-
1
-
-
84892029558
-
The darwinian biology of aristotle's political animals
-
May
-
1. Larry Arnhart, "The Darwinian Biology of Aristotle's Political Animals," American Journal of Political Science, 38 (May 1994): 479. See also Roger D. Masters, The Nature of Politics (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), and Beyond Relativism: Science and Human Values (Hanover: University of New England Press, 1993).
-
(1994)
American Journal of Political Science
, vol.38
, pp. 479
-
-
Arnhart, L.1
-
2
-
-
0003953909
-
-
New Haven: Yale University Press
-
1. Larry Arnhart, "The Darwinian Biology of Aristotle's Political Animals," American Journal of Political Science, 38 (May 1994): 479. See also Roger D. Masters, The Nature of Politics (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), and Beyond Relativism: Science and Human Values (Hanover: University of New England Press, 1993).
-
(1989)
The Nature of Politics
-
-
Masters, R.D.1
-
3
-
-
0003693541
-
-
Hanover: University of New England Press
-
1. Larry Arnhart, "The Darwinian Biology of Aristotle's Political Animals," American Journal of Political Science, 38 (May 1994): 479. See also Roger D. Masters, The Nature of Politics (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989), and Beyond Relativism: Science and Human Values (Hanover: University of New England Press, 1993).
-
(1993)
Beyond Relativism: Science and Human Values
-
-
-
4
-
-
85033645497
-
-
note
-
2. Wilson has yet to receive the attention he deserves, especially in light of his numerous and important contributions to the founding of the American republic. He was a revolutionary pamphleteer of some note and served in the Continental Congress for three periods: 1775-1777, 1782-1783, and 1785-1787. He was one of only six men to have signed both the Declaration of Independence and the Constitution of 1787. He was instrumental in securing the ratification of the Constitution in his home state of Pennsylvania, and was appointed by George Washington to the first Supreme Court of the United States.
-
-
-
-
5
-
-
0011668186
-
-
New York: Penguin Books
-
3. There are, of course, important differences between the terms "law of nature" and "natural law." As F. C. Coppleston argues, the "term 'natural law' does not bear the same sense. . . that is borne by the term 'law of nature' when the law of gravitation, for example, is spoken of as a law of nature or as a natural law. Irrational things do indeed reflect the eternal law in their activities and behaviors; but if we talk about them obeying a natural law the word 'law,' insists Aquinas, is used analogically. For law is defined as an ordinance of reason, and irrational creatures, being irrational, cannot recognize and promulgate to themselves any natural law. Human beings, however, can do so. And the term 'natural law' is applicable in the strict sense, not to the natural tendencies and inclinations of man on which his reason reflects, but to the precepts which his reason enunciates as the result of this reflection." See F. C. Coppleston, Aquinas (New York: Penguin Books, 1986), pp. 221-22. Wilson, however, uses the terms interchangeably, for reasons which will become clear as we proceed.
-
(1986)
Aquinas
, pp. 221-222
-
-
Coppleston, F.C.1
-
6
-
-
0011551012
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, cited by volume and page number
-
4. All references to Wilson's writings are taken from Robert G. McClosky, The Works of James Wilson, 2 vols. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1967), cited by volume and page number. Wilson's spelling is not modernized.
-
(1967)
The Works of James Wilson
, vol.2
-
-
McClosky, R.G.1
-
7
-
-
0011610947
-
-
Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press
-
5. The most notable Thomistic interpreters of Wilson thought are: Charles Page Smith, James Wilson: Founding Father, 1742-1798 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1956), p. 319; William F. Obering, The Philosophy of Law of James Wilson: A Study in Comparative Jurisprudence (Washington, DC: Issued by the Office of the Secretary of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, 1936), pp. 6, 49, and 62; Homer T. Rosenberg, "James Wilson's Theories of Punishment," Pennsylvania Magazine of History and Biography, 73 (1949): 47; Randolph G. Adams, Selected Political Essays of James Wilson (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1930), p. 7; and Arnaud B. Leavelle, "James Wilson and the Relation of Scottish Metaphysics to American Political Thought," Political Science Quarterly, 57 (1957): 402.
-
(1956)
James Wilson: Founding Father, 1742-1798
, pp. 319
-
-
Smith, C.P.1
-
8
-
-
0011613164
-
-
Washington, DC: Issued by the Office of the Secretary of the American Catholic Philosophical Association
-
5. The most notable Thomistic interpreters of Wilson thought are: Charles Page Smith, James Wilson: Founding Father, 1742-1798 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1956), p. 319; William F. Obering, The Philosophy of Law of James Wilson: A Study in Comparative Jurisprudence (Washington, DC: Issued by the Office of the Secretary of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, 1936), pp. 6, 49, and 62; Homer T. Rosenberg, "James Wilson's Theories of Punishment," Pennsylvania Magazine of History and Biography, 73 (1949): 47; Randolph G. Adams, Selected Political Essays of James Wilson (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1930), p. 7; and Arnaud B. Leavelle, "James Wilson and the Relation of Scottish Metaphysics to American Political Thought," Political Science Quarterly, 57 (1957): 402.
-
(1936)
The Philosophy of Law of James Wilson: A Study in Comparative Jurisprudence
, pp. 6
-
-
Obering, W.F.1
-
9
-
-
0011552354
-
James Wilson's theories of punishment
-
5. The most notable Thomistic interpreters of Wilson thought are: Charles Page Smith, James Wilson: Founding Father, 1742-1798 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1956), p. 319; William F. Obering, The Philosophy of Law of James Wilson: A Study in Comparative Jurisprudence (Washington, DC: Issued by the Office of the Secretary of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, 1936), pp. 6, 49, and 62; Homer T. Rosenberg, "James Wilson's Theories of Punishment," Pennsylvania Magazine of History and Biography, 73 (1949): 47; Randolph G. Adams, Selected Political Essays of James Wilson (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1930), p. 7; and Arnaud B. Leavelle, "James Wilson and the Relation of Scottish Metaphysics to American Political Thought," Political Science Quarterly, 57 (1957): 402.
-
(1949)
Pennsylvania Magazine of History and Biography
, vol.73
, pp. 47
-
-
Rosenberg, H.T.1
-
10
-
-
0011658271
-
-
New York: Alfred A. Knopf
-
5. The most notable Thomistic interpreters of Wilson thought are: Charles Page Smith, James Wilson: Founding Father, 1742-1798 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1956), p. 319; William F. Obering, The Philosophy of Law of James Wilson: A Study in Comparative Jurisprudence (Washington, DC: Issued by the Office of the Secretary of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, 1936), pp. 6, 49, and 62; Homer T. Rosenberg, "James Wilson's Theories of Punishment," Pennsylvania Magazine of History and Biography, 73 (1949): 47; Randolph G. Adams, Selected Political Essays of James Wilson (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1930), p. 7; and Arnaud B. Leavelle, "James Wilson and the Relation of Scottish Metaphysics to American Political Thought," Political Science Quarterly, 57 (1957): 402.
-
(1930)
Selected Political Essays of James Wilson
, pp. 7
-
-
Adams, R.G.1
-
11
-
-
0011615374
-
James Wilson and the relation of Scottish metaphysics to American political thought
-
5. The most notable Thomistic interpreters of Wilson thought are: Charles Page Smith, James Wilson: Founding Father, 1742-1798 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1956), p. 319; William F. Obering, The Philosophy of Law of James Wilson: A Study in Comparative Jurisprudence (Washington, DC: Issued by the Office of the Secretary of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, 1936), pp. 6, 49, and 62; Homer T. Rosenberg, "James Wilson's Theories of Punishment," Pennsylvania Magazine of History and Biography, 73 (1949): 47; Randolph G. Adams, Selected Political Essays of James Wilson (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1930), p. 7; and Arnaud B. Leavelle, "James Wilson and the Relation of Scottish Metaphysics to American Political Thought," Political Science Quarterly, 57 (1957): 402.
-
(1957)
Political Science Quarterly
, vol.57
, pp. 402
-
-
Leavelle, A.B.1
-
12
-
-
0011548279
-
James Wilson's political thought and the constitutional convention
-
Fall
-
6. George W. Carey argues that "Just as Wilson could see a compatible and mutually supporting relationship between reason, common sense, and conscience, so too he sees a symbiotic relationship between these and revelation" in "James Wilson's Political Thought and the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987): p. 57. This opinion is shared by Jean-Marc Pascal, The Political Ideas of James Wilson: 1742-1798 (New York: Garland Publishing, 1991), p. 54. Thomas L. Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1988), pp. 122-25, was an exception, but in The Ennobling of Democracy: The Challenge of the Postmodern Age (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1992), pp. 115-17, he sides with the Thomists.
-
(1987)
Political Science Reviewer
, vol.17
, pp. 57
-
-
Carey, G.W.1
-
13
-
-
0011668187
-
-
New York: Garland Publishing
-
6. George W. Carey argues that "Just as Wilson could see a compatible and mutually supporting relationship between reason, common sense, and conscience, so too he sees a symbiotic relationship between these and revelation" in "James Wilson's Political Thought and the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987): p. 57. This opinion is shared by Jean-Marc Pascal, The Political Ideas of James Wilson: 1742-1798 (New York: Garland Publishing, 1991), p. 54. Thomas L. Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1988), pp. 122-25, was an exception, but in The Ennobling of Democracy: The Challenge of the Postmodern Age (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1992), pp. 115-17, he sides with the Thomists.
-
(1991)
The Political Ideas of James Wilson: 1742-1798
, pp. 54
-
-
Pascal, J.-M.1
-
14
-
-
0003394981
-
-
Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, was an exception
-
6. George W. Carey argues that "Just as Wilson could see a compatible and mutually supporting relationship between reason, common sense, and conscience, so too he sees a symbiotic relationship between these and revelation" in "James Wilson's Political Thought and the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987): p. 57. This opinion is shared by Jean-Marc Pascal, The Political Ideas of James Wilson: 1742-1798 (New York: Garland Publishing, 1991), p. 54. Thomas L. Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1988), pp. 122-25, was an exception, but in The Ennobling of Democracy: The Challenge of the Postmodern Age (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1992), pp. 115-17, he sides with the Thomists.
-
(1988)
The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke
, pp. 122-125
-
-
Pangle, T.L.1
-
15
-
-
0003942609
-
-
Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, he sides with the Thomists
-
6. George W. Carey argues that "Just as Wilson could see a compatible and mutually supporting relationship between reason, common sense, and conscience, so too he sees a symbiotic relationship between these and revelation" in "James Wilson's Political Thought and the Constitutional Convention," Political Science Reviewer, 17 (Fall 1987): p. 57. This opinion is shared by Jean-Marc Pascal, The Political Ideas of James Wilson: 1742-1798 (New York: Garland Publishing, 1991), p. 54. Thomas L. Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism: The Moral Vision of the American Founders and the Philosophy of Locke (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1988), pp. 122-25, was an exception, but in The Ennobling of Democracy: The Challenge of the Postmodern Age (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1992), pp. 115-17, he sides with the Thomists.
-
(1992)
The Ennobling of Democracy: The Challenge of the Postmodern Age
, pp. 115-117
-
-
-
16
-
-
0002514564
-
-
ed. Richard Tuck New York: Cambridge University Press, chs. 13-14
-
7. Although Hobbes argues that "A LAW OF NATURE, (lex naturalis), is a Precept, or generall Rule, found out by reason," there is no doubt that this reason is founded in the passions. According to Hobbes, "The passions that encline men to Peace, are Feare of Death; Desire of such things as are necessary to commodious living; and a Hope by their Industry to obtain them. And Reason suggesteth convenient Articles of Peace, upon which men may be drawn to agreement. These Articles, are they, which otherwise are called the Lawes of Nature. . . ." See Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. Richard Tuck (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 90-91, chs. 13-14.
-
(1991)
Leviathan
, pp. 90-91
-
-
Hobbes, T.1
-
17
-
-
79957520258
-
Polite foundation: Citizenship and common sense in James Wilson's republican theory
-
8. The most recent attempt to link Wilson to the Scottish Enlightenment is the work of Stephen A. Conrad. See his "Polite Foundation: Citizenship and Common Sense in James Wilson's Republican Theory," Supreme Court Review (1984): 359-88; "Metaphor and Imagination in Wilson's Theory of Federal Union," Law and Social Inquiry, 13 (1988): 1-70; and "James Wilson's 'Assimilation of the Common Law Mind,' " Northwestern University Law Review, 84 (1990): 186-219. His reading of "sociability" as explicitly anti-liberal is shared by Carl J. Richard, The Founders and the Classics: Greece, Rome, and the American Enlightenment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994), pp. 176-77, and Mary T. Delahanty, The Integralist Philosophy of James Wilson (New York: Pageant Press, Inc., 1969), p. 4.
-
(1984)
Supreme Court Review
, pp. 359-388
-
-
Conrad, S.A.1
-
18
-
-
0011550719
-
Metaphor and imagination in Wilson's theory of federal union
-
8. The most recent attempt to link Wilson to the Scottish Enlightenment is the work of Stephen A. Conrad. See his "Polite Foundation: Citizenship and Common Sense in James Wilson's Republican Theory," Supreme Court Review (1984): 359-88; "Metaphor and Imagination in Wilson's Theory of Federal Union," Law and Social Inquiry, 13 (1988): 1-70; and "James Wilson's 'Assimilation of the Common Law Mind,' " Northwestern University Law Review, 84 (1990): 186-219. His reading of "sociability" as explicitly anti-liberal is shared by Carl J. Richard, The Founders and the Classics: Greece, Rome, and the American Enlightenment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994), pp. 176-77, and Mary T. Delahanty, The Integralist Philosophy of James Wilson (New York: Pageant Press, Inc., 1969), p. 4.
-
(1988)
Law and Social Inquiry
, vol.13
, pp. 1-70
-
-
-
19
-
-
84928849347
-
James Wilson's 'assimilation of the common law mind,'
-
8. The most recent attempt to link Wilson to the Scottish Enlightenment is the work of Stephen A. Conrad. See his "Polite Foundation: Citizenship and Common Sense in James Wilson's Republican Theory," Supreme Court Review (1984): 359-88; "Metaphor and Imagination in Wilson's Theory of Federal Union," Law and Social Inquiry, 13 (1988): 1-70; and "James Wilson's 'Assimilation of the Common Law Mind,' " Northwestern University Law Review, 84 (1990): 186-219. His reading of "sociability" as explicitly anti-liberal is shared by Carl J. Richard, The Founders and the Classics: Greece, Rome, and the American Enlightenment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994), pp. 176-77, and Mary T. Delahanty, The Integralist Philosophy of James Wilson (New York: Pageant Press, Inc., 1969), p. 4.
-
(1990)
Northwestern University Law Review
, vol.84
, pp. 186-219
-
-
-
20
-
-
0004175165
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
8. The most recent attempt to link Wilson to the Scottish Enlightenment is the work of Stephen A. Conrad. See his "Polite Foundation: Citizenship and Common Sense in James Wilson's Republican Theory," Supreme Court Review (1984): 359-88; "Metaphor and Imagination in Wilson's Theory of Federal Union," Law and Social Inquiry, 13 (1988): 1-70; and "James Wilson's 'Assimilation of the Common Law Mind,' " Northwestern University Law Review, 84 (1990): 186-219. His reading of "sociability" as explicitly anti-liberal is shared by Carl J. Richard, The Founders and the Classics: Greece, Rome, and the American Enlightenment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994), pp. 176-77, and Mary T. Delahanty, The Integralist Philosophy of James Wilson (New York: Pageant Press, Inc., 1969), p. 4.
-
(1994)
The Founders and the Classics: Greece, Rome, and the American Enlightenment
, pp. 176-177
-
-
Richard, C.J.1
-
21
-
-
85033643543
-
-
New York: Pageant Press, Inc.
-
8. The most recent attempt to link Wilson to the Scottish Enlightenment is the work of Stephen A. Conrad. See his "Polite Foundation: Citizenship and Common Sense in James Wilson's Republican Theory," Supreme Court Review (1984): 359-88; "Metaphor and Imagination in Wilson's Theory of Federal Union," Law and Social Inquiry, 13 (1988): 1-70; and "James Wilson's 'Assimilation of the Common Law Mind,' " Northwestern University Law Review, 84 (1990): 186-219. His reading of "sociability" as explicitly anti-liberal is shared by Carl J. Richard, The Founders and the Classics: Greece, Rome, and the American Enlightenment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994), pp. 176-77, and Mary T. Delahanty, The Integralist Philosophy of James Wilson (New York: Pageant Press, Inc., 1969), p. 4.
-
(1969)
The Integralist Philosophy of James Wilson
, pp. 4
-
-
Delahanty, M.T.1
-
22
-
-
0004031462
-
-
New York: Doubleday and Company
-
9. Most notably Garry Wills, Inventing America: Jefferson's Declaration of Independence (New York: Doubleday and Company, 1978), pp. 168-80. For correctives to Wills's thesis upon which this article builds, see Frank D. Balog, "The Scottish Enlightenment and the Liberal Political Tradition," in Confronting the Constitution: The Challenge to Locke, Montesquieu, Jefferson, and the Federalists from Utilitarianism, Historicism, Marxism, Freudianism, Pragmatism, Existentialism. . . , ed. Allan Bloom (Washington, DC: The American Enterprise Institute, 1990), pp. 191-208; Ronald Hamowy, "Jefferson and the Scottish Enlightenment: A Critique of Garry Wills' Inventing America: Jefferson's Declaration of Independence," William and Mary Quarterly, 3rd ser., 36 (October 1979): 503-23; and Richard C. Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 70-71.
-
(1978)
Inventing America: Jefferson's Declaration of Independence
, pp. 168-180
-
-
Wills, G.1
-
23
-
-
0003241237
-
The Scottish enlightenment and the liberal political tradition
-
ed. Allan Bloom Washington, DC: The American Enterprise Institute
-
9. Most notably Garry Wills, Inventing America: Jefferson's Declaration of Independence (New York: Doubleday and Company, 1978), pp. 168-80. For correctives to Wills's thesis upon which this article builds, see Frank D. Balog, "The Scottish Enlightenment and the Liberal Political Tradition," in Confronting the Constitution: The Challenge to Locke, Montesquieu, Jefferson, and the Federalists from Utilitarianism, Historicism, Marxism, Freudianism, Pragmatism, Existentialism. . . , ed. Allan Bloom (Washington, DC: The American Enterprise Institute, 1990), pp. 191-208; Ronald Hamowy, "Jefferson and the Scottish Enlightenment: A Critique of Garry Wills' Inventing America: Jefferson's Declaration of Independence," William and Mary Quarterly, 3rd ser., 36 (October 1979): 503-23; and Richard C. Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 70-71.
-
(1990)
Confronting the Constitution: The Challenge to Locke, Montesquieu, Jefferson, and the Federalists from Utilitarianism, Historicism, Marxism, Freudianism, Pragmatism, Existentialism
, pp. 191-208
-
-
Balog, F.D.1
-
24
-
-
0011674863
-
Jefferson and the Scottish enlightenment: A critique of Garry Wills' inventing America: Jefferson's declaration of independence
-
October
-
9. Most notably Garry Wills, Inventing America: Jefferson's Declaration of Independence (New York: Doubleday and Company, 1978), pp. 168-80. For correctives to Wills's thesis upon which this article builds, see Frank D. Balog, "The Scottish Enlightenment and the Liberal Political Tradition," in Confronting the Constitution: The Challenge to Locke, Montesquieu, Jefferson, and the Federalists from Utilitarianism, Historicism, Marxism, Freudianism, Pragmatism, Existentialism. . . , ed. Allan Bloom (Washington, DC: The American Enterprise Institute, 1990), pp. 191-208; Ronald Hamowy, "Jefferson and the Scottish Enlightenment: A Critique of Garry Wills' Inventing America: Jefferson's Declaration of Independence," William and Mary Quarterly, 3rd ser., 36 (October 1979): 503-23; and Richard C. Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 70-71.
-
(1979)
William and Mary Quarterly, 3rd Ser.
, vol.36
, pp. 503-523
-
-
Hamowy, R.1
-
25
-
-
0004009097
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press
-
9. Most notably Garry Wills, Inventing America: Jefferson's Declaration of Independence (New York: Doubleday and Company, 1978), pp. 168-80. For correctives to Wills's thesis upon which this article builds, see Frank D. Balog, "The Scottish Enlightenment and the Liberal Political Tradition," in Confronting the Constitution: The Challenge to Locke, Montesquieu, Jefferson, and the Federalists from Utilitarianism, Historicism, Marxism, Freudianism, Pragmatism, Existentialism. . . , ed. Allan Bloom (Washington, DC: The American Enterprise Institute, 1990), pp. 191-208; Ronald Hamowy, "Jefferson and the Scottish Enlightenment: A Critique of Garry Wills' Inventing America: Jefferson's Declaration of Independence," William and Mary Quarterly, 3rd ser., 36 (October 1979): 503-23; and Richard C. Sinopoli, The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 70-71.
-
(1992)
The Foundations of American Citizenship: Liberalism, the Constitution, and Civic Virtue
, pp. 70-71
-
-
Sinopoli, R.C.1
-
26
-
-
0011616805
-
-
Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press
-
10. A useful guide to the various claims made by the philosophers of the Scottish Enlightenment is Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Rationality? Whose Justice? (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988).
-
(1988)
Whose Rationality? Whose Justice?
-
-
Macintyre, A.1
-
27
-
-
0003691257
-
-
ed. and Introduction and Notes by Peter Laslett New York: Cambridge University Press
-
11. John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, ed. and Introduction and Notes by Peter Laslett (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988), Second Treatise, p. 275, Sec. 12.
-
(1988)
Two Treatises of Government
-
-
Locke, J.1
-
28
-
-
84875528188
-
-
Sec. 12
-
11. John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, ed. and Introduction and Notes by Peter Laslett (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988), Second Treatise, p. 275, Sec. 12.
-
Second Treatise
, pp. 275
-
-
-
29
-
-
0004088235
-
-
with text revised and notes by P. H. Nidditch New York: Oxford University Press, Bk. III, Pt. I, Sec. II
-
12. Cf. David Hume, A Treatise on Human Nature, 2nd ed. with text revised and notes by P. H. Nidditch (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), p. 471; Bk. III, Pt. I, Sec. II; and David Hume, Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, 3rd ed., with text revised and notes by P. H. Nidditch (New York: Oxford University Press, 1975), p. 293; "Appendix I," Sec. 244. An often useful guide that highlights Wilson's liberal use of passages from various Scottish Enlightenment texts is Pascal, The Political Ideas of James Wilson, pp. 48-111.
-
(1990)
A Treatise on Human Nature, 2nd Ed.
, pp. 471
-
-
Hume, D.1
-
30
-
-
0003743259
-
-
with text revised and notes by P. H. Nidditch New York: Oxford University Press, "Appendix I," Sec. 244
-
12. Cf. David Hume, A Treatise on Human Nature, 2nd ed. with text revised and notes by P. H. Nidditch (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), p. 471; Bk. III, Pt. I, Sec. II; and David Hume, Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, 3rd ed., with text revised and notes by P. H. Nidditch (New York: Oxford University Press, 1975), p. 293; "Appendix I," Sec. 244. An often useful guide that highlights Wilson's liberal use of passages from various Scottish Enlightenment texts is Pascal, The Political Ideas of James Wilson, pp. 48-111.
-
(1975)
Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, 3rd Ed.
, pp. 293
-
-
Hume, D.1
-
31
-
-
85033650698
-
-
12. Cf. David Hume, A Treatise on Human Nature, 2nd ed. with text revised and notes by P. H. Nidditch (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), p. 471; Bk. III, Pt. I, Sec. II; and David Hume, Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, 3rd ed., with text revised and notes by P. H. Nidditch (New York: Oxford University Press, 1975), p. 293; "Appendix I," Sec. 244. An often useful guide that highlights Wilson's liberal use of passages from various Scottish Enlightenment texts is Pascal, The Political Ideas of James Wilson, pp. 48-111.
-
The Political Ideas of James Wilson
, pp. 48-111
-
-
Pascal1
-
32
-
-
0004297618
-
-
ST I-II, Q. 84, A. 2.
-
13. Aquinas, On Law, Morality, and Politics, p. 48; ST I-II, Q. 84, A. 2. References to Aquinas are taken from a compilation of the Summas found in St. Thomas Aquinas, On Law, Morality, and Politics, ed. and Intro. William P. Baumgrath and Richard J. Regan, S.J. (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, 1988). I cite this anthology by page number first, and then provide the references to the Summa Theologiae (ST).
-
On Law, Morality, and Politics
, pp. 48
-
-
Aquinas1
-
33
-
-
0004297618
-
-
ed. and Intro. William P. Baumgrath and Richard J. Regan, S.J. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company
-
13. Aquinas, On Law, Morality, and Politics, p. 48; ST I-II, Q. 84, A. 2. References to Aquinas are taken from a compilation of the Summas found in St. Thomas Aquinas, On Law, Morality, and Politics, ed. and Intro. William P. Baumgrath and Richard J. Regan, S.J. (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, 1988). I cite this anthology by page number first, and then provide the references to the Summa Theologiae (ST).
-
(1988)
On Law, Morality, and Politics
-
-
Aquinas, S.T.1
-
34
-
-
0004297618
-
-
ST 1-II, Q. 94, A. 2
-
14. Aquinas, On Law, Morality, and Politics, p. 48; ST 1-II, Q. 94, A. 2.
-
On Law, Morality, and Politics
, pp. 48
-
-
Aquinas1
-
35
-
-
0040138757
-
-
Bk. III, Pt. I, Sec. I
-
15. Cf. Hume, Treatise, pp. 455-70; Bk. III, Pt. I, Sec. I; and Reid, Inquiry into the Human Mind and the Principles of Common Sense, pp. 57-58; Ch. V, Sec. VII, in Thomas Reid, Inquiry and Essays, ed. E. Beanblossom and Keith Lehrer (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, 1983). See also Pascal, The Political Ideas of James Wilson, pp. 62-64.
-
Treatise
, pp. 455-470
-
-
Hume1
-
36
-
-
0003553968
-
-
Ch. V, Sec. VII
-
15. Cf. Hume, Treatise, pp. 455-70; Bk. III, Pt. I, Sec. I; and Reid, Inquiry into the Human Mind and the Principles of Common Sense, pp. 57-58; Ch. V, Sec. VII, in Thomas Reid, Inquiry and Essays, ed. E. Beanblossom and Keith Lehrer (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, 1983). See also Pascal, The Political Ideas of James Wilson, pp. 62-64.
-
Inquiry into the Human Mind and the Principles of Common Sense
, pp. 57-58
-
-
Reid1
-
37
-
-
0011611249
-
-
ed. E. Beanblossom and Keith Lehrer Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company
-
15. Cf. Hume, Treatise, pp. 455-70; Bk. III, Pt. I, Sec. I; and Reid, Inquiry into the Human Mind and the Principles of Common Sense, pp. 57-58; Ch. V, Sec. VII, in Thomas Reid, Inquiry and Essays, ed. E. Beanblossom and Keith Lehrer (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, 1983). See also Pascal, The Political Ideas of James Wilson, pp. 62-64.
-
(1983)
Inquiry and Essays
-
-
Reid, T.1
-
38
-
-
85033650698
-
-
15. Cf. Hume, Treatise, pp. 455-70; Bk. III, Pt. I, Sec. I; and Reid, Inquiry into the Human Mind and the Principles of Common Sense, pp. 57-58; Ch. V, Sec. VII, in Thomas Reid, Inquiry and Essays, ed. E. Beanblossom and Keith Lehrer (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, 1983). See also Pascal, The Political Ideas of James Wilson, pp. 62-64.
-
The Political Ideas of James Wilson
, pp. 62-64
-
-
Pascal1
-
39
-
-
0004136793
-
-
New York: Agustus M. Kelly, Publishers, Bk. I, Ch. III, Sec. I
-
16. Cf. Francis Hutcheson, A System of Moral Philosophy (New York: Agustus M. Kelly, Publishers, 1968), p. 38; Bk. I, Ch. III, Sec. I.
-
(1968)
A System of Moral Philosophy
, pp. 38
-
-
Hutcheson, F.1
-
40
-
-
0004297618
-
-
ST I-II, Q. 19, AA. 5-6
-
17. Aquinas, On Law, Morality, and Politics, p. 5; ST I-II, Q. 19, AA. 5-6.
-
On Law, Morality, and Politics
, pp. 5
-
-
Aquinas1
-
41
-
-
84875344568
-
-
"Appendix I," Sec. 244
-
18. Cf. Hume, Enquiries, p. 293; "Appendix I," Sec. 244.
-
Enquiries
, pp. 293
-
-
Hume1
-
42
-
-
85033660142
-
-
Book II, Ch. 17, Sec. 7
-
19. Cf. Hutcheson, System, p. 129; Book II, Ch. 17, Sec. 7. See also Pascal, The Political Ideas of James Wilson, pp. 76-78.
-
System
, pp. 129
-
-
Hutcheson1
-
44
-
-
0011610949
-
-
20. The failure to read the appeal to Cicero in context leads to the mistaken interpretation of Wilson as a classical republican. See Richard, The Founders and the Classics, pp. 176-77.
-
The Founders and the Classics
, pp. 176-177
-
-
Richard1
-
45
-
-
0004291606
-
-
trans. A. C. Campbell, Intro. David J. Hill (Westport, CT: Hyperion Press, n.d.); Bk. 1, Sec. 14
-
21. See Hugo Grotius, The Rights of War and Peace, trans. A. C. Campbell, Intro. David J. Hill (Westport, CT: Hyperion Press, n.d.), p. 25; Bk. 1, Sec. 14.
-
The Rights of War and Peace
, pp. 25
-
-
Grotius, H.1
-
46
-
-
0011666793
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press, provides a useful analysis of the relation between the law of nature and the law of nations, which may be applied to the study of Wilson. Of the Lockean law of nations, Cox writes that "it is a doctrine which necessarily partakes of all the singular characteristics of his general theory of natural law: his law of nature, viewed as a law of nations, is not a body of law strictly speaking, but rather a body of theoretical principles regarding the abstract rights and duties of sovereign bodies, just as the law of nature is such a body of principles with respect to individual men living in a state of nature" (p. 138)
-
22. Richard H. Cox, Locke on War and Peace (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1960), provides a useful analysis of the relation between the law of nature and the law of nations, which may be applied to the study of Wilson. Of the Lockean law of nations, Cox writes that "it is a doctrine which necessarily partakes of all the singular characteristics of his general theory of natural law: his law of nature, viewed as a law of nations, is not a body of law strictly speaking, but rather a body of theoretical principles regarding the abstract rights and duties of sovereign bodies, just as the law of nature is such a body of principles with respect to individual men living in a state of nature" (p. 138).
-
(1960)
Locke on War and Peace
-
-
Cox, R.H.1
-
47
-
-
0004287799
-
-
ch. XIV
-
23. Hobbes, Leviathan, p. 92; ch. XIV.
-
Leviathan
, pp. 92
-
-
Hobbes1
-
48
-
-
0004287799
-
-
ch. XXVI
-
24. Hobbes, Leviathan, p. 92; ch. XXVI.
-
Leviathan
, pp. 92
-
-
Hobbes1
-
50
-
-
0004350167
-
-
Sec. 62E
-
26. Locke, Second Treatise, pp. 270-71; Sec. 62E
-
Second Treatise
, pp. 270-271
-
-
Locke1
-
52
-
-
0004110659
-
-
Pt. I, Ch. V, Sec. 5, emphasis added
-
28. Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, p. 25; Pt. I, Ch. V, Sec. 5, emphasis added.
-
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
, pp. 25
-
-
Smith1
-
54
-
-
0004350167
-
-
Secs. 78-79
-
30. Locke, Second Treatise, pp. 319-20; Secs. 78-79. See also Reid, Essays on the Active Powers of the Human Mind, pp. 145-48; Essay III, Ch. IV.
-
Second Treatise
, pp. 319-320
-
-
Locke1
-
56
-
-
84942523345
-
-
Pt. I, Ch. I, Sec. 5
-
31. Cf. The Theory of Moral Sentiments, p. 10; Pt. I, Ch. I, Sec. 5. Smith writes: "Pity and compassion are words appropriated to signify our fellow - feeling with the sorrow of others. Sympathy, though its meaning was, perhaps, originally the same, may now, without much impropriety, be made use of to denote our fellow-feeling with any passion whatever." Sympathy is not benevolence.
-
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
, pp. 10
-
-
-
57
-
-
0011611496
-
-
ed. from the Manuscripts with an Introduction and a Commentary by Knud Haakonssen Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, Lecture XVI
-
32. Cf. Thomas Reid, Practical Ethics Being Lectures and Papers on Natural Religion, Self-Government, Natural Jurisprudence, and the Law of Nations, ed. from the Manuscripts with an Introduction and a Commentary by Knud Haakonssen (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990), p. 249; Lecture XVI.
-
(1990)
Practical Ethics Being Lectures and Papers on Natural Religion, Self-government, Natural Jurisprudence, and the Law of Nations
, pp. 249
-
-
Reid, T.1
-
58
-
-
0004350167
-
-
Sec. 80
-
33. Cf. Locke, Second Treatise, pp. 320-21; Sec. 80.
-
Second Treatise
, pp. 320-321
-
-
Locke1
-
59
-
-
0004080299
-
-
trans. and with an Introduction, Notes, and Glossary by Carnes Lord Chicago: The University of Chicago Press; 1253a19-29
-
34. Cf. Aristotle, Politics, trans. and with an Introduction, Notes, and Glossary by Carnes Lord (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1984), p. 37; 1253a19-29.
-
(1984)
Politics
, pp. 37
-
-
Aristotle1
-
60
-
-
0004350167
-
-
Sec. 95
-
35. Locke, Second Treatise, pp. 330-31; Sec. 95, and Hobbes, Leviathan, p. 120; ch. XVII.
-
Second Treatise
, pp. 330-331
-
-
Locke1
-
61
-
-
0004287799
-
-
ch. XVII
-
35. Locke, Second Treatise, pp. 330-31; Sec. 95, and Hobbes, Leviathan, p. 120; ch. XVII.
-
Leviathan
, pp. 120
-
-
Hobbes1
-
63
-
-
0040138757
-
-
Bk. III, Pt. II, Sec. I
-
37. Hume, Treatise, pp. 477-84; Bk. III, Pt. II, Sec. I.
-
Treatise
, pp. 477-484
-
-
Hume1
-
64
-
-
0040138757
-
-
Bk. III, Pt. II, Sec. I
-
38. Hume, Treatise, p. 484; Bk. III, Pt. II, Sec. I.
-
Treatise
, pp. 484
-
-
Hume1
-
65
-
-
0040138757
-
-
Bk. III, Pt. I, Sec. II
-
39. Hume, Treatise, pp. 499-500; Bk. III, Pt. I, Sec. II.
-
Treatise
, pp. 499-500
-
-
Hume1
-
66
-
-
0003560904
-
-
Lecture X
-
40. Reid, Practical Ethics, pp. 190-91; Lecture X.
-
Practical Ethics
, pp. 190-191
-
-
Reid1
-
67
-
-
80051523374
-
-
Bk. II, Ch. IV
-
41. Hutcheson, System, pp. 281-99; Bk. II, Ch. IV.
-
System
, pp. 281-299
-
-
Hutcheson1
-
69
-
-
0003560904
-
-
Lecture XVII
-
43. Reid, Practical Ethics, p. 269; Lecture XVII.
-
Practical Ethics
, pp. 269
-
-
Reid1
-
70
-
-
0011614304
-
A short introduction to moral philosophy
-
Facsimile Editions by Bernhard Fabian, Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlagsburchhandlong; Bk. I, Ch. 6
-
44. Francis Hutcheson, A Short Introduction to Moral Philosophy in The Collected Works of Francis Hutcheson, Facsimile Editions by Bernhard Fabian, Vol. 4 (Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlagsburchhandlong, 1969), p. 83; Bk. I, Ch. 6.
-
(1969)
The Collected Works of Francis Hutcheson
, vol.4
, pp. 83
-
-
Hutcheson, F.1
-
73
-
-
85033642392
-
-
Ch. II
-
46. Reid, Essays on the Active Powers of the Human Mind, pp. 132-33; Essay III, Ch. II.
-
Essay
, vol.3
-
-
-
74
-
-
84922590290
-
-
47. Reid, Essays, p. 134.
-
Essays
, pp. 134
-
-
Reid1
-
75
-
-
84922590290
-
-
emphasis added
-
48. Reid, Essays, pp. 134-35, emphasis added.
-
Essays
, pp. 134-135
-
-
Reid1
-
78
-
-
0011665994
-
-
The Federalist, edited, with an Introduction and Notes, by Jacob E. Cooke Wesleyan University Press
-
51. Cf. Hamilton, Federalist, no. 27, in The Federalist, edited, with an Introduction and Notes, by Jacob E. Cooke (Wesleyan University Press, 1961), pp. 173-74.
-
(1961)
Federalist
, vol.27
, pp. 173-174
-
-
Hamilton1
-
80
-
-
0003380623
-
Idea of a perfect commonwealth
-
53. Cf. "Idea of a Perfect Commonwealth," in Hume, Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, pp. 512-29. A useful examination of the relation between the social passions and Wilson's federalism is found in Samuel H. Beer, To Make a Nation: The Rediscovery of American Federalism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), pp. 341-77.
-
Essays Moral, Political, and Literary
, pp. 512-529
-
-
Hume1
-
81
-
-
0004007925
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
53. Cf. "Idea of a Perfect Commonwealth," in Hume, Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, pp. 512-29. A useful examination of the relation between the social passions and Wilson's federalism is found in Samuel H. Beer, To Make a Nation: The Rediscovery of American Federalism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), pp. 341-77.
-
(1993)
To Make A Nation: The Rediscovery of American Federalism
, pp. 341-377
-
-
Beer, S.H.1
|