메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 22, Issue 3, 1996, Pages 275-299

Democracies don't fight: A case of the wrong research agenda?

(1)  Macmillan, John a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0030487309     PISSN: 02602105     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s0260210500118558     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (21)

References (115)
  • 1
    • 0039169797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The literature uses the terms 'liberal state', 'democracy', 'liberal democracy' and 'libertarian' state to signify virtually the same subject. I shall use the term' liberal state', though when discussing particular authors shall use the term they themselves employ.
  • 2
    • 21144465634 scopus 로고
    • Why don't democracies fight each other: An experimental study
    • Sept.
    • A. Mintz and N. Geva, 'Why Don't Democracies Fight Each Other: An Experimental Study', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 37:3 (Sept. 1993), p. 484.
    • (1993) Journal of Conflict Resolution , vol.37 , Issue.3 , pp. 484
    • Mintz, A.1    Geva, N.2
  • 3
    • 84880654215 scopus 로고
    • Back to the future: Instability in europe after the cold war
    • Summer
    • For recent articles critical of the claim see J. J. Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future: Instability in Europe after the Cold War', International Security, 15:1 (Summer 1990), pp. 5-56; K. Waltz, 'The Emerging Structure of International Politics', International Security, 18:2 (Fall 1993), pp. 44-79; R. Cohen, 'Pacific Unions: A Reappraisal of the Theory that "Democracies do not Go to War with Each Other"', Review of International Studies, 20:3 (July 1994); C. Layne, 'Kant or Cant: The Myth of the Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 5-49; D. Spiro, 'The Insignificance of the Liberal Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 50-86. J. M. Owen, 'How Liberalism Produces Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 87-125, is sympathetic to the claim that there is a positive relationship between democracies and peace, accredits this to liberalism, though maintains that the relationship is manifest only in inter-liberal state relations.
    • (1990) International Security , vol.15 , Issue.1 , pp. 5-56
    • Mearsheimer, J.J.1
  • 4
    • 85043437787 scopus 로고
    • The emerging structure of international politics
    • Fall
    • For recent articles critical of the claim see J. J. Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future: Instability in Europe after the Cold War', International Security, 15:1 (Summer 1990), pp. 5-56; K. Waltz, 'The Emerging Structure of International Politics', International Security, 18:2 (Fall 1993), pp. 44-79; R. Cohen, 'Pacific Unions: A Reappraisal of the Theory that "Democracies do not Go to War with Each Other"', Review of International Studies, 20:3 (July 1994); C. Layne, 'Kant or Cant: The Myth of the Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 5-49; D. Spiro, 'The Insignificance of the Liberal Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 50-86. J. M. Owen, 'How Liberalism Produces Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 87-125, is sympathetic to the claim that there is a positive relationship between democracies and peace, accredits this to liberalism, though maintains that the relationship is manifest only in inter-liberal state relations.
    • (1993) International Security , vol.18 , Issue.2 , pp. 44-79
    • Waltz, K.1
  • 5
    • 84974220833 scopus 로고
    • Pacific unions: A reappraisal of the theory that "democracies do not go to war with each other"
    • July
    • For recent articles critical of the claim see J. J. Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future: Instability in Europe after the Cold War', International Security, 15:1 (Summer 1990), pp. 5-56; K. Waltz, 'The Emerging Structure of International Politics', International Security, 18:2 (Fall 1993), pp. 44-79; R. Cohen, 'Pacific Unions: A Reappraisal of the Theory that "Democracies do not Go to War with Each Other"', Review of International Studies, 20:3 (July 1994); C. Layne, 'Kant or Cant: The Myth of the Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 5-49; D. Spiro, 'The Insignificance of the Liberal Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 50-86. J. M. Owen, 'How Liberalism Produces Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 87-125, is sympathetic to the claim that there is a positive relationship between democracies and peace, accredits this to liberalism, though maintains that the relationship is manifest only in inter-liberal state relations.
    • (1994) Review of International Studies , vol.20 , Issue.3
    • Cohen, R.1
  • 6
    • 61449162892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant or cant: The myth of the democratic peace
    • Fall
    • For recent articles critical of the claim see J. J. Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future: Instability in Europe after the Cold War', International Security, 15:1 (Summer 1990), pp. 5-56; K. Waltz, 'The Emerging Structure of International Politics', International Security, 18:2 (Fall 1993), pp. 44-79; R. Cohen, 'Pacific Unions: A Reappraisal of the Theory that "Democracies do not Go to War with Each Other"', Review of International Studies, 20:3 (July 1994); C. Layne, 'Kant or Cant: The Myth of the Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 5-49; D. Spiro, 'The Insignificance of the Liberal Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 50-86. J. M. Owen, 'How Liberalism Produces Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 87-125, is sympathetic to the claim that there is a positive relationship between democracies and peace, accredits this to liberalism, though maintains that the relationship is manifest only in inter-liberal state relations.
    • (1994) International Security , vol.19 , Issue.2 , pp. 5-49
    • Layne, C.1
  • 7
    • 0040408963 scopus 로고
    • The insignificance of the liberal peace
    • Fall
    • For recent articles critical of the claim see J. J. Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future: Instability in Europe after the Cold War', International Security, 15:1 (Summer 1990), pp. 5-56; K. Waltz, 'The Emerging Structure of International Politics', International Security, 18:2 (Fall 1993), pp. 44-79; R. Cohen, 'Pacific Unions: A Reappraisal of the Theory that "Democracies do not Go to War with Each Other"', Review of International Studies, 20:3 (July 1994); C. Layne, 'Kant or Cant: The Myth of the Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 5-49; D. Spiro, 'The Insignificance of the Liberal Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 50-86. J. M. Owen, 'How Liberalism Produces Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 87-125, is sympathetic to the claim that there is a positive relationship between democracies and peace, accredits this to liberalism, though maintains that the relationship is manifest only in inter-liberal state relations.
    • (1994) International Security , vol.19 , Issue.2 , pp. 50-86
    • Spiro, D.1
  • 8
    • 2042420611 scopus 로고
    • How liberalism produces democratic peace
    • Fall is sympathetic to the claim that there is a positive relationship between democracies and peace, accredits this to liberalism, though maintains that the relationship is manifest only in inter-liberal state relations
    • For recent articles critical of the claim see J. J. Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future: Instability in Europe after the Cold War', International Security, 15:1 (Summer 1990), pp. 5-56; K. Waltz, 'The Emerging Structure of International Politics', International Security, 18:2 (Fall 1993), pp. 44-79; R. Cohen, 'Pacific Unions: A Reappraisal of the Theory that "Democracies do not Go to War with Each Other"', Review of International Studies, 20:3 (July 1994); C. Layne, 'Kant or Cant: The Myth of the Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 5-49; D. Spiro, 'The Insignificance of the Liberal Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 50-86. J. M. Owen, 'How Liberalism Produces Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:2 (Fall 1994), pp. 87-125, is sympathetic to the claim that there is a positive relationship between democracies and peace, accredits this to liberalism, though maintains that the relationship is manifest only in inter-liberal state relations.
    • (1994) International Security , vol.19 , Issue.2 , pp. 87-125
    • Owen, J.M.1
  • 9
    • 0038461460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • I borrow the term 'pacificism' from M. Ceadel, Thinking about Peace and War (Oxford, 1987). It refers to the belief that peace is both possible and desirable, and is thus similar to 'eirenicism'.
    • (1987) Thinking about Peace and War
    • Ceadel, M.1
  • 10
    • 0002778779 scopus 로고
    • A force for peace
    • April
    • M. D. Babst, 'A Force for Peace', Industrial Research, April 1972, pp. 55-8; M. Small and J. D. Singer, 'The War-Proneness of Democratic Regimes', Jerusalem Journal of International Relations, 1:1 (1976), R. J. Rummel 'Libertarianism and International Violence', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 27:1 (1983), pp 27-71; M. W. Doyle, 'Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 1', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12:3 (1983), pp. 205-35; M. W. Doyle, 'Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 2', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12:4 (1983), pp. 323-53.
    • (1972) Industrial Research , pp. 55-58
    • Babst, M.D.1
  • 11
    • 0003151693 scopus 로고
    • The war-proneness of democratic regimes
    • M. D. Babst, 'A Force for Peace', Industrial Research, April 1972, pp. 55-8; M. Small and J. D. Singer, 'The War-Proneness of Democratic Regimes', Jerusalem Journal of International Relations, 1:1 (1976), R. J. Rummel 'Libertarianism and International Violence', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 27:1 (1983), pp 27-71; M. W. Doyle, 'Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 1', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12:3 (1983), pp. 205-35; M. W. Doyle, 'Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 2', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12:4 (1983), pp. 323-53.
    • (1976) Jerusalem Journal of International Relations , vol.1 , Issue.1
    • Small, M.1    Singer, J.D.2
  • 12
    • 33846018188 scopus 로고
    • Libertarianism and international violence
    • M. D. Babst, 'A Force for Peace', Industrial Research, April 1972, pp. 55-8; M. Small and J. D. Singer, 'The War-Proneness of Democratic Regimes', Jerusalem Journal of International Relations, 1:1 (1976), R. J. Rummel 'Libertarianism and International Violence', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 27:1 (1983), pp 27-71; M. W. Doyle, 'Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 1', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12:3 (1983), pp. 205-35; M. W. Doyle, 'Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 2', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12:4 (1983), pp. 323-53.
    • (1983) Journal of Conflict Resolution , vol.27 , Issue.1 , pp. 27-71
    • Rummel, R.J.1
  • 13
    • 0000248716 scopus 로고
    • Kant, liberal legacies, and foreign affairs, part 1
    • M. D. Babst, 'A Force for Peace', Industrial Research, April 1972, pp. 55-8; M. Small and J. D. Singer, 'The War-Proneness of Democratic Regimes', Jerusalem Journal of International Relations, 1:1 (1976), R. J. Rummel 'Libertarianism and International Violence', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 27:1 (1983), pp 27-71; M. W. Doyle, 'Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 1', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12:3 (1983), pp. 205-35; M. W. Doyle, 'Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 2', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12:4 (1983), pp. 323-53.
    • (1983) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.12 , Issue.3 , pp. 205-235
    • Doyle, M.W.1
  • 14
    • 0000248716 scopus 로고
    • Kant, liberal legacies, and foreign affairs, part 2
    • M. D. Babst, 'A Force for Peace', Industrial Research, April 1972, pp. 55-8; M. Small and J. D. Singer, 'The War-Proneness of Democratic Regimes', Jerusalem Journal of International Relations, 1:1 (1976), R. J. Rummel 'Libertarianism and International Violence', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 27:1 (1983), pp 27-71; M. W. Doyle, 'Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 1', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12:3 (1983), pp. 205-35; M. W. Doyle, 'Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs, Part 2', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12:4 (1983), pp. 323-53.
    • (1983) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.12 , Issue.4 , pp. 323-353
    • Doyle, M.W.1
  • 17
    • 84920423750 scopus 로고
    • Domestic politics and war
    • has, as will be discussed below, drawn attention to the differences between the way historians and political scientists study the question of war
    • There are a number of scholars besides Rummel who have considered different aspects of the relationship between liberal states and peace. J. S. Levy, 'Domestic Politics and War', Journal of Interdisciplinary History, 18:3 (1988), pp. 653-73, has, as will be discussed below, drawn attention to the differences between the way historians and political scientists study the question of war. R. L. Schweller, 'Domestic Structure and Preventive War: Are Democracies More Pacific?', World Politics, 44:2 (1992), pp. 235-69, has developed the interesting argument that democracies do not wage preventive war as this is inconsistent with liberal principles. A merit of this piece is that Schweller recognizes that liberal democracies recognize norms applicable beyond inter-liberal state relations. D. P. Forsythe, Human Rights and Peace (Lincoln and London, 1993), has developed an approach which synthesizes the variables of rights and power in explaining the breakdown of peace, and supports his case with a number of empirical case-studies. This argument is, however, in the context of the claim that democracies don't fight each other. C. Lynch, 'Kant, the Republican Peace, and Moral Guidance in International Law', Ethics and International Affairs, 8 (1994) directed a discussion of Kantian ethics to the relationship between liberal states and peace.
    • (1988) Journal of Interdisciplinary History , vol.18 , Issue.3 , pp. 653-673
    • Levy, J.S.1
  • 18
    • 84933491913 scopus 로고
    • Domestic structure and preventive war: Are democracies more pacific?
    • has developed the interesting argument that democracies do not wage preventive war as this is inconsistent with liberal principles
    • There are a number of scholars besides Rummel who have considered different aspects of the relationship between liberal states and peace. J. S. Levy, 'Domestic Politics and War', Journal of Interdisciplinary History, 18:3 (1988), pp. 653-73, has, as will be discussed below, drawn attention to the differences between the way historians and political scientists study the question of war. R. L. Schweller, 'Domestic Structure and Preventive War: Are Democracies More Pacific?', World Politics, 44:2 (1992), pp. 235-69, has developed the interesting argument that democracies do not wage preventive war as this is inconsistent with liberal principles. A merit of this piece is that Schweller recognizes that liberal democracies recognize norms applicable beyond inter-liberal state relations. D. P. Forsythe, Human Rights and Peace (Lincoln and London, 1993), has developed an approach which synthesizes the variables of rights and power in explaining the breakdown of peace, and supports his case with a number of empirical case-studies. This argument is, however, in the context of the claim that democracies don't fight each other. C. Lynch, 'Kant, the Republican Peace, and Moral Guidance in International Law', Ethics and International Affairs, 8 (1994) directed a discussion of Kantian ethics to the relationship between liberal states and peace.
    • (1992) World Politics , vol.44 , Issue.2 , pp. 235-269
    • Schweller, R.L.1
  • 19
    • 0004153340 scopus 로고
    • Lincoln and London, has developed an approach which synthesizes the variables of rights and power in explaining the breakdown of peace, and supports his case with a number of empirical case-studies.
    • There are a number of scholars besides Rummel who have considered different aspects of the relationship between liberal states and peace. J. S. Levy, 'Domestic Politics and War', Journal of Interdisciplinary History, 18:3 (1988), pp. 653-73, has, as will be discussed below, drawn attention to the differences between the way historians and political scientists study the question of war. R. L. Schweller, 'Domestic Structure and Preventive War: Are Democracies More Pacific?', World Politics, 44:2 (1992), pp. 235-69, has developed the interesting argument that democracies do not wage preventive war as this is inconsistent with liberal principles. A merit of this piece is that Schweller recognizes that liberal democracies recognize norms applicable beyond inter-liberal state relations. D. P. Forsythe, Human Rights and Peace (Lincoln and London, 1993), has developed an approach which synthesizes the variables of rights and power in explaining the breakdown of peace, and supports his case with a number of empirical case-studies. This argument is, however, in the context of the claim that democracies don't fight each other. C. Lynch, 'Kant, the Republican Peace, and Moral Guidance in International Law', Ethics and International Affairs, 8 (1994) directed a discussion of Kantian ethics to the relationship between liberal states and peace.
    • (1993) Human Rights and Peace
    • Forsythe, D.P.1
  • 20
    • 84974277225 scopus 로고
    • Kant, the republican peace, and moral guidance in international law
    • directed a discussion of Kantian ethics to the relationship between liberal states and peace
    • There are a number of scholars besides Rummel who have considered different aspects of the relationship between liberal states and peace. J. S. Levy, 'Domestic Politics and War', Journal of Interdisciplinary History, 18:3 (1988), pp. 653-73, has, as will be discussed below, drawn attention to the differences between the way historians and political scientists study the question of war. R. L. Schweller, 'Domestic Structure and Preventive War: Are Democracies More Pacific?', World Politics, 44:2 (1992), pp. 235-69, has developed the interesting argument that democracies do not wage preventive war as this is inconsistent with liberal principles. A merit of this piece is that Schweller recognizes that liberal democracies recognize norms applicable beyond inter-liberal state relations. D. P. Forsythe, Human Rights and Peace (Lincoln and London, 1993), has developed an approach which synthesizes the variables of rights and power in explaining the breakdown of peace, and supports his case with a number of empirical case-studies. This argument is, however, in the context of the claim that democracies don't fight each other. C. Lynch, 'Kant, the Republican Peace, and Moral Guidance in International Law', Ethics and International Affairs, 8 (1994) directed a discussion of Kantian ethics to the relationship between liberal states and peace.
    • (1994) Ethics and International Affairs , pp. 8
    • Lynch, C.1
  • 21
    • 84970177345 scopus 로고
    • Domestic structure, decisional constraints, and war: So why kant democracies fight?
    • June
    • Besides the works cited above in notes 2 and 3 see, for instance, C. T. Morgan and S. Howard Campbell, 'Domestic Structure, Decisional Constraints, and War: So Why Kant Democracies Fight?', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 35:2 (June 1991), pp. 187-211; C. T. Morgan and V. Schwebach, 'Take Two Democracies and Call Me in the Morning: A Prescription for Peace?', International Interactions, 17:3 (1992), pp. 305-20; N. Gleditsch, 'Democracy and Peace', Journal of Peace Research, 29:4 (1992), pp. 369-76; H. Starr, 'Why Don't Democracies Fight One Another? Evaluating the Theory-Findings Feedback Loop', Jerusalem Journal of International Relations, 14:4 (1992), pp. 41-59; J. L. Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies: Rare, or Nonexistent?', International Interactions, 18:3 (1993), pp. 251-76; B. Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace (Princeton, 1993).
    • (1991) Journal of Conflict Resolution , vol.35 , Issue.2 , pp. 187-211
    • Morgan, C.T.1    Campbell, S.H.2
  • 22
    • 84948883145 scopus 로고
    • Take two democracies and call me in the morning: A prescription for peace?
    • Besides the works cited above in notes 2 and 3 see, for instance, C. T. Morgan and S. Howard Campbell, 'Domestic Structure, Decisional Constraints, and War: So Why Kant Democracies Fight?', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 35:2 (June 1991), pp. 187-211; C. T. Morgan and V. Schwebach, 'Take Two Democracies and Call Me in the Morning: A Prescription for Peace?', International Interactions, 17:3 (1992), pp. 305-20; N. Gleditsch, 'Democracy and Peace', Journal of Peace Research, 29:4 (1992), pp. 369-76; H. Starr, 'Why Don't Democracies Fight One Another? Evaluating the Theory-Findings Feedback Loop', Jerusalem Journal of International Relations, 14:4 (1992), pp. 41-59; J. L. Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies: Rare, or Nonexistent?', International Interactions, 18:3 (1993), pp. 251-76; B. Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace (Princeton, 1993).
    • (1992) International Interactions , vol.17 , Issue.3 , pp. 305-320
    • Morgan, C.T.1    Schwebach, V.2
  • 23
    • 84970188379 scopus 로고
    • Democracy and peace
    • Besides the works cited above in notes 2 and 3 see, for instance, C. T. Morgan and S. Howard Campbell, 'Domestic Structure, Decisional Constraints, and War: So Why Kant Democracies Fight?', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 35:2 (June 1991), pp. 187-211; C. T. Morgan and V. Schwebach, 'Take Two Democracies and Call Me in the Morning: A Prescription for Peace?', International Interactions, 17:3 (1992), pp. 305-20; N. Gleditsch, 'Democracy and Peace', Journal of Peace Research, 29:4 (1992), pp. 369-76; H. Starr, 'Why Don't Democracies Fight One Another? Evaluating the Theory-Findings Feedback Loop', Jerusalem Journal of International Relations, 14:4 (1992), pp. 41-59; J. L. Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies: Rare, or Nonexistent?', International Interactions, 18:3 (1993), pp. 251-76; B. Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace (Princeton, 1993).
    • (1992) Journal of Peace Research , vol.29 , Issue.4 , pp. 369-376
    • Gleditsch, N.1
  • 24
    • 84970177345 scopus 로고
    • Why don't democracies fight one another? Evaluating the theory-findings feedback loop
    • Besides the works cited above in notes 2 and 3 see, for instance, C. T. Morgan and S. Howard Campbell, 'Domestic Structure, Decisional Constraints, and War: So Why Kant Democracies Fight?', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 35:2 (June 1991), pp. 187-211; C. T. Morgan and V. Schwebach, 'Take Two Democracies and Call Me in the Morning: A Prescription for Peace?', International Interactions, 17:3 (1992), pp. 305-20; N. Gleditsch, 'Democracy and Peace', Journal of Peace Research, 29:4 (1992), pp. 369-76; H. Starr, 'Why Don't Democracies Fight One Another? Evaluating the Theory-Findings Feedback Loop', Jerusalem Journal of International Relations, 14:4 (1992), pp. 41-59; J. L. Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies: Rare, or Nonexistent?', International Interactions, 18:3 (1993), pp. 251-76; B. Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace (Princeton, 1993).
    • (1992) Jerusalem Journal of International Relations , vol.14 , Issue.4 , pp. 41-59
    • Starr, H.1
  • 25
    • 84972901760 scopus 로고
    • Wars between democracies: Rare, or nonexistent?
    • Besides the works cited above in notes 2 and 3 see, for instance, C. T. Morgan and S. Howard Campbell, 'Domestic Structure, Decisional Constraints, and War: So Why Kant Democracies Fight?', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 35:2 (June 1991), pp. 187-211; C. T. Morgan and V. Schwebach, 'Take Two Democracies and Call Me in the Morning: A Prescription for Peace?', International Interactions, 17:3 (1992), pp. 305-20; N. Gleditsch, 'Democracy and Peace', Journal of Peace Research, 29:4 (1992), pp. 369-76; H. Starr, 'Why Don't Democracies Fight One Another? Evaluating the Theory-Findings Feedback Loop', Jerusalem Journal of International Relations, 14:4 (1992), pp. 41-59; J. L. Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies: Rare, or Nonexistent?', International Interactions, 18:3 (1993), pp. 251-76; B. Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace (Princeton, 1993).
    • (1993) International Interactions , vol.18 , Issue.3 , pp. 251-276
    • J L, R.1
  • 26
    • 84970177345 scopus 로고
    • Princeton
    • Besides the works cited above in notes 2 and 3 see, for instance, C. T. Morgan and S. Howard Campbell, 'Domestic Structure, Decisional Constraints, and War: So Why Kant Democracies Fight?', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 35:2 (June 1991), pp. 187-211; C. T. Morgan and V. Schwebach, 'Take Two Democracies and Call Me in the Morning: A Prescription for Peace?', International Interactions, 17:3 (1992), pp. 305-20; N. Gleditsch, 'Democracy and Peace', Journal of Peace Research, 29:4 (1992), pp. 369-76; H. Starr, 'Why Don't Democracies Fight One Another? Evaluating the Theory-Findings Feedback Loop', Jerusalem Journal of International Relations, 14:4 (1992), pp. 41-59; J. L. Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies: Rare, or Nonexistent?', International Interactions, 18:3 (1993), pp. 251-76; B. Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace (Princeton, 1993).
    • (1993) Grasping the Democratic Peace
    • Russett, B.1
  • 30
    • 84937295044 scopus 로고
    • Democratisation as foreign policy: The case of haiti
    • Jan.
    • K. von Hippel, 'Democratisation as Foreign Policy: the Case of Haiti', in The World Today, 51:1 (Jan. 1995), pp. 11-14.
    • (1995) The World Today , vol.51 , Issue.1 , pp. 11-14
    • Von Hippel, K.1
  • 31
    • 0003897575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, [1748]
    • C. L. de Secondat de Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws (Cambridge, 1989 [1748]), pp. 132, 143, 338; I. Kant, Perpetual Peace, in H. Reiss (ed.), Kant's Political Philosophy (Cambridge, 1991 [1795]); J. A. Schumpeter, 'The Sociology of Imperialism', in Imperialism and Social Classes (New York, 1955 [1919]). Doyle discusses Schumpeter at some length in M. V. Doyle, 'Liberalism and World Politics', American Political Science Review, 80:4 (Dec. 1986), pp. 1151-69.
    • (1989) The Spirit of the Laws , pp. 132
    • De Secondat De Montesquieu, C.L.1
  • 32
    • 0003353990 scopus 로고
    • Perpetual peace
    • H. Reiss (ed.), Cambridge, [1795]
    • C. L. de Secondat de Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws (Cambridge, 1989 [1748]), pp. 132, 143, 338; I. Kant, Perpetual Peace, in H. Reiss (ed.), Kant's Political Philosophy (Cambridge, 1991 [1795]); J. A. Schumpeter, 'The Sociology of Imperialism', in Imperialism and Social Classes (New York, 1955 [1919]). Doyle discusses Schumpeter at some length in M. V. Doyle, 'Liberalism and World Politics', American Political Science Review, 80:4 (Dec. 1986), pp. 1151-69.
    • (1991) Kant's Political Philosophy
    • Kant, I.1
  • 33
    • 77956016010 scopus 로고
    • The sociology of imperialism
    • New York, [1919]
    • C. L. de Secondat de Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws (Cambridge, 1989 [1748]), pp. 132, 143, 338; I. Kant, Perpetual Peace, in H. Reiss (ed.), Kant's Political Philosophy (Cambridge, 1991 [1795]); J. A. Schumpeter, 'The Sociology of Imperialism', in Imperialism and Social Classes (New York, 1955 [1919]). Doyle discusses Schumpeter at some length in M. V. Doyle, 'Liberalism and World Politics', American Political Science Review, 80:4 (Dec. 1986), pp. 1151-69.
    • (1955) Imperialism and Social Classes
    • Schumpeter, J.A.1
  • 34
    • 84973962290 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism and world politics
    • Dec.
    • C. L. de Secondat de Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws (Cambridge, 1989 [1748]), pp. 132, 143, 338; I. Kant, Perpetual Peace, in H. Reiss (ed.), Kant's Political Philosophy (Cambridge, 1991 [1795]); J. A. Schumpeter, 'The Sociology of Imperialism', in Imperialism and Social Classes (New York, 1955 [1919]). Doyle discusses Schumpeter at some length in M. V. Doyle, 'Liberalism and World Politics', American Political Science Review, 80:4 (Dec. 1986), pp. 1151-69.
    • (1986) American Political Science Review , vol.80 , Issue.4 , pp. 1151-1169
    • Doyle, M.V.1
  • 35
    • 0003430827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cites ch. 4 of his own book
    • Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 30, cites ch. 4 of his own book; S. A. Bremer, 'Dangerous Dyads: Conditions Affecting the Likelihood of Interstate War, 1816-1965', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 36:2 (1992), pp. 309-41; and Z. Maoz and N. Abdolali, 'Regime Types and International Conflict', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 33:1 (1989), pp. 3-35. One of Maoz and Abdolali's general conclusions, for instance, is that 'there is no relationship between regime type and conflict involvement at the national (or polity) level of analysis. This finding is extremely robust; it holds regardless of the indexes of regime type used, the aggregation of specific indexes to overall regime categories, the indexes of conflict involvement, and the breakdown of the temporal domain into subperiods' (p. 30). Qualitative factors are, however, completely neglected and as such there is no indication of how the incidence of violence by liberal states is related to any normative framework. See also Mintz and Geva, 'Why Don't Democracies . . .?'.
    • Grasping the Democratic Peace , pp. 30
    • Russett1
  • 36
    • 84965400237 scopus 로고
    • Dangerous dyads: Conditions affecting the likelihood of interstate war, 1816-1965
    • Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 30, cites ch. 4 of his own book; S. A. Bremer, 'Dangerous Dyads: Conditions Affecting the Likelihood of Interstate War, 1816-1965', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 36:2 (1992), pp. 309-41; and Z. Maoz and N. Abdolali, 'Regime Types and International Conflict', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 33:1 (1989), pp. 3-35. One of Maoz and Abdolali's general conclusions, for instance, is that 'there is no relationship between regime type and conflict involvement at the national (or polity) level of analysis. This finding is extremely robust; it holds regardless of the indexes of regime type used, the aggregation of specific indexes to overall regime categories, the indexes of conflict involvement, and the breakdown of the temporal domain into subperiods' (p. 30). Qualitative factors are, however, completely neglected and as such there is no indication of how the incidence of violence by liberal states is related to any normative framework. See also Mintz and Geva, 'Why Don't Democracies . . .?'.
    • (1992) Journal of Conflict Resolution , vol.36 , Issue.2 , pp. 309-341
    • Bremer, S.A.1
  • 37
    • 84970255920 scopus 로고
    • Regime types and international conflict
    • Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 30, cites ch. 4 of his own book; S. A. Bremer, 'Dangerous Dyads: Conditions Affecting the Likelihood of Interstate War, 1816-1965', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 36:2 (1992), pp. 309-41; and Z. Maoz and N. Abdolali, 'Regime Types and International Conflict', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 33:1 (1989), pp. 3-35. One of Maoz and Abdolali's general conclusions, for instance, is that 'there is no relationship between regime type and conflict involvement at the national (or polity) level of analysis. This finding is extremely robust; it holds regardless of the indexes of regime type used, the aggregation of specific indexes to overall regime categories, the indexes of conflict involvement, and the breakdown of the temporal domain into subperiods' (p. 30). Qualitative factors are, however, completely neglected and as such there is no indication of how the incidence of violence by liberal states is related to any normative framework. See also Mintz and Geva, 'Why Don't Democracies . . .?'.
    • (1989) Journal of Conflict Resolution , vol.33 , Issue.1 , pp. 3-35
    • Maoz, Z.1    Abdolali, N.2
  • 38
    • 0040948403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 30, cites ch. 4 of his own book; S. A. Bremer, 'Dangerous Dyads: Conditions Affecting the Likelihood of Interstate War, 1816-1965', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 36:2 (1992), pp. 309-41; and Z. Maoz and N. Abdolali, 'Regime Types and International Conflict', Journal of Conflict Resolution, 33:1 (1989), pp. 3-35. One of Maoz and Abdolali's general conclusions, for instance, is that 'there is no relationship between regime type and conflict involvement at the national (or polity) level of analysis. This finding is extremely robust; it holds regardless of the indexes of regime type used, the aggregation of specific indexes to overall regime categories, the indexes of conflict involvement, and the breakdown of the temporal domain into subperiods' (p. 30). Qualitative factors are, however, completely neglected and as such there is no indication of how the incidence of violence by liberal states is related to any normative framework. See also Mintz and Geva, 'Why Don't Democracies . . .?'.
    • Why Don't Democracies . . .?
    • Mintz1    Geva2
  • 41
    • 0040948401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 225; see also Doyle, 'Kant, Part 2'; Doyle, 'Liberalism and World Politics', pp. 1156-7; and M. W. Doyle, 'Liberalism and International Relations', in R. Beiner and W. J. Booth, Kant and Political Philosophy: The Contemporary Legacy (London, 1993), pp. 176-7.
    • Kant, Part 1 , pp. 225
  • 42
    • 0040354342 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 225; see also Doyle, 'Kant, Part 2'; Doyle, 'Liberalism and World Politics', pp. 1156-7; and M. W. Doyle, 'Liberalism and International Relations', in R. Beiner and W. J. Booth, Kant and Political Philosophy: The Contemporary Legacy (London, 1993), pp. 176-7.
    • Kant, Part 2
    • Doyle1
  • 43
    • 0040948402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 225; see also Doyle, 'Kant, Part 2'; Doyle, 'Liberalism and World Politics', pp. 1156-7; and M. W. Doyle, 'Liberalism and International Relations', in R. Beiner and W. J. Booth, Kant and Political Philosophy: The Contemporary Legacy (London, 1993), pp. 176-7.
    • Liberalism and World Politics , pp. 1156-1157
    • Doyle1
  • 44
    • 0040948393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberalism and international relations
    • R. Beiner and W. J. Booth, London
    • Ibid., p. 225; see also Doyle, 'Kant, Part 2'; Doyle, 'Liberalism and World Politics', pp. 1156-7; and M. W. Doyle, 'Liberalism and International Relations', in R. Beiner and W. J. Booth, Kant and Political Philosophy: The Contemporary Legacy (London, 1993), pp. 176-7.
    • (1993) Kant and Political Philosophy: The Contemporary Legacy , pp. 176-177
    • Doyle, M.W.1
  • 45
    • 0040948393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be fair to Doyle, in his most recent work he does qualify his claim that 'peaceful restraint only seems to work in the liberals' relations with other liberals' with the qualification that relations with non-liberals do appear to be 'more complicated'. Doyle, 'Liberalism and International Relations', pp. 176-7. In his 'Kant, Part 2' he discusses the relations of liberal states with non-liberal states at some length.
    • Liberalism and International Relations , pp. 176-177
    • Doyle1
  • 46
    • 0040354345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the heading of Doyle's lists of liberal states in Doyle, 'Kant, Part 1', p. 209, and Doyle, 'Liberalism and International Relations', p. 193.
    • Kant, Part 1 , pp. 209
    • Doyle1
  • 49
    • 0039762301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H. Suganami, Reflections on the Causes of War (provisional title, Oxford, 1996), ch. 3; Cohen, 'Pacific Unions', p. 214.
    • Pacific Unions , pp. 214
    • Cohen1
  • 50
    • 0000099890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And yet it moves
    • (Spring 1995), and n.16 therein
    • See B. Russett, 'And Yet It Moves', International Security, 19:4 (Spring 1995), pp. 164-84, pp. 171-2 and n.16 therein; see also Z. Maoz and B. Russett, 'Normative and Structural Causes of Democratic Peace', American Political Science Review, 87:3 (Sept. 1993), pp. 624-38.
    • International Security , vol.19 , Issue.4 , pp. 164-184
    • Russett, B.1
  • 51
    • 33746328420 scopus 로고
    • Normative and structural causes of democratic peace
    • Sept.
    • See B. Russett, 'And Yet It Moves', International Security, 19:4 (Spring 1995), pp. 164-84, pp. 171-2 and n.16 therein; see also Z. Maoz and B. Russett, 'Normative and Structural Causes of Democratic Peace', American Political Science Review, 87:3 (Sept. 1993), pp. 624-38.
    • (1993) American Political Science Review , vol.87 , Issue.3 , pp. 624-638
    • Maoz, Z.1    Russett, B.2
  • 52
    • 84971896246 scopus 로고
    • Raymond cohen on pacific unions: A response and a reply
    • July
    • B. Russett, J. L. Ray and R. Cohen, 'Raymond Cohen on Pacific Unions: A Response and a Reply', Review of International Studies, 21:3 (July 1995), pp. 319-25, p. 325.
    • (1995) Review of International Studies , vol.21 , Issue.3 , pp. 319-325
    • Russett, B.1    Ray, J.L.2    Cohen, R.3
  • 53
    • 0039762301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, 'Pacific Unions'; Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future'; Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies'; J. MacMillan, 'Liberalism and Peace', D.Phil thesis, University of Oxford (1991); Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 85; Spiro, 'Insignificance of Liberal Peace'. Forsythe, Human Rights, pp. 27-31, draws on Mueller's 'developmentalism' enunciated in J. Mueller, Retreat from Doomsday (New York, 1989). The argument is in two parts: first, that all developed states (authoritarian as well as democratic) know that even a major conventional war would not be in their interests, and second that there is an increasing moral revulsion against war among such states which is a consequence of a broad historical learning process. Russett and Spiro continue their debate upon statistical methods in 'Correspondence: The Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:4 (Spring 1995), pp. 164-84.
    • Pacific Unions
    • Cohen1
  • 54
    • 0040948397 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, 'Pacific Unions'; Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future'; Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies'; J. MacMillan, 'Liberalism and Peace', D.Phil thesis, University of Oxford (1991); Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 85; Spiro, 'Insignificance of Liberal Peace'. Forsythe, Human Rights, pp. 27-31, draws on Mueller's 'developmentalism' enunciated in J. Mueller, Retreat from Doomsday (New York, 1989). The argument is in two parts: first, that all developed states (authoritarian as well as democratic) know that even a major conventional war would not be in their interests, and second that there is an increasing moral revulsion against war among such states which is a consequence of a broad historical learning process. Russett and Spiro continue their debate upon statistical methods in 'Correspondence: The Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:4 (Spring 1995), pp. 164-84.
    • Back to the Future
    • Mearsheimer1
  • 55
    • 0040354340 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, 'Pacific Unions'; Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future'; Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies'; J. MacMillan, 'Liberalism and Peace', D.Phil thesis, University of Oxford (1991); Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 85; Spiro, 'Insignificance of Liberal Peace'. Forsythe, Human Rights, pp. 27-31, draws on Mueller's 'developmentalism' enunciated in J. Mueller, Retreat from Doomsday (New York, 1989). The argument is in two parts: first, that all developed states (authoritarian as well as democratic) know that even a major conventional war would not be in their interests, and second that there is an increasing moral revulsion against war among such states which is a consequence of a broad historical learning process. Russett and Spiro continue their debate upon statistical methods in 'Correspondence: The Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:4 (Spring 1995), pp. 164-84.
    • Wars Between Democracies
    • Ray1
  • 56
    • 0039762300 scopus 로고
    • D.Phil thesis, University of Oxford
    • Cohen, 'Pacific Unions'; Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future'; Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies'; J. MacMillan, 'Liberalism and Peace', D.Phil thesis, University of Oxford (1991); Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 85; Spiro, 'Insignificance of Liberal Peace'. Forsythe, Human Rights, pp. 27-31, draws on Mueller's 'developmentalism' enunciated in J. Mueller, Retreat from Doomsday (New York, 1989). The argument is in two parts: first, that all developed states (authoritarian as well as democratic) know that even a major conventional war would not be in their interests, and second that there is an increasing moral revulsion against war among such states which is a consequence of a broad historical learning process. Russett and Spiro continue their debate upon statistical methods in 'Correspondence: The Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:4 (Spring 1995), pp. 164-84.
    • (1991) Liberalism and Peace
    • MacMillan, J.1
  • 57
    • 0003430827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, 'Pacific Unions'; Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future'; Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies'; J. MacMillan, 'Liberalism and Peace', D.Phil thesis, University of Oxford (1991); Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 85; Spiro, 'Insignificance of Liberal Peace'. Forsythe, Human Rights, pp. 27-31, draws on Mueller's 'developmentalism' enunciated in J. Mueller, Retreat from Doomsday (New York, 1989). The argument is in two parts: first, that all developed states (authoritarian as well as democratic) know that even a major conventional war would not be in their interests, and second that there is an increasing moral revulsion against war among such states which is a consequence of a broad historical learning process. Russett and Spiro continue their debate upon statistical methods in 'Correspondence: The Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:4 (Spring 1995), pp. 164-84.
    • Grasping the Democratic Peace , pp. 85
    • Russett1
  • 58
    • 0013490411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, 'Pacific Unions'; Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future'; Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies'; J. MacMillan, 'Liberalism and Peace', D.Phil thesis, University of Oxford (1991); Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 85; Spiro, 'Insignificance of Liberal Peace'. Forsythe, Human Rights, pp. 27-31, draws on Mueller's 'developmentalism' enunciated in J. Mueller, Retreat from Doomsday (New York, 1989). The argument is in two parts: first, that all developed states (authoritarian as well as democratic) know that even a major conventional war would not be in their interests, and second that there is an increasing moral revulsion against war among such states which is a consequence of a broad historical learning process. Russett and Spiro continue their debate upon statistical methods in 'Correspondence: The Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:4 (Spring 1995), pp. 164-84.
    • Insignificance of Liberal Peace
    • Spiro1
  • 59
    • 0011859126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, 'Pacific Unions'; Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future'; Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies'; J. MacMillan, 'Liberalism and Peace', D.Phil thesis, University of Oxford (1991); Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 85; Spiro, 'Insignificance of Liberal Peace'. Forsythe, Human Rights, pp. 27-31, draws on Mueller's 'developmentalism' enunciated in J. Mueller, Retreat from Doomsday (New York, 1989). The argument is in two parts: first, that all developed states (authoritarian as well as democratic) know that even a major conventional war would not be in their interests, and second that there is an increasing moral revulsion against war among such states which is a consequence of a broad historical learning process. Russett and Spiro continue their debate upon statistical methods in 'Correspondence: The Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:4 (Spring 1995), pp. 164-84.
    • Human Rights , pp. 27-31
    • Forsythe1
  • 60
    • 0011518629 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • Cohen, 'Pacific Unions'; Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future'; Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies'; J. MacMillan, 'Liberalism and Peace', D.Phil thesis, University of Oxford (1991); Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 85; Spiro, 'Insignificance of Liberal Peace'. Forsythe, Human Rights, pp. 27-31, draws on Mueller's 'developmentalism' enunciated in J. Mueller, Retreat from Doomsday (New York, 1989). The argument is in two parts: first, that all developed states (authoritarian as well as democratic) know that even a major conventional war would not be in their interests, and second that there is an increasing moral revulsion against war among such states which is a consequence of a broad historical learning process. Russett and Spiro continue their debate upon statistical methods in 'Correspondence: The Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:4 (Spring 1995), pp. 164-84.
    • (1989) Retreat from Doomsday
    • Mueller, J.1
  • 61
    • 0000099890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Correspondence: The democratic peace
    • continue their debate upon statistical methods in Spring
    • Cohen, 'Pacific Unions'; Mearsheimer, 'Back to the Future'; Ray, 'Wars Between Democracies'; J. MacMillan, 'Liberalism and Peace', D.Phil thesis, University of Oxford (1991); Russett, Grasping the Democratic Peace, p. 85; Spiro, 'Insignificance of Liberal Peace'. Forsythe, Human Rights, pp. 27-31, draws on Mueller's 'developmentalism' enunciated in J. Mueller, Retreat from Doomsday (New York, 1989). The argument is in two parts: first, that all developed states (authoritarian as well as democratic) know that even a major conventional war would not be in their interests, and second that there is an increasing moral revulsion against war among such states which is a consequence of a broad historical learning process. Russett and Spiro continue their debate upon statistical methods in 'Correspondence: The Democratic Peace', International Security, 19:4 (Spring 1995), pp. 164-84.
    • (1995) International Security , vol.19 , Issue.4 , pp. 164-184
    • Russett1    Spiro2
  • 64
    • 0039762290 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • R. J. B. Bosworth, Italy, the Least of the Great Powers (Cambridge, 1979), pp. 123, 132, 134. In fact, the situation is more complicated, for, by Italian standards, the leaders concerned would have regarded themselves as being liberals. In the Italian context, however, this led to an especial concern for certain territorial acquisitions in the interests of the completion of the Risorgimento. This indicates further questions for research in this area regarding the diversity of the liberal traditions in various national contexts and also that there is a degree of tension in the liberal tradition between universalism and particularism.
    • (1979) Italy, the Least of the Great Powers , pp. 123
    • Bosworth, R.J.B.1
  • 68
    • 0003776178 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • See for example A. J. P. Taylor, The Struggle for Mastery in Europe 1848-1918 (Oxford, 1954), p. 381; P. M. Kennedy, The Realities Behind Diplomacy (London, 1981), p. 112; J. Joll, Europe since 1870 (Harmondsworth, 1985), p. 98.
    • (1954) The Struggle for Mastery in Europe 1848-1918 , pp. 381
    • Taylor, A.J.P.1
  • 69
    • 0003792106 scopus 로고
    • London
    • See for example A. J. P. Taylor, The Struggle for Mastery in Europe 1848-1918 (Oxford, 1954), p. 381; P. M. Kennedy, The Realities Behind Diplomacy (London, 1981), p. 112; J. Joll, Europe since 1870 (Harmondsworth, 1985), p. 98.
    • (1981) The Realities Behind Diplomacy , pp. 112
    • Kennedy, P.M.1
  • 70
    • 0039847290 scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth
    • See for example A. J. P. Taylor, The Struggle for Mastery in Europe 1848-1918 (Oxford, 1954), p. 381; P. M. Kennedy, The Realities Behind Diplomacy (London, 1981), p. 112; J. Joll, Europe since 1870 (Harmondsworth, 1985), p. 98.
    • (1985) Europe since 1870 , pp. 98
    • Joll, J.1
  • 71
    • 0039762301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cohen, 'Pacific Unions', p. 219, and Layne, 'Kant or Cant', pp. 28-33. Their interpretation of the conflict in terms of superior British power probably overplays the assumption of 'rationality'. They overlook the possibility that the parties could have been pushed to war through concern for other factors such as credibility, honour, or domestic political pressures.
    • Pacific Unions , pp. 219
    • Cohen1
  • 72
    • 61449162892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cohen, 'Pacific Unions', p. 219, and Layne, 'Kant or Cant', pp. 28-33. Their interpretation of the conflict in terms of superior British power probably overplays the assumption of 'rationality'. They overlook the possibility that the parties could have been pushed to war through concern for other factors such as credibility, honour, or domestic political pressures.
    • Kant or Cant , pp. 28-33
    • Layne1
  • 75
    • 0039762238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (London, forthcoming) for the development of this approach
    • See J. MacMillan, On Liberal Peace (London, forthcoming) for the development of this approach.
    • On Liberal Peace
    • MacMillan, J.1
  • 82
    • 84970639568 scopus 로고
    • A kantian protest against the peculiar discourse of inter-liberal state peace
    • Winter
    • Although I do discuss the implications of Kant's political philosophy for the 'democracies don't fight' debate, and the way in which Kant's thought has been interpreted by liberal peace theorists, in 'A Kantian Protest against the Peculiar Discourse of Inter-Liberal State Peace', Millennium, 24:3 (Winter 1995), pp. 549-62.
    • (1995) Millennium , vol.24 , Issue.3 , pp. 549-562
  • 83
    • 0003984012 scopus 로고
    • New York, book 3, ch. 22
    • A. de Tocqueville, Democracy in America (New York, 1990), book 3, ch. 22, p. 269. Montesquieu explicitly referred to the dangers presented by conquest to the domestic constitution of a democracy: 'If a democracy conquers a people in order to govern it as a subject, it will expose its own liberty, because it will entrust too much power to the magistrates whom it sends out to the conquered state'. Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws, p. 143.
    • (1990) Democracy in America , pp. 269
    • De Tocqueville, A.1
  • 84
    • 0003897575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A. de Tocqueville, Democracy in America (New York, 1990), book 3, ch. 22, p. 269. Montesquieu explicitly referred to the dangers presented by conquest to the domestic constitution of a democracy: 'If a democracy conquers a people in order to govern it as a subject, it will expose its own liberty, because it will entrust too much power to the magistrates whom it sends out to the conquered state'. Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws, p. 143.
    • The Spirit of the Laws , pp. 143
    • Montesquieu1
  • 93
    • 0003483665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 158. Z. Maoz and B. Russett adopt a broadly similar explanatory framework in 'Normative and Structural Causes'.
    • War and Reason , pp. 158
  • 95
    • 0037926000 scopus 로고
    • The metaphysics of morals
    • H. Reiss (ed.), Cambridge
    • I. Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals', in H. Reiss (ed.), Kant's Political Writings (Cambridge, 1991), p. 174.
    • (1991) Kant's Political Writings , pp. 174
    • Kant, I.1
  • 97
    • 0040354335 scopus 로고
    • The duties of liberal states
    • C. Navari (ed.), Milton Keynes
    • C. Brewin, 'The Duties of Liberal States', in C. Navari (ed.), The Condition of States (Milton Keynes, 1991), p. 207.
    • (1991) The Condition of States , pp. 207
    • Brewin, C.1
  • 98
    • 0039169789 scopus 로고
    • 3 November
    • 558 H. C. Deb., 1905, 3 November 1956.
    • (1956) H. C. Deb. , vol.558 , pp. 1905
  • 103
    • 18944401546 scopus 로고
    • ASEAN's search for regional order
    • Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences, National University of Singapore
    • M. Leifer, 'ASEAN's Search for Regional Order', Faculty Lecture 12, Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences, National University of Singapore, 1987.
    • (1987) Faculty Lecture , vol.12
    • Leifer, M.1
  • 104
    • 0000960445 scopus 로고
    • A neo-gramscian approach to international organisation
    • J. MacMillan and Andrew Linklater (eds.), London
    • For a critical discussion of the adoption of the neoliberal model of economic development see K. Lee, 'A Neo-Gramscian Approach to International Organisation', in J. MacMillan and Andrew Linklater (eds.), Boundaries in Question: New Directions in International Relations (London, 1995). R. Rosecrance, The Rise of the Trading State (New York, 1986); C. Ziegler, Foreign Policy and East Asia, Learning and Adaptation in the Gorbachev Era (Cambridge, 1993).
    • (1995) Boundaries in Question: New Directions in International Relations
    • Lee, K.1
  • 105
    • 0003653875 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • For a critical discussion of the adoption of the neoliberal model of economic development see K. Lee, 'A Neo-Gramscian Approach to International Organisation', in J. MacMillan and Andrew Linklater (eds.), Boundaries in Question: New Directions in International Relations (London, 1995). R. Rosecrance, The Rise of the Trading State (New York, 1986); C. Ziegler, Foreign Policy and East Asia, Learning and Adaptation in the Gorbachev Era (Cambridge, 1993).
    • (1986) The Rise of the Trading State
    • Rosecrance, R.1
  • 106
    • 0011260224 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • For a critical discussion of the adoption of the neoliberal model of economic development see K. Lee, 'A Neo-Gramscian Approach to International Organisation', in J. MacMillan and Andrew Linklater (eds.), Boundaries in Question: New Directions in International Relations (London, 1995). R. Rosecrance, The Rise of the Trading State (New York, 1986); C. Ziegler, Foreign Policy and East Asia, Learning and Adaptation in the Gorbachev Era (Cambridge, 1993).
    • (1993) Foreign Policy and East Asia, Learning and Adaptation in the Gorbachev Era
    • Ziegler, C.1
  • 107
    • 0003566525 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ, shows convincingly the way in which the foreign aid regime emerged after World War II as the international counterpart of the domestic welfare state and increasing awareness of world poverty and beliefs regarding the interdependencies of peace, prosperity and justice
    • In this vein, D. H. Lumsdaine, Moral Vision in International Politics: The Foreign Aid Regime, 1949-1989 (Princeton, NJ, 1993), shows convincingly the way in which the foreign aid regime emerged after World War II as the international counterpart of the domestic welfare state and increasing awareness of world poverty and beliefs regarding the interdependencies of peace, prosperity and justice.
    • (1993) Moral Vision in International Politics: The Foreign Aid Regime, 1949-1989
    • Lumsdaine, D.H.1
  • 108
    • 0038461460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a study of the relationship between domestic political ideologies and foreign policy assumptions see Ceadel, Thinking about Peace and War.
    • Thinking about Peace and War
    • Ceadel1
  • 110
    • 84970203238 scopus 로고
    • Social forces, states and world order: Beyond international theory
    • See for instance R. Cox, 'Social Forces, States and World Order: Beyond International Theory', Millennium 10:2 (1981); A. Wendt, 'Anarchy is What States Make of it: The Social Construction of Power Politics', International Organisation, 46 (1992), pp. 392-425; M. Neufeld, 'Reflexivity and International Relations Theory', Millennium, 22:1 (1993). Lumsdaine's Moral Vision is a major study to have linked philosophical factors with policy developments.
    • (1981) Millennium , vol.10 , Issue.2
    • Cox, R.1
  • 111
    • 84972442822 scopus 로고
    • Anarchy is what states make of it: The social construction of power politics
    • See for instance R. Cox, 'Social Forces, States and World Order: Beyond International Theory', Millennium 10:2 (1981); A. Wendt, 'Anarchy is What States Make of it: The Social Construction of Power Politics', International Organisation, 46 (1992), pp. 392-425; M. Neufeld, 'Reflexivity and International Relations Theory', Millennium, 22:1 (1993). Lumsdaine's Moral Vision is a major study to have linked philosophical factors with policy developments.
    • (1992) International Organisation , vol.46 , pp. 392-425
    • Wendt, A.1
  • 112
    • 0003126391 scopus 로고
    • Reflexivity and international relations theory
    • See for instance R. Cox, 'Social Forces, States and World Order: Beyond International Theory', Millennium 10:2 (1981); A. Wendt, 'Anarchy is What States Make of it: The Social Construction of Power Politics', International Organisation, 46 (1992), pp. 392-425; M. Neufeld, 'Reflexivity and International Relations Theory', Millennium, 22:1 (1993). Lumsdaine's Moral Vision is a major study to have linked philosophical factors with policy developments.
    • (1993) Millennium , vol.22 , Issue.1
    • Neufeld, M.1
  • 114
    • 0011618515 scopus 로고
    • London, [1924].
    • F. Meinecke, Machiavellism (London, 1957 [1924]). In case readers think it odd that I should draw upon Realist writers to support an argument rooted in liberalism, it should be remembered that a number of liberals (e.g. Kant) held similar views regarding the impediment to moral development presented by the anarchic nature of the international system.
    • (1957) Machiavellism
    • Meinecke, F.1
  • 115
    • 0040948386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Lumsdaine's analysis of the foreign aid regime in Moral Vision is a notable model of how to disaggregate the significance of particularly liberal elements upon policy-making within a liberal democratic state.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.