-
1
-
-
85164848677
-
-
Berkeley: University of California Press
-
A sampling of these theories would include Ronald Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992); Robert N. Bellah, Richard Madsen, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler and Steven M. Tipton, Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life (New York: Harper & Row, 1985); Amitai Etzioni, ed., New Communitarian Thinking: Persons, Virtues, Institutions, and Communities (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1995); Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities, and the Communitarian Agenda (New York: Crown, 1993); William Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); William Galston, "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995), 516-34; Mary Ann Glendon, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse (New York: The Free Press, 1991); Mary Ann Glendon and David Blankenhorn, eds., Seedbeds of Virtue: Sources of Competence, Character, and Citizenship in American Society (New York: Madison Books, 1995); and Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990). For a useful overview and typology of contemporary citizenship theories, see Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman, "Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory," Ethics 104 (1994), 352-81. The above works lie between (and complicate) Kymlicka and Norman's categories of "civil society theories" and "liberal virtue theories." As the above list suggests, the majority of theorists of liberal citizenship are American, and their analyses can appear parochially so. In popular and political rhetoric, public policy and academic theory, however, the perspective has its influence in Canada and the United Kingdom as well (though even in these latter contexts, the United States tends to be treated as paradigmatic of the dangers represented by a decline in liberal citizen virtues).
-
(1992)
What's the Matter with Liberalism?
-
-
Beiner, R.1
-
2
-
-
0004057043
-
-
New York: Harper & Row
-
A sampling of these theories would include Ronald Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992); Robert N. Bellah, Richard Madsen, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler and Steven M. Tipton, Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life (New York: Harper & Row, 1985); Amitai Etzioni, ed., New Communitarian Thinking: Persons, Virtues, Institutions, and Communities (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1995); Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities, and the Communitarian Agenda (New York: Crown, 1993); William Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); William Galston, "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995), 516-34; Mary Ann Glendon, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse (New York: The Free Press, 1991); Mary Ann Glendon and David Blankenhorn, eds., Seedbeds of Virtue: Sources of Competence, Character, and Citizenship in American Society (New York: Madison Books, 1995); and Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990). For a useful overview and typology of contemporary citizenship theories, see Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman, "Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory," Ethics 104 (1994), 352-81. The above works lie between (and complicate) Kymlicka and Norman's categories of "civil society theories" and "liberal virtue theories." As the above list suggests, the majority of theorists of liberal citizenship are American, and their analyses can appear parochially so. In popular and political rhetoric, public policy and academic theory, however, the perspective has its influence in Canada and the United Kingdom as well (though even in these latter contexts, the United States tends to be treated as paradigmatic of the dangers represented by a decline in liberal citizen virtues).
-
(1985)
Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life
-
-
Bellah, R.N.1
Madsen, R.2
Sullivan, W.M.3
Swidler, A.4
Tipton, S.M.5
-
3
-
-
0003463512
-
-
Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia
-
A sampling of these theories would include Ronald Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992); Robert N. Bellah, Richard Madsen, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler and Steven M. Tipton, Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life (New York: Harper & Row, 1985); Amitai Etzioni, ed., New Communitarian Thinking: Persons, Virtues, Institutions, and Communities (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1995); Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities, and the Communitarian Agenda (New York: Crown, 1993); William Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); William Galston, "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995), 516-34; Mary Ann Glendon, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse (New York: The Free Press, 1991); Mary Ann Glendon and David Blankenhorn, eds., Seedbeds of Virtue: Sources of Competence, Character, and Citizenship in American Society (New York: Madison Books, 1995); and Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990). For a useful overview and typology of contemporary citizenship theories, see Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman, "Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory," Ethics 104 (1994), 352-81. The above works lie between (and complicate) Kymlicka and Norman's categories of "civil society theories" and "liberal virtue theories." As the above list suggests, the majority of theorists of liberal citizenship are American, and their analyses can appear parochially so. In popular and political rhetoric, public policy and academic theory, however, the perspective has its influence in Canada and the United Kingdom as well (though even in these latter contexts, the United States tends to be treated as paradigmatic of the dangers represented by a decline in liberal citizen virtues).
-
(1995)
New Communitarian Thinking: Persons, Virtues, Institutions, and Communities
-
-
Etzioni, A.1
-
4
-
-
0004010696
-
-
New York: Crown
-
A sampling of these theories would include Ronald Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992); Robert N. Bellah, Richard Madsen, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler and Steven M. Tipton, Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life (New York: Harper & Row, 1985); Amitai Etzioni, ed., New Communitarian Thinking: Persons, Virtues, Institutions, and Communities (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1995); Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities, and the Communitarian Agenda (New York: Crown, 1993); William Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); William Galston, "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995), 516-34; Mary Ann Glendon, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse (New York: The Free Press, 1991); Mary Ann Glendon and David Blankenhorn, eds., Seedbeds of Virtue: Sources of Competence, Character, and Citizenship in American Society (New York: Madison Books, 1995); and Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990). For a useful overview and typology of contemporary citizenship theories, see Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman, "Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory," Ethics 104 (1994), 352-81. The above works lie between (and complicate) Kymlicka and Norman's categories of "civil society theories" and "liberal virtue theories." As the above list suggests, the majority of theorists of liberal citizenship are American, and their analyses can appear parochially so. In popular and political rhetoric, public policy and academic theory, however, the perspective has its influence in Canada and the United Kingdom as well (though even in these latter contexts, the United States tends to be treated as paradigmatic of the dangers represented by a decline in liberal citizen virtues).
-
(1993)
The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities, and the Communitarian Agenda
-
-
Etzioni, A.1
-
5
-
-
0003491522
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
A sampling of these theories would include Ronald Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992); Robert N. Bellah, Richard Madsen, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler and Steven M. Tipton, Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life (New York: Harper & Row, 1985); Amitai Etzioni, ed., New Communitarian Thinking: Persons, Virtues, Institutions, and Communities (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1995); Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities, and the Communitarian Agenda (New York: Crown, 1993); William Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); William Galston, "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995), 516-34; Mary Ann Glendon, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse (New York: The Free Press, 1991); Mary Ann Glendon and David Blankenhorn, eds., Seedbeds of Virtue: Sources of Competence, Character, and Citizenship in American Society (New York: Madison Books, 1995); and Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990). For a useful overview and typology of contemporary citizenship theories, see Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman, "Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory," Ethics 104 (1994), 352-81. The above works lie between (and complicate) Kymlicka and Norman's categories of "civil society theories" and "liberal virtue theories." As the above list suggests, the majority of theorists of liberal citizenship are American, and their analyses can appear parochially so. In popular and political rhetoric, public policy and academic theory, however, the perspective has its influence in Canada and the United Kingdom as well (though even in these latter contexts, the United States tends to be treated as paradigmatic of the dangers represented by a decline in liberal citizen virtues).
-
(1991)
Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State
-
-
Galston, W.1
-
6
-
-
84916947233
-
Two concepts of liberalism
-
A sampling of these theories would include Ronald Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992); Robert N. Bellah, Richard Madsen, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler and Steven M. Tipton, Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life (New York: Harper & Row, 1985); Amitai Etzioni, ed., New Communitarian Thinking: Persons, Virtues, Institutions, and Communities (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1995); Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities, and the Communitarian Agenda (New York: Crown, 1993); William Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); William Galston, "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995), 516-34; Mary Ann Glendon, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse (New York: The Free Press, 1991); Mary Ann Glendon and David Blankenhorn, eds., Seedbeds of Virtue: Sources of Competence, Character, and Citizenship in American Society (New York: Madison Books, 1995); and Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990). For a useful overview and typology of contemporary citizenship theories, see Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman, "Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory," Ethics 104 (1994), 352-81. The above works lie between (and complicate) Kymlicka and Norman's categories of "civil society theories" and "liberal virtue theories." As the above list suggests, the majority of theorists of liberal citizenship are American, and their analyses can appear parochially so. In popular and political rhetoric, public policy and academic theory, however, the perspective has its influence in Canada and the United Kingdom as well (though even in these latter contexts, the United States tends to be treated as paradigmatic of the dangers represented by a decline in liberal citizen virtues).
-
(1995)
Ethics
, vol.105
, pp. 516-534
-
-
Galston, W.1
-
7
-
-
0003400722
-
-
New York: The Free Press
-
A sampling of these theories would include Ronald Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992); Robert N. Bellah, Richard Madsen, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler and Steven M. Tipton, Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life (New York: Harper & Row, 1985); Amitai Etzioni, ed., New Communitarian Thinking: Persons, Virtues, Institutions, and Communities (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1995); Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities, and the Communitarian Agenda (New York: Crown, 1993); William Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); William Galston, "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995), 516-34; Mary Ann Glendon, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse (New York: The Free Press, 1991); Mary Ann Glendon and David Blankenhorn, eds., Seedbeds of Virtue: Sources of Competence, Character, and Citizenship in American Society (New York: Madison Books, 1995); and Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990). For a useful overview and typology of contemporary citizenship theories, see Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman, "Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory," Ethics 104 (1994), 352-81. The above works lie between (and complicate) Kymlicka and Norman's categories of "civil society theories" and "liberal virtue theories." As the above list suggests, the majority of theorists of liberal citizenship are American, and their analyses can appear parochially so. In popular and political rhetoric, public policy and academic theory, however, the perspective has its influence in Canada and the United Kingdom as well (though even in these latter contexts, the United States tends to be treated as paradigmatic of the dangers represented by a decline in liberal citizen virtues).
-
(1991)
Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse
-
-
Glendon, M.A.1
-
8
-
-
0003789435
-
-
New York: Madison Books
-
A sampling of these theories would include Ronald Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992); Robert N. Bellah, Richard Madsen, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler and Steven M. Tipton, Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life (New York: Harper & Row, 1985); Amitai Etzioni, ed., New Communitarian Thinking: Persons, Virtues, Institutions, and Communities (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1995); Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities, and the Communitarian Agenda (New York: Crown, 1993); William Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); William Galston, "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995), 516-34; Mary Ann Glendon, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse (New York: The Free Press, 1991); Mary Ann Glendon and David Blankenhorn, eds., Seedbeds of Virtue: Sources of Competence, Character, and Citizenship in American Society (New York: Madison Books, 1995); and Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990). For a useful overview and typology of contemporary citizenship theories, see Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman, "Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory," Ethics 104 (1994), 352-81. The above works lie between (and complicate) Kymlicka and Norman's categories of "civil society theories" and "liberal virtue theories." As the above list suggests, the majority of theorists of liberal citizenship are American, and their analyses can appear parochially so. In popular and political rhetoric, public policy and academic theory, however, the perspective has its influence in Canada and the United Kingdom as well (though even in these latter contexts, the United States tends to be treated as paradigmatic of the dangers represented by a decline in liberal citizen virtues).
-
(1995)
Seedbeds of Virtue: Sources of Competence, Character, and Citizenship in American Society
-
-
Glendon, M.A.1
Blankenhorn, D.2
-
9
-
-
0003796286
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
A sampling of these theories would include Ronald Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992); Robert N. Bellah, Richard Madsen, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler and Steven M. Tipton, Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life (New York: Harper & Row, 1985); Amitai Etzioni, ed., New Communitarian Thinking: Persons, Virtues, Institutions, and Communities (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1995); Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities, and the Communitarian Agenda (New York: Crown, 1993); William Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); William Galston, "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995), 516-34; Mary Ann Glendon, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse (New York: The Free Press, 1991); Mary Ann Glendon and David Blankenhorn, eds., Seedbeds of Virtue: Sources of Competence, Character, and Citizenship in American Society (New York: Madison Books, 1995); and Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990). For a useful overview and typology of contemporary citizenship theories, see Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman, "Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory," Ethics 104 (1994), 352-81. The above works lie between (and complicate) Kymlicka and Norman's categories of "civil society theories" and "liberal virtue theories." As the above list suggests, the majority of theorists of liberal citizenship are American, and their analyses can appear parochially so. In popular and political rhetoric, public policy and academic theory, however, the perspective has its influence in Canada and the United Kingdom as well (though even in these latter contexts, the United States tends to be treated as paradigmatic of the dangers represented by a decline in liberal citizen virtues).
-
(1990)
Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism
-
-
Macedo, S.1
-
10
-
-
0001386035
-
Return of the citizen: A survey of recent work on citizenship theory
-
A sampling of these theories would include Ronald Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992); Robert N. Bellah, Richard Madsen, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler and Steven M. Tipton, Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life (New York: Harper & Row, 1985); Amitai Etzioni, ed., New Communitarian Thinking: Persons, Virtues, Institutions, and Communities (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1995); Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities, and the Communitarian Agenda (New York: Crown, 1993); William Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991); William Galston, "Two Concepts of Liberalism," Ethics 105 (1995), 516-34; Mary Ann Glendon, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse (New York: The Free Press, 1991); Mary Ann Glendon and David Blankenhorn, eds., Seedbeds of Virtue: Sources of Competence, Character, and Citizenship in American Society (New York: Madison Books, 1995); and Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990). For a useful overview and typology of contemporary citizenship theories, see Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman, "Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory," Ethics 104 (1994), 352-81. The above works lie between (and complicate) Kymlicka and Norman's categories of "civil society theories" and "liberal virtue theories." As the above list suggests, the majority of theorists of liberal citizenship are American, and their analyses can appear parochially so. In popular and political rhetoric, public policy and academic theory, however, the perspective has its influence in Canada and the United Kingdom as well (though even in these latter contexts, the United States tends to be treated as paradigmatic of the dangers represented by a decline in liberal citizen virtues).
-
(1994)
Ethics
, vol.104
, pp. 352-381
-
-
Kymlicka, W.1
Norman, W.2
-
11
-
-
0003913651
-
-
Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press
-
For example, Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981); Michael J. Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983); and Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality (Oxford: Martin Robertson, 1983).
-
(1981)
After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory
-
-
Macintyre, A.1
-
12
-
-
0004253960
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
For example, Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981); Michael J. Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983); and Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality (Oxford: Martin Robertson, 1983).
-
(1983)
Liberalism and the Limits of Justice
-
-
Sandel, M.J.1
-
13
-
-
0003924191
-
-
Oxford: Martin Robertson
-
For example, Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981); Michael J. Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983); and Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality (Oxford: Martin Robertson, 1983).
-
(1983)
Spheres of Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality
-
-
Walzer, M.1
-
14
-
-
84972623105
-
Political liberalism
-
Charles Larmore, "Political Liberalism," Political Theory 18 (1990), 339-60; J. Donald Moon, Constructing Community: Moral Pluralism and Tragic Conflicts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993); Thomas Nagel, Equality and Partiality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991); and John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993).
-
(1990)
Political Theory
, vol.18
, pp. 339-360
-
-
Larmore, C.1
-
15
-
-
84890582589
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
Charles Larmore, "Political Liberalism," Political Theory 18 (1990), 339-60; J. Donald Moon, Constructing Community: Moral Pluralism and Tragic Conflicts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993); Thomas Nagel, Equality and Partiality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991); and John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993).
-
(1993)
Constructing Community: Moral Pluralism and Tragic Conflicts
-
-
Moon, J.D.1
-
16
-
-
84972623105
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Charles Larmore, "Political Liberalism," Political Theory 18 (1990), 339-60; J. Donald Moon, Constructing Community: Moral Pluralism and Tragic Conflicts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993); Thomas Nagel, Equality and Partiality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991); and John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993).
-
(1991)
Equality and Partiality
-
-
Nagel, T.1
-
17
-
-
84972623105
-
-
New York: Columbia University Press
-
Charles Larmore, "Political Liberalism," Political Theory 18 (1990), 339-60; J. Donald Moon, Constructing Community: Moral Pluralism and Tragic Conflicts (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993); Thomas Nagel, Equality and Partiality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991); and John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993).
-
(1993)
Political Liberalism
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
18
-
-
0039296333
-
-
note
-
For contextualist theorists, the term "understandings" comprises not only the concepts a group self-consciously employs but the web of socially formed desires, habits and judgments that give these concepts their resonance for the group. There thus is an intimate link between understandings, values and forms of character.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
84935600853
-
Assessing the communitarian critique of liberalism
-
See, for example, Allen E. Buchanan, "Assessing the Communitarian Critique of Liberalism," Ethics 99 (1989), 852-82; Amy Gutmann, "Communitarian Critics of Liberalism," Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1985), 308-22; and Will Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community and Culture (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991).
-
(1989)
Ethics
, vol.99
, pp. 852-882
-
-
Buchanan, A.E.1
-
20
-
-
84935566128
-
Communitarian critics of liberalism
-
See, for example, Allen E. Buchanan, "Assessing the Communitarian Critique of Liberalism," Ethics 99 (1989), 852-82; Amy Gutmann, "Communitarian Critics of Liberalism," Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1985), 308-22; and Will Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community and Culture (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991).
-
(1985)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.14
, pp. 308-322
-
-
Gutmann, A.1
-
21
-
-
0003460304
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
See, for example, Allen E. Buchanan, "Assessing the Communitarian Critique of Liberalism," Ethics 99 (1989), 852-82; Amy Gutmann, "Communitarian Critics of Liberalism," Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1985), 308-22; and Will Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community and Culture (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991).
-
(1991)
Liberalism, Community and Culture
-
-
Kymlicka, W.1
-
22
-
-
0003624191
-
-
Rawls does not suggest that justice as fairness would dictate a resolution to every public dispute; he is most interested in the basic structure of society, and his examples tend to single out distributive issues. Though Rawls does at times seem to hope for a wider scope of application for his method: consider his comments on the reasonableness of a qualified right to abortion (Political Liberalism, 243ff.) or on advertising and freedom of speech (ibid., 363-66).
-
Political Liberalism
-
-
-
23
-
-
0003624191
-
-
Rawls does not suggest that justice as fairness would dictate a resolution to every public dispute; he is most interested in the basic structure of society, and his examples tend to single out distributive issues. Though Rawls does at times seem to hope for a wider scope of application for his method: consider his comments on the reasonableness of a qualified right to abortion (Political Liberalism, 243ff.) or on advertising and freedom of speech (ibid., 363-66).
-
Political Liberalism
, pp. 363-366
-
-
-
24
-
-
0040481284
-
-
note
-
Abstract or general public agreements do in fact have determinate consequences when embodied in legislation; however messy the agreement that puts a law in place, the application of that law will have concrete effects. Unlike on the political liberal model, however, the consequences of institutionalized agreements do not necessarily sit comfortably with the comprehensive understandings of a diverse citizenry. Where Rawls's overlapping consensus would provide a way around disputes over basic justice, giving each party reasons from its own perspective to agree to previously controversial outcomes, the fact of pervasiveness suggests that political agreements - both abstract and concrete - will have a more approximate quality than this, and will derive a looser kind of legitimacy than Rawls seeks for "justice as fairness." To use Rawlsian parlance, the shared public culture of liberal democratic societies permits something like a "constitutional consensus," whereas the fact of pervasiveness stands permanently in the way of an overlapping consensus of the sort modeled by Rawls. This points not to a permanent deficit of justice or legitimacy, but to the fact that Rawls's theory premises justice and legitimacy on an unnecessarily and unrealistically strong form of agreement.
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
84909229643
-
Democratic character and community: The logic of congruence?
-
Galston and Macedo are two among many theorists of liberal citizenship; I focus upon their work because it provides the most carefully articulated versions of the argumentative strategy I wish to criticize, and because their failings are reiterated by other work in this vein. Their failings also have implications for theories of democratic citizenship, insofar as these repeat the strategy of arguing from putatively "shared" understandings of democratic virtues to particular policies for their cultivation. For a valuable review of "constitutive democratic theory" see Nancy L. Rosenblum, "Democratic Character and Community: The Logic of Congruence?" Journal of Political Philosophy 2 (1994), 67-97.
-
(1994)
Journal of Political Philosophy
, vol.2
, pp. 67-97
-
-
Rosenblum, N.L.1
-
27
-
-
58149478781
-
Liberal civic education and religious fundamentalism: The case of God v. John rawls
-
Macedo may have moved somewhat closer to a Rawlsian emphasis on the nonimpositional character of liberal public reasonableness; see Macedo, "Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls," Ethics 105 (1995), 468-96. He continues, however, to view liberalism as a way of life or regime that seeks to remake certain comprehensive commitments (ibid., 477 n. 39). He calls this "political liberalism with spine" (ibid., 470).
-
(1995)
Ethics
, vol.105
, pp. 468-496
-
-
Macedo1
-
28
-
-
0040481278
-
-
Macedo may have moved somewhat closer to a Rawlsian emphasis on the nonimpositional character of liberal public reasonableness; see Macedo, "Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls," Ethics 105 (1995), 468-96. He continues, however, to view liberalism as a way of life or regime that seeks to remake certain comprehensive commitments (ibid., 477 n. 39). He calls this "political liberalism with spine" (ibid., 470).
-
Ethics
, vol.39
, pp. 477
-
-
-
29
-
-
0039888303
-
-
Macedo may have moved somewhat closer to a Rawlsian emphasis on the nonimpositional character of liberal public reasonableness; see Macedo, "Liberal Civic Education and Religious Fundamentalism: The Case of God v. John Rawls," Ethics 105 (1995), 468-96. He continues, however, to view liberalism as a way of life or regime that seeks to remake certain comprehensive commitments (ibid., 477 n. 39). He calls this "political liberalism with spine" (ibid., 470).
-
Ethics
, pp. 470
-
-
-
30
-
-
0000460954
-
Rawls' 'political' philosophy and american democracy
-
See George Klosko, "Rawls' 'Political' Philosophy and American Democracy," American Political Science Review 87 (1993), 348-59; Patrick Neal, "Justice as Fairness: Political or Metaphysical?" Political Theory 18 (1990), 24-50; and Brian Walker, "John Rawls, Mikhail Bakhtin and Liberal Toleration," Political Theory 23 (1995), 101-27.
-
(1993)
American Political Science Review
, vol.87
, pp. 348-359
-
-
Klosko, G.1
-
31
-
-
84930560079
-
Justice as fairness: Political or metaphysical?
-
See George Klosko, "Rawls' 'Political' Philosophy and American Democracy," American Political Science Review 87 (1993), 348-59; Patrick Neal, "Justice as Fairness: Political or Metaphysical?" Political Theory 18 (1990), 24-50; and Brian Walker, "John Rawls, Mikhail Bakhtin and Liberal Toleration," Political Theory 23 (1995), 101-27.
-
(1990)
Political Theory
, vol.18
, pp. 24-50
-
-
Neal, P.1
-
32
-
-
84970775452
-
John Rawls, Mikhail Bakhtin and liberal toleration
-
See George Klosko, "Rawls' 'Political' Philosophy and American Democracy," American Political Science Review 87 (1993), 348-59; Patrick Neal, "Justice as Fairness: Political or Metaphysical?" Political Theory 18 (1990), 24-50; and Brian Walker, "John Rawls, Mikhail Bakhtin and Liberal Toleration," Political Theory 23 (1995), 101-27.
-
(1995)
Political Theory
, vol.23
, pp. 101-127
-
-
Walker, B.1
-
35
-
-
0003758111
-
-
Glendon blames inarticulateness about liberal goods not on neutrality per se but on a deracinated "rights talk," which "puts a damper on processes of public justification, communication, and deliberation upon which the continuing vitality of a democratic regime depends. It contributes to the erosion of the habits, practices, and attitudes of respect for others that are the ultimate and surest guarantees of human rights" (Glendon, Rights Talk, 171).
-
Rights Talk
, pp. 171
-
-
Glendon1
-
36
-
-
0004037474
-
-
Cambridge: Harvard University Press
-
While Charles Taylor's analysis of contemporary liberalism is more nuanced than that offered by theorists of liberal citizenship, he shares this set of concerns, and also the belief that articulacy about liberal goods would help overcome certain problems of stalemate and fragmentation. See Charles Taylor, The Ethics of Authenticity (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1992).
-
(1992)
The Ethics of Authenticity
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
41
-
-
0039888293
-
Ma, can I be a feminist and still like liberalism?
-
Chicago
-
An aspect of the alarmist tone particularly worth disputing is the blame implicitly heaped, by Galston especially, upon feminists, gay and lesbian activists and others who challenge traditional structures in the name of political and cultural recognition. Joan Tronto is appropriately scathing on the complacently mainstream "we" constructed by "cultural liberals" (Joan Tronto, "Ma, Can I Be a Feminist and Still Like Liberalism?" paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Association, Chicago, 1992, 16-25). For examples of such complacency see Galston, Liberal Purposes, 273; Glendon, Rights Talk, 58, 121, 148-55; and Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? passim.
-
(1992)
Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association
, pp. 16-25
-
-
Tronto, J.1
-
42
-
-
0003750156
-
-
An aspect of the alarmist tone particularly worth disputing is the blame implicitly heaped, by Galston especially, upon feminists, gay and lesbian activists and others who challenge traditional structures in the name of political and cultural recognition. Joan Tronto is appropriately scathing on the complacently mainstream "we" constructed by "cultural liberals" (Joan Tronto, "Ma, Can I Be a Feminist and Still Like Liberalism?" paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Association, Chicago, 1992, 16-25). For examples of such complacency see Galston, Liberal Purposes, 273; Glendon, Rights Talk, 58, 121, 148-55; and Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? passim.
-
Liberal Purposes
, pp. 273
-
-
Galston1
-
43
-
-
4243424012
-
-
An aspect of the alarmist tone particularly worth disputing is the blame implicitly heaped, by Galston especially, upon feminists, gay and lesbian activists and others who challenge traditional structures in the name of political and cultural recognition. Joan Tronto is appropriately scathing on the complacently mainstream "we" constructed by "cultural liberals" (Joan Tronto, "Ma, Can I Be a Feminist and Still Like Liberalism?" paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Association, Chicago, 1992, 16-25). For examples of such complacency see Galston, Liberal Purposes, 273; Glendon, Rights Talk, 58, 121, 148-55; and Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? passim.
-
Rights Talk
, vol.58-121
, pp. 148-155
-
-
Glendon1
-
44
-
-
0004174801
-
-
passim
-
An aspect of the alarmist tone particularly worth disputing is the blame implicitly heaped, by Galston especially, upon feminists, gay and lesbian activists and others who challenge traditional structures in the name of political and cultural recognition. Joan Tronto is appropriately scathing on the complacently mainstream "we" constructed by "cultural liberals" (Joan Tronto, "Ma, Can I Be a Feminist and Still Like Liberalism?" paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Association, Chicago, 1992, 16-25). For examples of such complacency see Galston, Liberal Purposes, 273; Glendon, Rights Talk, 58, 121, 148-55; and Beiner, What's the Matter with Liberalism? passim.
-
What's the Matter with Liberalism?
-
-
Beiner1
-
45
-
-
0003925898
-
-
Macedo does, in fact, acknowledge that "There are many ways of living as a liberal. Submitting to liberal justice and acting in conformity with the rules and regulations of the liberal state is, let us say, the proper extent of our enforceable political duties. A common posture of outward conformity with liberal rights and rules is enough to describe a situation of liberal coexistence, and is compatible with many attitudes, traits, and personal commitments: with mutual indifference and even hostility overlaid by a common fear of reprisal or punishment for breaches of liberal rules." He goes on to write, though, that "Such attitudes were, very likely, characteristic of the 'primitive moments' of liberalism, as liberal tolerance emerged in the seventeenth century out of religious strife and civil war. Liberal possibilities are not, however, exhausted by liberalism's primitive moments" (Macedo, Liberal Virtues, 254-55).
-
Liberal Virtues
, pp. 254-255
-
-
Macedo1
-
47
-
-
0003925898
-
-
The interpretive dimension of theories of liberal citizenship is complicated by their argument that certain goods or understandings are insufficiently shared in contemporary liberal societies. Substantive descriptions of liberal goods have thus to be derived, in part, from accounts of what it would mean to live up to the values embodied in central institutions. In Macedo's words, "Liberal ideals provide a vision of what we ought to stand for as a people, and that vision is recognizably an extension of existing practices and attitudes" (Macedo, Liberal Virtues, 254).
-
Liberal Virtues
, pp. 254
-
-
Macedo1
-
48
-
-
0003750156
-
-
Galston, Liberal Purposes, 221-24. For further lists of liberal goods and virtues - Galston offers a proliferation of lists - see ibid., 148, 178. Similarly general, and relatively uncontroversial in its vagueness, is Macedo's list of the constituents of a liberal public morality; such a morality "nurtures and draws upon the same capacities needed by persons to flourish in a pluralistic liberal society. These traits of character, or liberal virtues, include a reflective, self-critical attitude, tolerance, openness to change, self-control, a willingness to engage in dialogue with others, and a willingness to revise and shape projects in order to respect the rights of others or in response to fresh insight into one's own character and ideals" (Macedo, Liberal Virtues, 125).
-
Liberal Purposes
, pp. 221-224
-
-
Galston1
-
49
-
-
84887886081
-
-
Galston, Liberal Purposes, 221-24. For further lists of liberal goods and virtues - Galston offers a proliferation of lists - see ibid., 148, 178. Similarly general, and relatively uncontroversial in its vagueness, is Macedo's list of the constituents of a liberal public morality; such a morality "nurtures and draws upon the same capacities needed by persons to flourish in a pluralistic liberal society. These traits of character, or liberal virtues, include a reflective, self-critical attitude, tolerance, openness to change, self-control, a willingness to engage in dialogue with others, and a willingness to revise and shape projects in order to respect the rights of others or in response to fresh insight into one's own character and ideals" (Macedo, Liberal Virtues, 125).
-
Liberal Purposes
, pp. 148
-
-
-
50
-
-
0003925898
-
-
Galston, Liberal Purposes, 221-24. For further lists of liberal goods and virtues - Galston offers a proliferation of lists - see ibid., 148, 178. Similarly general, and relatively uncontroversial in its vagueness, is Macedo's list of the constituents of a liberal public morality; such a morality "nurtures and draws upon the same capacities needed by persons to flourish in a pluralistic liberal society. These traits of character, or liberal virtues, include a reflective, self-critical attitude, tolerance, openness to change, self-control, a willingness to engage in dialogue with others, and a willingness to revise and shape projects in order to respect the rights of others or in response to fresh insight into one's own character and ideals" (Macedo, Liberal Virtues, 125).
-
Liberal Virtues
, pp. 125
-
-
Macedo1
-
57
-
-
0001386035
-
-
Kymlicka and Norman gesture at this "hollowness" and "timidity" in works that would promote citizen virtues (see "Return of the Citizen," 368-69).
-
Return of the Citizen
, pp. 368-369
-
-
Kymlicka1
Norman2
-
60
-
-
0040481255
-
-
a journal in publication since
-
Galston and Glendon are joined in this prescriptive enterprise by other theorists and policy makers associated with The Responsive Community: Rights and Responsibilities, a journal in publication since 1991. This journal, representing a self-proclaimed "Communitarian Movement," usefully illustrates the legitimate concerns, as well as the worrisome propensity for blithe and sweeping proposals, typical of theories of liberal citizenship. For a further example of blithe proposals built on dubious claims see Etzioni, Spirit of Community, passim.
-
(1991)
The Responsive Community: Rights and Responsibilities
-
-
Galston1
Glendon2
-
61
-
-
0004089073
-
-
passim
-
Galston and Glendon are joined in this prescriptive enterprise by other theorists and policy makers associated with The Responsive Community: Rights and Responsibilities, a journal in publication since 1991. This journal, representing a self-proclaimed "Communitarian Movement," usefully illustrates the legitimate concerns, as well as the worrisome propensity for blithe and sweeping proposals, typical of theories of liberal citizenship. For a further example of blithe proposals built on dubious claims see Etzioni, Spirit of Community, passim.
-
Spirit of Community
-
-
Etzioni1
-
64
-
-
0041075388
-
-
note
-
Similarly placid is his proposal that public rhetoric be deployed in support of liberal values.
-
-
-
-
65
-
-
0041075389
-
-
note
-
Aspects of American public school curricula have met with challenges from religious fundamentalists, either for lacking religious "balance" or for encouraging reflexivity about divinely ordained beliefs. In these cases, those who view themselves as liberals tend to find themselves on one side of a fairly well-drawn line when it comes to issues of policy. See, for example, Mozert v. Hawkins County Bd. of Education, 827 F.2d 1058 (6th Cir. 1987); Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U.S. 205 (1971).
-
-
-
-
68
-
-
0039888302
-
-
How exactly are liberal conceptions of self, relationship and value cultivated in this particular institutional setting (for example, the family, church, the workplace, educational institutions or participatory political institutions)? Through exposure to difference? A sense of comradeship? Having a role in decision-making practices? Being treated with respect or love by particular others? Recognizing and deferring to expertise or leadership? Exercising self-reflexivity and self-control? Participating in egalitarian relationships? Nancy Rosenblum's discussion of the cultivation of democratic character is telling for projects of liberal cultivation as well: she points out that once we appreciate the range of qualities that might be deemed salient to citizen virtue, we are likely to discover that particular formative contexts foster some of these qualities while subverting others. This poses a deep problem for those advocating particular projects of cultivation. See Rosenblum, "Democratic Character and the Logic of Congruence," and also Nancy L. Rosenblum, "Civil Societies: Liberalism and the Moral Uses of Pluralism," Social Research 61 (1994), 539-62.
-
Democratic Character and the Logic of Congruence
-
-
Rosenblum1
-
69
-
-
84937309609
-
Civil societies: Liberalism and the moral uses of pluralism
-
How exactly are liberal conceptions of self, relationship and value cultivated in this particular institutional setting (for example, the family, church, the workplace, educational institutions or participatory political institutions)? Through exposure to difference? A sense of comradeship? Having a role in decision-making practices? Being treated with respect or love by particular others? Recognizing and deferring to expertise or leadership? Exercising self-reflexivity and self-control? Participating in egalitarian relationships? Nancy Rosenblum's discussion of the cultivation of democratic character is telling for projects of liberal cultivation as well: she points out that once we appreciate the range of qualities that might be deemed salient to citizen virtue, we are likely to discover that particular formative contexts foster some of these qualities while subverting others. This poses a deep problem for those advocating particular projects of cultivation. See Rosenblum, "Democratic Character and the Logic of Congruence," and also Nancy L. Rosenblum, "Civil Societies: Liberalism and the Moral Uses of Pluralism," Social Research 61 (1994), 539-62.
-
(1994)
Social Research
, vol.61
, pp. 539-562
-
-
Rosenblum, N.L.1
-
79
-
-
84937297693
-
Mothers, citizenship, and independence: A critique of pure family values
-
Iris Marion Young considers the influence of divorce and family structures on the capacities and characters of children, and suggests that there is dubious empirical evidence behind Galston's functional arguments for the two-parent heterosexual family. She points to studies that show family conflict rather than divorce to lie behind many of the ill effects that children suffer during marital breakups, a point that speaks against policies designed to make divorce more difficult. And her article as a whole shows the degree to which rhetoric linking single motherhood or family breakdown to character deficits among children is inflected by racism, sexism and other inclinations not obviously connected to or expressive of liberal virtues. See Iris Marion Young, "Mothers, Citizenship, and Independence: A Critique of Pure Family Values," Ethics 105 (1995), 535-56.
-
(1995)
Ethics
, vol.105
, pp. 535-556
-
-
Marion Young, I.1
-
85
-
-
0013544874
-
Diversity's gambit declined
-
Curtis Cook, ed., Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press
-
The following discussion of crisscrossing citizenship stories is analogous, in certain respects, to James Tully's picture of Canadian "federation stories." See James Tully, "Diversity's Gambit Declined," in Curtis Cook, ed., Constitutional Predicament: Canada after the Referendum of 1992 (Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press, 1994), 149-98.
-
(1994)
Constitutional Predicament: Canada after the Referendum of 1992
, pp. 149-198
-
-
Tully, J.1
-
86
-
-
84937295250
-
Civic education and social diversity
-
Amy Gutmann points to the contested nature of liberal virtues and their modes of cultivation, arguing that this lack of agreement is particularly acute for those approaches that argue from the public requirements of liberalism (and here she lumps together Rawls, Macedo and Galston); comprehensive or perfectionist liberalisms, on the other hand, can be more decisive on issues of civic education, given that they can appeal to the intrinsic value of such traits as individuality or autonomy. Gutmann provides a valuable discussion of how liberals can justify programmes of civic education in the face of illiberal objections; she seems far too sanguine, however, about the extent to which even such perfectionist liberal values as the dignity and worth of human beings have determinate implications for the substance of such programmes. See Amy Gutmann, "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995), 557-79. would in fact endorse Gutmann's description of democratic civic education in schools, which emphasizes deliberative skills and exposure to difference: this says more about my own variety of liberal democratic partisanship, however, than about what liberal goods and virtues "require." This latter point comes into relief if we compare Amy Gutmann's "Undemocratic Education" with William Galston's "Civic Education in a Liberal State," both in Nancy L. Rosenblum, ed., Liberalism and the Moral Life (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989), 71-88 and 89-101, respectively.
-
(1995)
Ethics
, vol.105
, pp. 557-579
-
-
Gutmann, A.1
-
87
-
-
0002805552
-
-
Amy Gutmann points to the contested nature of liberal virtues and their modes of cultivation, arguing that this lack of agreement is particularly acute for those approaches that argue from the public requirements of liberalism (and here she lumps together Rawls, Macedo and Galston); comprehensive or perfectionist liberalisms, on the other hand, can be more decisive on issues of civic education, given that they can appeal to the intrinsic value of such traits as individuality or autonomy. Gutmann provides a valuable discussion of how liberals can justify programmes of civic education in the face of illiberal objections; she seems far too sanguine, however, about the extent to which even such perfectionist liberal values as the dignity and worth of human beings have determinate implications for the substance of such programmes. See Amy Gutmann, "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995), 557-79. would in fact endorse Gutmann's description of democratic civic education in schools, which emphasizes deliberative skills and exposure to difference: this says more about my own variety of liberal democratic partisanship, however, than about what liberal goods and virtues "require." This latter point comes into relief if we compare Amy Gutmann's "Undemocratic Education" with William Galston's "Civic Education in a Liberal State," both in Nancy L. Rosenblum, ed., Liberalism and the Moral Life (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989), 71-88 and 89-101, respectively.
-
Undemocratic Education
-
-
Gutmann's, A.1
-
88
-
-
0041019684
-
-
Amy Gutmann points to the contested nature of liberal virtues and their modes of cultivation, arguing that this lack of agreement is particularly acute for those approaches that argue from the public requirements of liberalism (and here she lumps together Rawls, Macedo and Galston); comprehensive or perfectionist liberalisms, on the other hand, can be more decisive on issues of civic education, given that they can appeal to the intrinsic value of such traits as individuality or autonomy. Gutmann provides a valuable discussion of how liberals can justify programmes of civic education in the face of illiberal objections; she seems far too sanguine, however, about the extent to which even such perfectionist liberal values as the dignity and worth of human beings have determinate implications for the substance of such programmes. See Amy Gutmann, "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995), 557-79. would in fact endorse Gutmann's description of democratic civic education in schools, which emphasizes deliberative skills and exposure to difference: this says more about my own variety of liberal democratic partisanship, however, than about what liberal goods and virtues "require." This latter point comes into relief if we compare Amy Gutmann's "Undemocratic Education" with William Galston's "Civic Education in a Liberal State," both in Nancy L. Rosenblum, ed., Liberalism and the Moral Life (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989), 71-88 and 89-101, respectively.
-
Civic Education in a Liberal State
-
-
Galston's, W.1
-
89
-
-
0004283938
-
-
Cambridge: Harvard University Press
-
Amy Gutmann points to the contested nature of liberal virtues and their modes of cultivation, arguing that this lack of agreement is particularly acute for those approaches that argue from the public requirements of liberalism (and here she lumps together Rawls, Macedo and Galston); comprehensive or perfectionist liberalisms, on the other hand, can be more decisive on issues of civic education, given that they can appeal to the intrinsic value of such traits as individuality or autonomy. Gutmann provides a valuable discussion of how liberals can justify programmes of civic education in the face of illiberal objections; she seems far too sanguine, however, about the extent to which even such perfectionist liberal values as the dignity and worth of human beings have determinate implications for the substance of such programmes. See Amy Gutmann, "Civic Education and Social Diversity," Ethics 105 (1995), 557-79. would in fact endorse Gutmann's description of democratic civic education in schools, which emphasizes deliberative skills and exposure to difference: this says more about my own variety of liberal democratic partisanship, however, than about what liberal goods and virtues "require." This latter point comes into relief if we compare Amy Gutmann's "Undemocratic Education" with William Galston's "Civic Education in a Liberal State," both in Nancy L. Rosenblum, ed., Liberalism and the Moral Life (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989), 71-88 and 89-101, respectively.
-
(1989)
Liberalism and the Moral Life
, pp. 71-88
-
-
Rosenblum, N.L.1
-
90
-
-
42949148252
-
Incompletely theorized agreements
-
Cass R. Sunstein, "Incompletely Theorized Agreements," Harvard Law Review 108 (1995), 1733-72. I use the expression more loosely than Sunstein, who focuses primarily on a particular mode of legal adjudication.
-
(1995)
Harvard Law Review
, vol.108
, pp. 1733-1772
-
-
Sunstein, C.R.1
-
91
-
-
0039296321
-
-
note
-
When the language of liberal virtues functions in this way, it works only among those who buy into the pieties in question; as noted earlier, for example, there are religious groups in the US who staunchly resist the idea that school children should be exposed to diverse ways of life for the sake of inculcating tolerance. Arguing from shared liberal values is not a route to consensus, but at best a way of hammering out majoritarian agreements in contested areas of public policy.
-
-
-
|