesse, The Construction of Reality (Cambridge University Press, 1986).
    • (1986) The Construction of Reality
    • Arbib, M.A.1    Hesse, M.B.2
  • 86
    • 0004088235 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • D. Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), pp. 516-525. For a recent restatement in the light of Wittgenstein's work, see Bloor, Wittgenstein on Rules (cf. note 2).
    • (1990) A Treatise of Human Nature , pp. 516-525
    • Hume, D.1
  • 87
    • 85030054700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 2
    • D. Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), pp. 516-525. For a recent restatement in the light of Wittgenstein's work, see Bloor, Wittgenstein on Rules (cf. note 2).
    • Wittgenstein on Rules
    • Bloor1
  • 88
    • 0041111666 scopus 로고
    • How Psychologies 'Secrete' Moralities
    • For a different way of linking morality and psychology, see N. C. Much and R. Harre, 'How Psychologies 'Secrete' Moralities', New Ideas in Psychology 12 (1994), 291-321.
    • (1994) New Ideas in Psychology , vol.12 , pp. 291-321
    • Much, N.C.1    Harre, R.2
  • 89
    • 0343468534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes
    • See R. E. Nisbett and T. D. Wilson, 'Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes', Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231-259. This paper is often cited as if it were the 'ultimate refutation' of introspective psychology. It is worth noting, however, that some of its central contentions are controversial amongst experimentalists. For critical discussions, and further developement, see, e.g. E. R. Smith and F. D. Miller, 'Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson', Psychological Review 85 (1978), 355-362; K. A. Ericsson and H. A. Simon, 'Verbal Reports as Data', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 215-251; P. White, 'Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 105-112, Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); W. Lyons, The Disappearance of Introspection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); C. Færch and G. Kasper (eds), Introspection in Second Language Research (Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters, 1987); P. A. White, 'Knowing More About What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later', British Journal of Psychology 79 (1988), 13-45; R. T. Hurlburt, Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience (New York: Plenum Press, 1990); R. B. K. Howe, 'Introspection: A Reassessment', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 25-44; W. Lyons, 'Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 51-55; Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology' (cf. note 12). Cf. also Chap. 5 of Dennett, Consciousness Explained (cf. note 5).
    • (1977) Psychological Review , vol.84 , pp. 231-259
    • Nisbett, R.E.1    Wilson, T.D.2
  • 90
    • 0000141858 scopus 로고
    • Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson
    • See R. E. Nisbett and T. D. Wilson, 'Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes', Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231-259. This paper is often cited as if it were the 'ultimate refutation' of introspective psychology. It is worth noting, however, that some of its central contentions are controversial amongst experimentalists. For critical discussions, and further developement, see, e.g. E. R. Smith and F. D. Miller, 'Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson', Psychological Review 85 (1978), 355-362; K. A. Ericsson and H. A. Simon, 'Verbal Reports as Data', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 215-251; P. White, 'Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 105-112, Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); W. Lyons, The Disappearance of Introspection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); C. Færch and G. Kasper (eds), Introspection in Second Language Research (Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters, 1987); P. A. White, 'Knowing More About What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later', British Journal of Psychology 79 (1988), 13-45; R. T. Hurlburt, Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience (New York: Plenum Press, 1990); R. B. K. Howe, 'Introspection: A Reassessment', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 25-44; W. Lyons, 'Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 51-55; Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology' (cf. note 12). Cf. also Chap. 5 of Dennett, Consciousness Explained (cf. note 5).
    • (1978) Psychological Review , vol.85 , pp. 355-362
    • Smith, E.R.1    Miller, F.D.2
  • 91
    • 58149405625 scopus 로고
    • Verbal Reports as Data
    • See R. E. Nisbett and T. D. Wilson, 'Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes', Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231-259. This paper is often cited as if it were the 'ultimate refutation' of introspective psychology. It is worth noting, however, that some of its central contentions are controversial amongst experimentalists. For critical discussions, and further developement, see, e.g. E. R. Smith and F. D. Miller, 'Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson', Psychological Review 85 (1978), 355-362; K. A. Ericsson and H. A. Simon, 'Verbal Reports as Data', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 215-251; P. White, 'Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 105-112, Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); W. Lyons, The Disappearance of Introspection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); C. Færch and G. Kasper (eds), Introspection in Second Language Research (Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters, 1987); P. A. White, 'Knowing More About What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later', British Journal of Psychology 79 (1988), 13-45; R. T. Hurlburt, Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience (New York: Plenum Press, 1990); R. B. K. Howe, 'Introspection: A Reassessment', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 25-44; W. Lyons, 'Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 51-55; Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology' (cf. note 12). Cf. also Chap. 5 of Dennett, Consciousness Explained (cf. note 5).
    • (1980) Psychological Review , vol.87 , pp. 215-251
    • Ericsson, K.A.1    Simon, H.A.2
  • 92
    • 0000660401 scopus 로고
    • Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern
    • See R. E. Nisbett and T. D. Wilson, 'Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes', Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231-259. This paper is often cited as if it were the 'ultimate refutation' of introspective psychology. It is worth noting, however, that some of its central contentions are controversial amongst experimentalists. For critical discussions, and further developement, see, e.g. E. R. Smith and F. D. Miller, 'Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson', Psychological Review 85 (1978), 355-362; K. A. Ericsson and H. A. Simon, 'Verbal Reports as Data', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 215-251; P. White, 'Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 105-112, Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); W. Lyons, The Disappearance of Introspection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); C. Færch and G. Kasper (eds), Introspection in Second Language Research (Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters, 1987); P. A. White, 'Knowing More About What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later', British Journal of Psychology 79 (1988), 13-45; R. T. Hurlburt, Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience (New York: Plenum Press, 1990); R. B. K. Howe, 'Introspection: A Reassessment', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 25-44; W. Lyons, 'Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 51-55; Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology' (cf. note 12). Cf. also Chap. 5 of Dennett, Consciousness Explained (cf. note 5).
    • (1980) Psychological Review , vol.87 , pp. 105-112
    • White, P.1
  • 93
    • 0343468534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • See R. E. Nisbett and T. D. Wilson, 'Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes', Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231-259. This paper is often cited as if it were the 'ultimate refutation' of introspective psychology. It is worth noting, however, that some of its central contentions are controversial amongst experimentalists. For critical discussions, and further developement, see, e.g. E. R. Smith and F. D. Miller, 'Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson', Psychological Review 85 (1978), 355-362; K. A. Ericsson and H. A. Simon, 'Verbal Reports as Data', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 215-251; P. White, 'Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 105-112, Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); W. Lyons, The Disappearance of Introspection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); C. Færch and G. Kasper (eds), Introspection in Second Language Research (Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters, 1987); P. A. White, 'Knowing More About What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later', British Journal of Psychology 79 (1988), 13-45; R. T. Hurlburt, Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience (New York: Plenum Press, 1990); R. B. K. Howe, 'Introspection: A Reassessment', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 25-44; W. Lyons, 'Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 51-55; Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology' (cf. note 12). Cf. also Chap. 5 of Dennett, Consciousness Explained (cf. note 5).
    • (1984) Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data
  • 94
    • 0343468534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • See R. E. Nisbett and T. D. Wilson, 'Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes', Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231-259. This paper is often cited as if it were the 'ultimate refutation' of introspective psychology. It is worth noting, however, that some of its central contentions are controversial amongst experimentalists. For critical discussions, and further developement, see, e.g. E. R. Smith and F. D. Miller, 'Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson', Psychological Review 85 (1978), 355-362; K. A. Ericsson and H. A. Simon, 'Verbal Reports as Data', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 215-251; P. White, 'Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 105-112, Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); W. Lyons, The Disappearance of Introspection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); C. Færch and G. Kasper (eds), Introspection in Second Language Research (Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters, 1987); P. A. White, 'Knowing More About What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later', British Journal of Psychology 79 (1988), 13-45; R. T. Hurlburt, Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience (New York: Plenum Press, 1990); R. B. K. Howe, 'Introspection: A Reassessment', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 25-44; W. Lyons, 'Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 51-55; Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology' (cf. note 12). Cf. also Chap. 5 of Dennett, Consciousness Explained (cf. note 5).
    • (1986) The Disappearance of Introspection
    • Lyons, W.1
  • 95
    • 0343468534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters
    • See R. E. Nisbett and T. D. Wilson, 'Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes', Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231-259. This paper is often cited as if it were the 'ultimate refutation' of introspective psychology. It is worth noting, however, that some of its central contentions are controversial amongst experimentalists. For critical discussions, and further developement, see, e.g. E. R. Smith and F. D. Miller, 'Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson', Psychological Review 85 (1978), 355-362; K. A. Ericsson and H. A. Simon, 'Verbal Reports as Data', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 215-251; P. White, 'Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 105-112, Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); W. Lyons, The Disappearance of Introspection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); C. Færch and G. Kasper (eds), Introspection in Second Language Research (Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters, 1987); P. A. White, 'Knowing More About What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later', British Journal of Psychology 79 (1988), 13-45; R. T. Hurlburt, Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience (New York: Plenum Press, 1990); R. B. K. Howe, 'Introspection: A Reassessment', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 25-44; W. Lyons, 'Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 51-55; Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology' (cf. note 12). Cf. also Chap. 5 of Dennett, Consciousness Explained (cf. note 5).
    • (1987) Introspection in Second Language Research
    • Færch, C.1    Kasper, G.2
  • 96
    • 85004861434 scopus 로고
    • Knowing More about What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later
    • See R. E. Nisbett and T. D. Wilson, 'Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes', Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231-259. This paper is often cited as if it were the 'ultimate refutation' of introspective psychology. It is worth noting, however, that some of its central contentions are controversial amongst experimentalists. For critical discussions, and further developement, see, e.g. E. R. Smith and F. D. Miller, 'Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson', Psychological Review 85 (1978), 355-362; K. A. Ericsson and H. A. Simon, 'Verbal Reports as Data', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 215-251; P. White, 'Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 105-112, Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); W. Lyons, The Disappearance of Introspection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); C. Færch and G. Kasper (eds), Introspection in Second Language Research (Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters, 1987); P. A. White, 'Knowing More About What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later', British Journal of Psychology 79 (1988), 13-45; R. T. Hurlburt, Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience (New York: Plenum Press, 1990); R. B. K. Howe, 'Introspection: A Reassessment', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 25-44; W. Lyons, 'Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 51-55; Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology' (cf. note 12). Cf. also Chap. 5 of Dennett, Consciousness Explained (cf. note 5).
    • (1988) British Journal of Psychology , vol.79 , pp. 13-45
    • White, P.A.1
  • 97
    • 0343468534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Plenum Press
    • See R. E. Nisbett and T. D. Wilson, 'Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes', Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231-259. This paper is often cited as if it were the 'ultimate refutation' of introspective psychology. It is worth noting, however, that some of its central contentions are controversial amongst experimentalists. For critical discussions, and further developement, see, e.g. E. R. Smith and F. D. Miller, 'Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson', Psychological Review 85 (1978), 355-362; K. A. Ericsson and H. A. Simon, 'Verbal Reports as Data', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 215-251; P. White, 'Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 105-112, Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); W. Lyons, The Disappearance of Introspection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); C. Færch and G. Kasper (eds), Introspection in Second Language Research (Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters, 1987); P. A. White, 'Knowing More About What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later', British Journal of Psychology 79 (1988), 13-45; R. T. Hurlburt, Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience (New York: Plenum Press, 1990); R. B. K. Howe, 'Introspection: A Reassessment', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 25-44; W. Lyons, 'Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 51-55; Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology' (cf. note 12). Cf. also Chap. 5 of Dennett, Consciousness Explained (cf. note 5).
    • (1990) Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience
    • Hurlburt, R.T.1
  • 98
    • 0010827825 scopus 로고
    • Introspection: A Reassessment
    • See R. E. Nisbett and T. D. Wilson, 'Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes', Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231-259. This paper is often cited as if it were the 'ultimate refutation' of introspective psychology. It is worth noting, however, that some of its central contentions are controversial amongst experimentalists. For critical discussions, and further developement, see, e.g. E. R. Smith and F. D. Miller, 'Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson', Psychological Review 85 (1978), 355-362; K. A. Ericsson and H. A. Simon, 'Verbal Reports as Data', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 215-251; P. White, 'Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 105-112, Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); W. Lyons, The Disappearance of Introspection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); C. Færch and G. Kasper (eds), Introspection in Second Language Research (Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters, 1987); P. A. White, 'Knowing More About What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later', British Journal of Psychology 79 (1988), 13-45; R. T. Hurlburt, Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience (New York: Plenum Press, 1990); R. B. K. Howe, 'Introspection: A Reassessment', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 25-44; W. Lyons, 'Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 51-55; Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology' (cf. note 12). Cf. also Chap. 5 of Dennett, Consciousness Explained (cf. note 5).
    • (1991) New Ideas in Psychology , vol.9 , pp. 25-44
    • Howe, R.B.K.1
  • 99
    • 0039452746 scopus 로고
    • Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe
    • See R. E. Nisbett and T. D. Wilson, 'Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes', Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231-259. This paper is often cited as if it were the 'ultimate refutation' of introspective psychology. It is worth noting, however, that some of its central contentions are controversial amongst experimentalists. For critical discussions, and further developement, see, e.g. E. R. Smith and F. D. Miller, 'Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson', Psychological Review 85 (1978), 355-362; K. A. Ericsson and H. A. Simon, 'Verbal Reports as Data', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 215-251; P. White, 'Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 105-112, Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); W. Lyons, The Disappearance of Introspection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); C. Færch and G. Kasper (eds), Introspection in Second Language Research (Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters, 1987); P. A. White, 'Knowing More About What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later', British Journal of Psychology 79 (1988), 13-45; R. T. Hurlburt, Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience (New York: Plenum Press, 1990); R. B. K. Howe, 'Introspection: A Reassessment', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 25-44; W. Lyons, 'Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 51-55; Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology' (cf. note 12). Cf. also Chap. 5 of Dennett, Consciousness Explained (cf. note 5).
    • (1991) New Ideas in Psychology , vol.9 , pp. 51-55
    • Lyons, W.1
  • 100
    • 0343468534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 12
    • See R. E. Nisbett and T. D. Wilson, 'Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes', Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231-259. This paper is often cited as if it were the 'ultimate refutation' of introspective psychology. It is worth noting, however, that some of its central contentions are controversial amongst experimentalists. For critical discussions, and further developement, see, e.g. E. R. Smith and F. D. Miller, 'Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson', Psychological Review 85 (1978), 355-362; K. A. Ericsson and H. A. Simon, 'Verbal Reports as Data', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 215-251; P. White, 'Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 105-112, Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); W. Lyons, The Disappearance of Introspection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); C. Færch and G. Kasper (eds), Introspection in Second Language Research (Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters, 1987); P. A. White, 'Knowing More About What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later', British Journal of Psychology 79 (1988), 13-45; R. T. Hurlburt, Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience (New York: Plenum Press, 1990); R. B. K. Howe, 'Introspection: A Reassessment', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 25-44; W. Lyons, 'Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 51-55; Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology' (cf. note 12). Cf. also Chap. 5 of Dennett, Consciousness Explained (cf. note 5).
    • The Psychology of Folk Psychology
    • Goldman1
  • 101
    • 0343468534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 5
    • See R. E. Nisbett and T. D. Wilson, 'Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes', Psychological Review 84 (1977), 231-259. This paper is often cited as if it were the 'ultimate refutation' of introspective psychology. It is worth noting, however, that some of its central contentions are controversial amongst experimentalists. For critical discussions, and further developement, see, e.g. E. R. Smith and F. D. Miller, 'Limits on Perception of Cognitive Processes: A Reply to Nisbett and Wilson', Psychological Review 85 (1978), 355-362; K. A. Ericsson and H. A. Simon, 'Verbal Reports as Data', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 215-251; P. White, 'Limitations on Verbal Reports of Internal Events: A Refutation of Nisbett and Wilson and of Bern', Psychological Review 87 (1980), 105-112, Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984); W. Lyons, The Disappearance of Introspection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); C. Færch and G. Kasper (eds), Introspection in Second Language Research (Philadelphia: Multilingual Matters, 1987); P. A. White, 'Knowing More About What We Can Tell: "Introspective Access" and Causal Report Accuracy 10 Years Later', British Journal of Psychology 79 (1988), 13-45; R. T. Hurlburt, Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience (New York: Plenum Press, 1990); R. B. K. Howe, 'Introspection: A Reassessment', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 25-44; W. Lyons, 'Introspection - A Two-level or One-level Account?: A Response to Howe', New Ideas in Psychology 9 (1991), 51-55; Goldman, 'The Psychology of Folk Psychology' (cf. note 12). Cf. also Chap. 5 of Dennett, Consciousness Explained (cf. note 5).
    • Consciousness Explained
    • Dennett1
  • 102
    • 79954826124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 12
    • Some regard this as an insurmountable problem for eliminativism. I do not. For discussion see, e.g. Heil, 'Being indiscrete' (cf. note 12); A. Rosenberg, 'How Is Eliminative Materialism Possible?', Mind and Common Sense, Bogdan (ed.) (cf. note 1), pp. 123-143; J. Bennett, 'Analysis Without Noise', ibid., pp. 15-36.
    • Being Indiscrete
    • Heil1
  • 103
    • 85030048221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How Is Eliminative Materialism Possible?
    • Bogdan (ed.) (cf. note 1)
    • Some regard this as an insurmountable problem for eliminativism. I do not. For discussion see, e.g. Heil, 'Being indiscrete' (cf. note 12); A. Rosenberg, 'How Is Eliminative Materialism Possible?', Mind and Common Sense, Bogdan (ed.) (cf. note 1), pp. 123-143; J. Bennett, 'Analysis Without Noise', ibid., pp. 15-36.
    • Mind and Common Sense , pp. 123-143
    • Rosenberg, A.1
  • 104
    • 12844272721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Analysis Without Noise
    • Some regard this as an insurmountable problem for eliminativism. I do not. For discussion see, e.g. Heil, 'Being indiscrete' (cf. note 12); A. Rosenberg, 'How Is Eliminative Materialism Possible?', Mind and Common Sense, Bogdan (ed.) (cf. note 1), pp. 123-143; J. Bennett, 'Analysis Without Noise', ibid., pp. 15-36.
    • Mind and Common Sense , pp. 15-36
    • Bennett, J.1
  • 106
    • 0001043432 scopus 로고
    • The National System of Scientific Measurement
    • See J. S. Hunter, The National System of Scientific Measurement', Science 210 (1980), 867-875.
    • (1980) Science , vol.210 , pp. 867-875
    • Hunter, J.S.1
  • 110
    • 60949224379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Inner States as Universals: Sceptical Reflections on Human Nature
    • Heelas and Lock (eds) (cf. note 36)
    • R. Needham, 'Inner States as Universals: Sceptical Reflections on Human Nature', Indigenous Psychologies, Heelas and Lock (eds) (cf. note 36), pp. 65-78.
    • Indigenous Psychologies , pp. 65-78
    • Needham, R.1
  • 111
    • 0001367235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rules Not Words
    • Heelas and Lock (eds) (cf. note 36)
    • S. Howell, 'Rules Not Words', Indigenous Psychologies, Heelas and Lock (eds) (cf. note 36), pp. 133-143.
    • Indigenous Psychologies , pp. 133-143
    • Howell, S.1
  • 112
    • 0007038520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Self and Experience in Maori Culture
    • Heelas and Lock (eds) (cf. note 36)
    • J. Smith, 'Self and Experience in Maori Culture', Indigenous Psychologies, Heelas and Lock (eds) (cf. note 36), pp. 145-159.
    • Indigenous Psychologies , pp. 145-159
    • Smith, J.1
  • 113
    • 0026250084 scopus 로고
    • Culture and the Categorisation of Emotions
    • J. A. Russell, 'Culture and the Categorisation of Emotions', Psychological Bulletin 110 (1991), pp. 426-450; R. Harré (ed.), The Social Construction of Emotions (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986).
    • (1991) Psychological Bulletin , vol.110 , pp. 426-450
    • Russell, J.A.1
  • 114
    • 0026250084 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • J. A. Russell, 'Culture and the Categorisation of Emotions', Psychological Bulletin 110 (1991), pp. 426-450; R. Harré (ed.), The Social Construction of Emotions (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986).
    • (1986) The Social Construction of Emotions
    • Harré, R.1
  • 115
    • 0348128387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Psychological Variety
    • Heelas and Lock (eds) (cf. note 36), here p. 85
    • R. Harre, 'Psychological Variety', Indigenous Psychologies, Heelas and Lock (eds) (cf. note 36), pp. 79-103, here p. 85.
    • Indigenous Psychologies , pp. 79-103
    • Harre, R.1
  • 116
    • 85030046945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 33, This section is greatly indebted to comments and suggestions by David Bloor
    • Bennett, 'Analysis Without Noise' (cf. note 33), p. 20. This section is greatly indebted to comments and suggestions by David Bloor.
    • Analysis Without Noise , pp. 20
    • Bennett1
  • 117
    • 0004225610 scopus 로고
    • London: Sheed & Ward, 1975 first published in
    • By German hermeneutic philosophers of the nineteenth century, like Schleiermacher or Dilthey. See e.g. H.-G. Gadamer, Truth and Method (London: Sheed & Ward, 1975 (first published in 1960)). This observation is not new. See, e.g. Goldman, 'Interpretation' (cf. note 13).
    • (1960) Truth and Method
    • Gadamer, H.-G.1
  • 118
    • 21544474178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 13
    • By German hermeneutic philosophers of the nineteenth century, like Schleiermacher or Dilthey. See e.g. H.-G. Gadamer, Truth and Method (London: Sheed & Ward, 1975 (first published in 1960)). This observation is not new. See, e.g. Goldman, 'Interpretation' (cf. note 13).
    • Interpretation
    • Goldman1
  • 119
    • 0004221292 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Polity Press, 1984 first published in
    • These ideas are central in ethnometholodogy. See, e.g. H. Garfinkel, Studies in Ethnomethodology (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1984 (first published in 1967)).
    • (1967) Studies in Ethnomethodology
    • Garfinkel, H.1
  • 120
    • 0000312158 scopus 로고
    • Collective Intentions and Actions
    • P. R. Cohen, J. Morgan and M. Pollock (eds). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • J. R. Searle, 'Collective Intentions and Actions', in P. R. Cohen, J. Morgan and M. Pollock (eds). Intentions in Communication (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990), pp. 401-415.
    • (1990) Intentions in Communication , pp. 401-415
    • Searle, J.R.1
  • 121
    • 0043083835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 25
    • A point much emphasised in Searle, Construction (cf. note 25), p. 24.
    • Construction , pp. 24
    • Searle1
  • 122
    • 0006297337 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • For work on the calibration of instruments, see N. Jardine, The Scenes of Inquiry (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986). For the concept of 'interpretation function', see, e.g. Churchland, Scientific Realism (cf. note 12), p. 108-110. I take the term 'priming' from Barnes, 'Social Life' (cf. note 25).
    • (1986) The Scenes of Inquiry
    • Jardine, N.1
  • 123
    • 85030051499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 12
    • For work on the calibration of instruments, see N. Jardine, The Scenes of Inquiry (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986). For the concept of 'interpretation function', see, e.g. Churchland, Scientific Realism (cf. note 12), p. 108-110. I take the term 'priming' from Barnes, 'Social Life' (cf. note 25).
    • Scientific Realism , pp. 108-110
    • Churchland1
  • 124
    • 84924348082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 25
    • For work on the calibration of instruments, see N. Jardine, The Scenes of Inquiry (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986). For the concept of 'interpretation function', see, e.g. Churchland, Scientific Realism (cf. note 12), p. 108-110. I take the term 'priming' from Barnes, 'Social Life' (cf. note 25).
    • Social Life
  • 125
    • 12844270434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Natural Kind
    • Guttenplan (ed.) (cf. note 12)
    • borrow the concept of artificial kind from S. Guttenplan, 'Natural Kind', A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, Guttenplan (ed.) (cf. note 12), pp. 449-450.
    • A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind , pp. 449-450
    • Guttenplan, S.1
  • 126
    • 0002836922 scopus 로고
    • World-Making by Kind-Making: Child-Abuse for Example
    • M. Douglas and D. Hull (eds), Edinburgh University Press
    • The analysis of social and natural kind terms given here owes almost everything to the writings of Barry Barnes and David Bloor (cf. note 25). The idea that natural kind terms do not change the things that are being classified comes from I. Hacking. His 'human kinds' are similar to my 'folk psychological, artificial kinds'. Hacking's conception is, however, insufficiently 'materialistic' in that he does not study the ways in which shaping the human body shapes the human mind. See I. Hacking, 'World-Making by Kind-Making: Child-Abuse for Example', in M. Douglas and D. Hull (eds), How Classification Works: Nelson Goodman Among the Social Sciences (Edinburgh University Press, 1992), pp. 180-238,
    • (1992) How Classification Works: Nelson Goodman among the Social Sciences , pp. 180-238
    • Hacking, I.1
  • 128
    • 0041036427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. note 16
    • This claim is often made by Wittgensteinians. See e.g. Hacker, 'Methodology' (cf. note 16). See also, e.g. C. Taylor, 'What is Human Agency?', T. Mischel (ed.), The Self: Psychological and Philosophical Issues (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1977), pp. 103-142.
    • Methodology
    • Hacker1
  • 129
    • 0003316839 scopus 로고
    • What is Human Agency?
    • T. Mischel (ed.), Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • This claim is often made by Wittgensteinians. See e.g. Hacker, 'Methodology' (cf. note 16). See also, e.g. C. Taylor, 'What is Human Agency?', T. Mischel (ed.), The Self: Psychological and Philosophical Issues (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1977), pp. 103-142.
    • (1977) The Self: Psychological and Philosophical Issues , pp. 103-142
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 131
    • 1542464299 scopus 로고
    • Five Parables
    • R. Rorty, J. B. Schneewind and Q. Skinner (eds), Cambridge University Press, here p. 124
    • The distinction between 'making' and 'remaking' comes from I. Hacking: 'We remake the world, but we make up people'. I insist on the obvious point that people are part of the world. See I. Hacking, 'Five Parables', in R. Rorty, J. B. Schneewind and Q. Skinner (eds), Philosophy in History (Cambridge University Press, 1984), pp. 103-124, here p. 124.
    • (1984) Philosophy in History , pp. 103-124
    • Hacking, I.1
  • 133
    • 0002914331 scopus 로고
    • Variations in Cutaneous Pain Sensitivity in Normal Subjects
    • W. P. Chapman and C. M. Jones, 'Variations in Cutaneous Pain Sensitivity in Normal Subjects', The Journal of Clinical Investigation 23 (1944), 81-91. Cf. N. Grahek, 'The Sensory Dimension of Pain', Philosophical Studies 79 (1995), 167-184; and N. Nelkin, 'Pains and Pain Sensations', The Journal of Philosophy LXXXIII (1986), 129-148.
    • (1944) The Journal of Clinical Investigation , vol.23 , pp. 81-91
    • Chapman, W.P.1    Jones, C.M.2
  • 134
    • 12844277922 scopus 로고
    • The Sensory Dimension of Pain
    • W. P. Chapman and C. M. Jones, 'Variations in Cutaneous Pain Sensitivity in Normal Subjects', The Journal of Clinical Investigation 23 (1944), 81-91. Cf. N. Grahek, 'The Sensory Dimension of Pain', Philosophical Studies 79 (1995), 167-184; and N. Nelkin, 'Pains and Pain Sensations', The Journal of Philosophy LXXXIII (1986), 129-148.
    • (1995) Philosophical Studies , vol.79 , pp. 167-184
    • Grahek, N.1
  • 135
    • 12844287440 scopus 로고
    • Pains and Pain Sensations
    • W. P. Chapman and C. M. Jones, 'Variations in Cutaneous Pain Sensitivity in Normal Subjects', The Journal of Clinical Investigation 23 (1944), 81-91. Cf. N. Grahek, 'The Sensory Dimension of Pain', Philosophical Studies 79 (1995), 167-184; and N. Nelkin, 'Pains and Pain Sensations', The Journal of Philosophy LXXXIII (1986), 129-148.
    • (1986) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.83 , pp. 129-148
    • Nelkin, N.1
  • 136
    • 2742513410 scopus 로고
    • The Biological Basis of Learning and Individuality
    • New York: Freeman & Co.
    • E. R. Kandel and R. D. Hawkins, 'The Biological Basis of Learning and Individuality', Mind and Brain: Readings From Scientific American Magazine (New York: Freeman & Co., 1993): pp. 40-53. See also R. Harré and G. Gillett, The Discursive Mind (London: Sage, 1994), pp. 80-96.
    • (1993) Mind and Brain: Readings from Scientific American Magazine , pp. 40-53
    • Kandel, E.R.1    Hawkins, R.D.2
  • 137
    • 0004185008 scopus 로고
    • London: Sage
    • E. R. Kandel and R. D. Hawkins, 'The Biological Basis of Learning and Individuality', Mind and Brain: Readings From Scientific American Magazine (New York: Freeman & Co., 1993): pp. 40-53. See also R. Harré and G. Gillett, The Discursive Mind (London: Sage, 1994), pp. 80-96.
    • (1994) The Discursive Mind , pp. 80-96
    • Harré, R.1    Gillett, G.2
  • 138
    • 0007203416 scopus 로고
    • The First Person
    • Q. Cassam (ed.), Oxford University Press, Anscombe's paper was first published in 1975
    • G. E. M. Anscombe, 'The First Person', Q. Cassam (ed.), Self-Knowledge (Oxford University Press, 1994), pp. 140-159.(Anscombe's paper was first published in 1975.)
    • (1994) Self-Knowledge , pp. 140-159
    • Anscombe, G.E.M.1
  • 139
    • 0003904537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford University Press
    • Ibid., p. 154.
    • Self-Knowledge , pp. 154
  • 140
    • 12844268462 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Other critics have argued that Anscombe's list of possible solutions is incomplete in other respects. C. McGinn and J. Glover miss a consideration of the possibility that 'I' is like 'now' or 'here'. See, e.g. C. McGinn, The Subjective View: Secondary Qualities and Indexical Thoughts (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), p. 54; Glover, I (cf. note 34), p. 206. There are some affinities between my account and that of R. Harré in his The Social Construction of Selves', in K. Yardley and T. Honess (eds), Self and Indentity: Psychosocial Perspectives (Chichester, NY: Wiley, 1987), pp. 41-52. Harré gestures a bit vaguely in the direction of self-referentiality.
    • (1983) The Subjective View: Secondary Qualities and Indexical Thoughts , pp. 54
    • McGinn, C.1
  • 141
    • 85030056555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I (cf. note 34), p. 206
    • Other critics have argued that Anscombe's list of possible solutions is incomplete in other respects. C. McGinn and J. Glover miss a consideration of the possibility that 'I' is like 'now' or 'here'. See, e.g. C. McGinn, The Subjective View: Secondary Qualities and Indexical Thoughts (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), p. 54; Glover, I (cf. note 34), p. 206. There are some affinities between my account and that of R. Harré in his The Social Construction of Selves', in K. Yardley and T. Honess (eds), Self and Indentity: Psychosocial Perspectives (Chichester, NY: Wiley, 1987), pp. 41-52. Harré gestures a bit vaguely in the direction of self-referentiality.
    • Glover1
  • 142
    • 0003851962 scopus 로고
    • Chichester, NY: Wiley, Harré gestures a bit vaguely in the direction of self-referentiality
    • Other critics have argued that Anscombe's list of possible solutions is incomplete in other respects. C. McGinn and J. Glover miss a consideration of the possibility that 'I' is like 'now' or 'here'. See, e.g. C. McGinn, The Subjective View: Secondary Qualities and Indexical Thoughts (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), p. 54; Glover, I (cf. note 34), p. 206. There are some affinities between my account and that of R. Harré in his The Social Construction of Selves', in K. Yardley and T. Honess (eds), Self and Indentity: Psychosocial Perspectives (Chichester, NY: Wiley, 1987), pp. 41-52. Harré gestures a bit vaguely in the direction of self-referentiality.
    • (1987) Self and Indentity: Psychosocial Perspectives , pp. 41-52
    • Yardley, K.1    Honess, T.2
  • 143
    • 84857453222 scopus 로고
    • Cogito, Ergo Sum: Inference or Performance?
    • G. J. D. Moyal (ed.), London: Routledge, Hintikka's paper was first published in 1962
    • take the idea of performative contradiction from J. Hintikka, 'Cogito, Ergo Sum: Inference or Performance?', in G. J. D. Moyal (ed.), René Descartes: Critical Assessments, Volume II (London: Routledge, 1991), pp. 162-184.(Hintikka's paper was first published in 1962.)
    • (1991) René Descartes: Critical Assessments , vol.2 , pp. 162-184
    • Hintikka, J.1
  • 144
    • 85030050720 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Did Descartes Misunderstand the Cogito?
    • (ed.) Moyal (cf. note 61)
    • For a discussion of Gassendi's objections, see K. Merrill, 'Did Descartes Misunderstand the Cogito?', in René Descartes (ed.) Moyal (cf. note 61), pp. 261-269.
    • René Descartes , pp. 261-269
    • Merrill, K.1
  • 145
    • 0042312894 scopus 로고
    • The Cartesian Circle: Circulus ex tempore
    • J. Echemendy, 'The Cartesian Circle: Circulus ex tempore', Studio Cartesiana 2 (1981), 5-42.
    • (1981) Studio Cartesiana , vol.2 , pp. 5-42
    • Echemendy, J.1
  • 147
    • 0043083835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cf. note 25), passim
    • This happy phrase is Searle's. See Searle, Construction (cf. note 25), passim.
    • Construction
    • Searle1
  • 148
    • 76549188238 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982 first published in
    • See. for example, L. Febvre, The Problem of Unbelief in the Sixteenth Century: The Religion of Rabelais (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982 (first published in 1942)); and M. Bloch, Feudal Society (London: Routledge & Kegan, 1962 (first published in 1936)). See also M. D. Altschule, 'Acedia: Its Evolution from Deadly Sin to Psychiatric Syndrome', British Journal of Psychiatry 111 (1965), 117-119.
    • (1942) The Problem of Unbelief in the Sixteenth Century: The Religion of Rabelais
    • Febvre, L.1
  • 149
    • 76549188238 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge & Kegan, 1962 first published in
    • See. for example, L. Febvre, The Problem of Unbelief in the Sixteenth Century: The Religion of Rabelais (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982 (first published in 1942)); and M. Bloch, Feudal Society (London: Routledge & Kegan, 1962 (first published in 1936)). See also M. D. Altschule, 'Acedia: Its Evolution from Deadly Sin to Psychiatric Syndrome', British Journal of Psychiatry 111 (1965), 117-119.
    • (1936) Feudal Society
    • Bloch, M.1
  • 150
    • 76549188238 scopus 로고
    • Acedia: Its Evolution from Deadly Sin to Psychiatric Syndrome
    • See. for example, L. Febvre, The Problem of Unbelief in the Sixteenth Century: The Religion of Rabelais (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982 (first published in 1942)); and M. Bloch, Feudal Society (London: Routledge & Kegan, 1962 (first published in 1936)). See also M. D. Altschule, 'Acedia: Its Evolution from Deadly Sin to Psychiatric Syndrome', British Journal of Psychiatry 111 (1965), 117-119.
    • (1965) British Journal of Psychiatry , vol.111 , pp. 117-119
    • Altschule, M.D.1
  • 151
    • 0003958336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (cf. note 12)
    • Paul Churchland invokes the case of psychoanalysis against those who doubt 'that the vocabulary of a sophisticated science could ever gain general use'. See Churchland, The Engine of Reason (cf. note 12), p. 323. 1 am not convinced that the case of psychoanalysis can support Churchland's hopes concerning neuralese. After all, psychoanalysis is still fairly close to our received belief-desire folk psychology.
    • The Engine of Reason , pp. 323
    • Churchland1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.