메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 29, Issue 4, 1996, Pages 751-777

Contending interpretations of Bentham's utilitarianism

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0030355162     PISSN: 00084239     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s0008423900014463     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (19)

References (177)
  • 1
    • 0004320376 scopus 로고
    • trans. by M. Morris 1928; Clifton, N.J.: Augustus M. Kelley
    • Though the terms of discussion have altered considerably in the decades since, the debate can be said to have originated in Elie Halévy's magisterial study, The Growth of Philosophic Radicalism [La Formation du radicalisme philosophique, 1901-4], trans. by M. Morris (1928; Clifton, N.J.: Augustus M. Kelley, 1972), esp. 17-18. Halévy outlined a tension in Bentham's utilitarianism between "the principle of the artificial identification of interests" and "the principle of the natural identity of interests."
    • (1901) The Growth of Philosophic Radicalism la Formation du Radicalisme Philosophique , pp. 17-18
    • Halévy's, E.1
  • 2
    • 0009314526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toronto: University of Toronto Press
    • Douglas G. Long, Bentham on Liberty: Jeremy Bentham's Idea of Liberty in Relation to His Utilitarianism (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1977); Douglas G. Long, "Bentham on Property," in Thomas M. Flanagan and Anthony Parel, eds., Theories of Property: Aristotle to the Present (Waterloo: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 1979), 221-54; J. R. Dinwiddy, "The Classical Economists and the Utilitarians," in E. K. Bramsted and K. J. Melhuish, eds., Western Liberalism: A History in Documents from Locke to Croce (London: Longmans, 1978), 12-25; L. J. Hume, Bentham and Bureaucracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Charles F. Bahmueller, The National Charity Company: Jeremy Bentham's Silent Revolution (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1981).
    • (1977) Bentham on Liberty: Jeremy Bentham's Idea of Liberty in Relation to His Utilitarianism
    • Long, D.G.1
  • 3
    • 0040353089 scopus 로고
    • Bentham on property
    • Thomas M. Flanagan and Anthony Parel, eds., Waterloo: Wilfrid Laurier University Press
    • Douglas G. Long, Bentham on Liberty: Jeremy Bentham's Idea of Liberty in Relation to His Utilitarianism (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1977); Douglas G. Long, "Bentham on Property," in Thomas M. Flanagan and Anthony Parel, eds., Theories of Property: Aristotle to the Present (Waterloo: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 1979), 221-54; J. R. Dinwiddy, "The Classical Economists and the Utilitarians," in E. K. Bramsted and K. J. Melhuish, eds., Western Liberalism: A History in Documents from Locke to Croce (London: Longmans, 1978), 12-25; L. J. Hume, Bentham and Bureaucracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Charles F. Bahmueller, The National Charity Company: Jeremy Bentham's Silent Revolution (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1981).
    • (1979) Theories of Property: Aristotle to the Present , pp. 221-254
    • Long, D.G.1
  • 4
    • 0039168535 scopus 로고
    • The classical economists and the utilitarians
    • E. K. Bramsted and K. J. Melhuish, eds., London: Longmans
    • Douglas G. Long, Bentham on Liberty: Jeremy Bentham's Idea of Liberty in Relation to His Utilitarianism (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1977); Douglas G. Long, "Bentham on Property," in Thomas M. Flanagan and Anthony Parel, eds., Theories of Property: Aristotle to the Present (Waterloo: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 1979), 221-54; J. R. Dinwiddy, "The Classical Economists and the Utilitarians," in E. K. Bramsted and K. J. Melhuish, eds., Western Liberalism: A History in Documents from Locke to Croce (London: Longmans, 1978), 12-25; L. J. Hume, Bentham and Bureaucracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Charles F. Bahmueller, The National Charity Company: Jeremy Bentham's Silent Revolution (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1981).
    • (1978) Western Liberalism: A History in Documents from Locke to Croce , pp. 12-25
    • Dinwiddy, J.R.1
  • 5
    • 0004187524 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Douglas G. Long, Bentham on Liberty: Jeremy Bentham's Idea of Liberty in Relation to His Utilitarianism (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1977); Douglas G. Long, "Bentham on Property," in Thomas M. Flanagan and Anthony Parel, eds., Theories of Property: Aristotle to the Present (Waterloo: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 1979), 221-54; J. R. Dinwiddy, "The Classical Economists and the Utilitarians," in E. K. Bramsted and K. J. Melhuish, eds., Western Liberalism: A History in Documents from Locke to Croce (London: Longmans, 1978), 12-25; L. J. Hume, Bentham and Bureaucracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Charles F. Bahmueller, The National Charity Company: Jeremy Bentham's Silent Revolution (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1981).
    • (1981) Bentham and Bureaucracy
    • Hume, L.J.1
  • 6
    • 85201611102 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • Douglas G. Long, Bentham on Liberty: Jeremy Bentham's Idea of Liberty in Relation to His Utilitarianism (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1977); Douglas G. Long, "Bentham on Property," in Thomas M. Flanagan and Anthony Parel, eds., Theories of Property: Aristotle to the Present (Waterloo: Wilfrid Laurier University Press, 1979), 221-54; J. R. Dinwiddy, "The Classical Economists and the Utilitarians," in E. K. Bramsted and K. J. Melhuish, eds., Western Liberalism: A History in Documents from Locke to Croce (London: Longmans, 1978), 12-25; L. J. Hume, Bentham and Bureaucracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Charles F. Bahmueller, The National Charity Company: Jeremy Bentham's Silent Revolution (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1981).
    • (1981) The National Charity Company: Jeremy Bentham's Silent Revolution
    • Bahmueller, C.F.1
  • 7
    • 0009386564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bentham MSS, UC 100/170 (ca. 1776), quoted in Long, Bentham on Liberty, 173.
    • Bentham on Liberty , pp. 173
    • Long1
  • 8
    • 0009314526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • UC 69/44 (ca. 1774), cited in ibid.; see also Dinwiddy, "The Classical Economists," 21.
    • Bentham on Liberty
  • 10
    • 0003543966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Paul Crook discerned "authoritarianism" in Bentham's proposals for the "powerful administrative departments" described in the Constitutional Code, "anticipating the positive state of the twentieth century" (American Democracy in English Politics 1815-1850 [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1965], 19-20); Bhikhu Parekh highlights the authoritarian character of Bentham's theory of law in "Bentham's Theory of Equality," Political Studies 18 (1970), 478-95; and John Riddoch Porter refers to the "dogmatically authoritarian" character of Bentham's pauper plan in Society and Pauperism: English Ideas on Poor Relief, 1795-1834 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1969), 109.
    • Constitutional Code
    • Crook, D.P.1
  • 11
    • 0039761058 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • David Paul Crook discerned "authoritarianism" in Bentham's proposals for the "powerful administrative departments" described in the Constitutional Code, "anticipating the positive state of the twentieth century" (American Democracy in English Politics 1815-1850 [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1965], 19-20); Bhikhu Parekh highlights the authoritarian character of Bentham's theory of law in "Bentham's Theory of Equality," Political Studies 18 (1970), 478-95; and John Riddoch Porter refers to the "dogmatically authoritarian" character of Bentham's pauper plan in Society and Pauperism: English Ideas on Poor Relief, 1795-1834 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1969), 109.
    • (1965) American Democracy in English Politics 1815-1850 , pp. 19-20
  • 12
    • 0040353083 scopus 로고
    • "Bentham's Theory of Equality,"
    • David Paul Crook discerned "authoritarianism" in Bentham's proposals for the "powerful administrative departments" described in the Constitutional Code, "anticipating the positive state of the twentieth century" (American Democracy in English Politics 1815-1850 [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1965], 19-20); Bhikhu Parekh highlights the authoritarian character of Bentham's theory of law in "Bentham's Theory of Equality," Political Studies 18 (1970), 478-95; and John Riddoch Porter refers to the "dogmatically authoritarian" character of Bentham's pauper plan in Society and Pauperism: English Ideas on Poor Relief, 1795-1834 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1969), 109.
    • (1970) Political Studies , vol.18 , pp. 478-495
    • Parekh, B.1
  • 13
    • 0039168520 scopus 로고
    • Toronto: University of Toronto Press
    • David Paul Crook discerned "authoritarianism" in Bentham's proposals for the "powerful administrative departments" described in the Constitutional Code, "anticipating the positive state of the twentieth century" (American Democracy in English Politics 1815-1850 [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1965], 19-20); Bhikhu Parekh highlights the authoritarian character of Bentham's theory of law in "Bentham's Theory of Equality," Political Studies 18 (1970), 478-95; and John Riddoch Porter refers to the "dogmatically authoritarian" character of Bentham's pauper plan in Society and Pauperism: English Ideas on Poor Relief, 1795-1834 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1969), 109.
    • (1969) Society and Pauperism: English Ideas on Poor Relief, 1795-1834 , pp. 109
    • Riddoch Porter, J.1
  • 14
    • 0039761054 scopus 로고
    • Jeremy bentham's democratic despotism
    • R. D. Collison Black, ed., London: Macmillan
    • Pedro Schwartz, "Jeremy Bentham's Democratic Despotism," in R. D. Collison Black, ed., Ideas in Economics (London: Macmillan, 1986), 74-103.
    • (1986) Ideas in Economics , pp. 74-103
    • Schwartz, P.1
  • 15
    • 0004040154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bahmueller, The National Charity Company; the totalitarian character of Bentham's "panopticism" has also been suggested by Gertrude Himmelfarb, "The Haunted House of Jeremy Bentham," in Victorian Minds (New York: Knopf, 1968), chap. 2; and D. J. Manning, The Mind of Jeremy Bentham (London: Longmans, 1968).
    • The National Charity Company
    • Bahmueller1
  • 16
    • 0011463138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The haunted house of Jeremy Bentham
    • New York: Knopf, chap. 2
    • Bahmueller, The National Charity Company; the totalitarian character of Bentham's "panopticism" has also been suggested by Gertrude Himmelfarb, "The Haunted House of Jeremy Bentham," in Victorian Minds (New York: Knopf, 1968), chap. 2; and D. J. Manning, The Mind of Jeremy Bentham (London: Longmans, 1968).
    • (1968) Victorian Minds
    • Himmelfarb, G.1
  • 17
    • 0039168534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London: Longmans
    • Bahmueller, The National Charity Company; the totalitarian character of Bentham's "panopticism" has also been suggested by Gertrude Himmelfarb, "The Haunted House of Jeremy Bentham," in Victorian Minds (New York: Knopf, 1968), chap. 2; and D. J. Manning, The Mind of Jeremy Bentham (London: Longmans, 1968).
    • The Mind of Jeremy Bentham , vol.1968
    • Manning, D.J.1
  • 18
    • 0040947089 scopus 로고
    • 3 vols.; London: Methuen
    • W. H. Greenleaf, The British Political Tradition (3 vols.; London: Methuen, 1983-1987), Vol. 1, 248. Mary Mack describes Bentham's political thought as "equalitarian state socialism," in Jeremy Bentham: An Odyssey of Ideas, 1748-1792 (London: Heinemann, 1962), 299.
    • (1983) The British Political Tradition , vol.1 , pp. 248
    • Greenleaf, W.H.1
  • 19
    • 0038634889 scopus 로고
    • London: Heinemann
    • W. H. Greenleaf, The British Political Tradition (3 vols.; London: Methuen, 1983-1987), Vol. 1, 248. Mary Mack describes Bentham's political thought as "equalitarian state socialism," in Jeremy Bentham: An Odyssey of Ideas, 1748-1792 (London: Heinemann, 1962), 299.
    • (1962) Jeremy Bentham: An Odyssey of Ideas, 1748-1792 , pp. 299
    • Mack, M.1
  • 21
    • 0040947088 scopus 로고
    • 3 vols.; Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • See F. A. Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty: A New Statement of the Liberal Principles of Justice and Political Economy (3 vols.; Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973-79), Vol. 1, 22, 74, 95; F. A. Hayek, "The Errors of Constructivism," in New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the History of Ideas (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), 3-22; and Douglas G. Long, "Science and Secularization in Hume, Smith and Bentham," in James E. Crimmins, ed., Religion, Secularization and Political Thought: Thomas Hobbes to J. S. Mill (London: Routledge, 1990), 90-110.
    • (1973) Law, Legislation and Liberty: A New Statement of the Liberal Principles of Justice and Political Economy , vol.1 , pp. 22
    • Hayek, F.A.1
  • 22
    • 0039761053 scopus 로고
    • The errors of constructivism
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • See F. A. Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty: A New Statement of the Liberal Principles of Justice and Political Economy (3 vols.; Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973-79), Vol. 1, 22, 74, 95; F. A. Hayek, "The Errors of Constructivism," in New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the History of Ideas (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), 3-22; and Douglas G. Long, "Science and Secularization in Hume, Smith and Bentham," in James E. Crimmins, ed., Religion, Secularization and Political Thought: Thomas Hobbes to J. S. Mill (London: Routledge, 1990), 90-110.
    • (1978) New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the History of Ideas , pp. 3-22
    • Hayek, F.A.1
  • 23
    • 84972126200 scopus 로고
    • Science and secularization in Hume, Smith and Bentham
    • James E. Crimmins, ed., London: Routledge
    • See F. A. Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty: A New Statement of the Liberal Principles of Justice and Political Economy (3 vols.; Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973-79), Vol. 1, 22, 74, 95; F. A. Hayek, "The Errors of Constructivism," in New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the History of Ideas (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), 3-22; and Douglas G. Long, "Science and Secularization in Hume, Smith and Bentham," in James E. Crimmins, ed., Religion, Secularization and Political Thought: Thomas Hobbes to J. S. Mill (London: Routledge, 1990), 90-110.
    • (1990) Religion, Secularization and Political Thought: Thomas Hobbes to J. S. Mill , pp. 90-110
    • Long, D.G.1
  • 26
    • 0040353105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In many respects, the descriptive terms employed by both schools of interpretation are anachronistic, including the terms "liberal" and "liberalism." The epithet "liberal" was used of a political movement for the first time in 1810 or 1811 when it was adopted by the Spanish party of Liberales - anticlerical members of the Cortes and their supporters who were in favour of liberty of the press (Greenleaf, The British Political Tradition, Vol. 2, 20). As Rosen tells us, the term "liberalism" gained ideological purchase in England only in the second quarter of the nineteenth century; see F. Rosen, Bentham, Byron and Greece: Constitutionalism, Nationalism, and Early Liberal Political Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 5.
    • The British Political Tradition , vol.2 , pp. 20
    • Greenleaf1
  • 27
    • 84958655617 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • In many respects, the descriptive terms employed by both schools of interpretation are anachronistic, including the terms "liberal" and "liberalism." The epithet "liberal" was used of a political movement for the first time in 1810 or 1811 when it was adopted by the Spanish party of Liberales - anticlerical members of the Cortes and their supporters who were in favour of liberty of the press (Greenleaf, The British Political Tradition, Vol. 2, 20). As Rosen tells us, the term "liberalism" gained ideological purchase in England only in the second quarter of the nineteenth century; see F. Rosen, Bentham, Byron and Greece: Constitutionalism, Nationalism, and Early Liberal Political Thought (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 5.
    • (1992) Bentham, Byron and Greece: Constitutionalism, Nationalism, and Early Liberal Political Thought , pp. 5
    • Rosen, F.1
  • 28
    • 0004164867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • F. Rosen, Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy: A Study of the Constitutional Code (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983); F. Rosen, "The Origin of Liberal Utilitarianism: Jeremy Bentham and Liberty," in Richard Bellamy, ed., Victorian Liberalism: Nineteenth-Century Political Thought and Practice (London: Routledge, 1990), chap. 4; Lea Campos Boralevi, Bentham and the Oppressed (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1984); P. J. Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: Jeremy Bentham and the Civil Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990); Allison Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness in Bentham's Political Thought (New York: Garland, 1991); and Gerald J. Postema, Bentham and the Common Law Tradition (1986; corrected ed.; New York: Clarendon Press, 1989).
    • (1983) Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy: A Study of the Constitutional Code
    • Rosen, F.1
  • 29
    • 0009313178 scopus 로고
    • The origin of liberal utilitarianism: Jeremy Bentham and liberty
    • Richard Bellamy, ed., London: Routledge, chap. 4
    • F. Rosen, Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy: A Study of the Constitutional Code (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983); F. Rosen, "The Origin of Liberal Utilitarianism: Jeremy Bentham and Liberty," in Richard Bellamy, ed., Victorian Liberalism: Nineteenth-Century Political Thought and Practice (London: Routledge, 1990), chap. 4; Lea Campos Boralevi, Bentham and the Oppressed (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1984); P. J. Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: Jeremy Bentham and the Civil Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990); Allison Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness in Bentham's Political Thought (New York: Garland, 1991); and Gerald J. Postema, Bentham and the Common Law Tradition (1986; corrected ed.; New York: Clarendon Press, 1989).
    • (1990) Victorian Liberalism: Nineteenth-Century Political Thought and Practice
    • Rosen, F.1
  • 30
    • 0040353104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1984)
    • F. Rosen, Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy: A Study of the Constitutional Code (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983); F. Rosen, "The Origin of Liberal Utilitarianism: Jeremy Bentham and Liberty," in Richard Bellamy, ed., Victorian Liberalism: Nineteenth-Century Political Thought and Practice (London: Routledge, 1990), chap. 4; Lea Campos Boralevi, Bentham and the Oppressed (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1984); P. J. Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: Jeremy Bentham and the Civil Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990); Allison Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness in Bentham's Political Thought (New York: Garland, 1991); and Gerald J. Postema, Bentham and the Common Law Tradition (1986; corrected ed.; New York: Clarendon Press, 1989).
    • Bentham and the Oppressed
    • Campos Boralevi, L.1
  • 31
    • 0039168509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • F. Rosen, Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy: A Study of the Constitutional Code (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983); F. Rosen, "The Origin of Liberal Utilitarianism: Jeremy Bentham and Liberty," in Richard Bellamy, ed., Victorian Liberalism: Nineteenth-Century Political Thought and Practice (London: Routledge, 1990), chap. 4; Lea Campos Boralevi, Bentham and the Oppressed (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1984); P. J. Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: Jeremy Bentham and the Civil Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990); Allison Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness in Bentham's Political Thought (New York: Garland, 1991); and Gerald J. Postema, Bentham and the Common Law Tradition (1986; corrected ed.; New York: Clarendon Press, 1989).
    • (1990) Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: Jeremy Bentham and the Civil Law
    • Kelly, P.J.1
  • 32
    • 0040353093 scopus 로고
    • New York: Garland
    • F. Rosen, Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy: A Study of the Constitutional Code (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983); F. Rosen, "The Origin of Liberal Utilitarianism: Jeremy Bentham and Liberty," in Richard Bellamy, ed., Victorian Liberalism: Nineteenth-Century Political Thought and Practice (London: Routledge, 1990), chap. 4; Lea Campos Boralevi, Bentham and the Oppressed (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1984); P. J. Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: Jeremy Bentham and the Civil Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990); Allison Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness in Bentham's Political Thought (New York: Garland, 1991); and Gerald J. Postema, Bentham and the Common Law Tradition (1986; corrected ed.; New York: Clarendon Press, 1989).
    • (1991) The Theme of Acquisitiveness in Bentham's Political Thought
    • Dube, A.1
  • 33
    • 0003883951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • corrected ed.; New York: Clarendon Press
    • F. Rosen, Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy: A Study of the Constitutional Code (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983); F. Rosen, "The Origin of Liberal Utilitarianism: Jeremy Bentham and Liberty," in Richard Bellamy, ed., Victorian Liberalism: Nineteenth-Century Political Thought and Practice (London: Routledge, 1990), chap. 4; Lea Campos Boralevi, Bentham and the Oppressed (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1984); P. J. Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: Jeremy Bentham and the Civil Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990); Allison Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness in Bentham's Political Thought (New York: Garland, 1991); and Gerald J. Postema, Bentham and the Common Law Tradition (1986; corrected ed.; New York: Clarendon Press, 1989).
    • (1986) Bentham and the Common Law Tradition
    • Postema, G.J.1
  • 34
    • 0040353092 scopus 로고
    • Bentham to John Lind (March 27-28 to April 1, 1776), 1752-1776, 2 vols.; London: Athlone Press
    • Bentham to John Lind (March 27-28 to April 1, 1776), in The Correspondence of Jeremy Bentham, Vol. 1: 1752-1776, ed. by T. L. S. Sprigge (2 vols.; London: Athlone Press, 1968), 311. The seeming contradiction with the quotation given above (from about the same date) disappears when it is considered that Bentham's focus here is on the "definition of liberty," although individualist interpreters do not always appreciate the fact (see Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 311).
    • (1968) The Correspondence of Jeremy Bentham , vol.1 , pp. 311
    • Sprigge, T.L.S.1
  • 35
    • 0039761062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bentham to John Lind (March 27-28 to April 1, 1776), in The Correspondence of Jeremy Bentham, Vol. 1: 1752-1776, ed. by T. L. S. Sprigge (2 vols.; London: Athlone Press, 1968), 311. The seeming contradiction with the quotation given above (from about the same date) disappears when it is considered that Bentham's focus here is on the "definition of liberty," although individualist interpreters do not always appreciate the fact (see Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 311).
    • The Theme of Acquisitiveness , pp. 311
    • Dube1
  • 37
    • 0009407749 scopus 로고
    • Elie Halévy and Bentham's authoritarian liberalism
    • F. Rosen, "Elie Halévy and Bentham's Authoritarian Liberalism," Enlightenment and Dissent 6 (1987), 69.
    • (1987) Enlightenment and Dissent , vol.6 , pp. 69
    • Rosen, F.1
  • 38
    • 0039761063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rosen, "The Origin of Liberal Utilitarianism," 60, 62. See also Rosen, Bentham, Byron and Greece, 4, 33-37, and for a discussion of "constitutional liberty" as "security" in Bentham's thought see the introduction more generally and chap. 2 of this work.
    • The Origin of Liberal Utilitarianism , pp. 60
    • Rosen1
  • 39
    • 0040353103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rosen, "The Origin of Liberal Utilitarianism," 60, 62. See also Rosen, Bentham, Byron and Greece, 4, 33-37, and for a discussion of "constitutional liberty" as "security" in Bentham's thought see the introduction more generally and chap. 2 of this work.
    • Bentham, Byron and Greece , vol.4 , pp. 33-37
    • Rosen1
  • 40
    • 0002093359 scopus 로고
    • Meaning and understanding in the history of ideas
    • Quentin Skinner, "Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas," History and Theory 8 (1969), 3-53.
    • (1969) History and Theory , vol.8 , pp. 3-53
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 41
    • 0011413495 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Naturally, not all commentators accept that Bentham's thought is as systematic as he supposed. For example, in the context of Bentham's panopticon scheme, Letwin points to the adoption of means which lead to ends contrary to those desired, see Shirley Robin Letwin, The Pursuit of Certainty: David Hume, Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill, Beatrice Webb (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965), 188; and both W. H. Coatcs, "Benthamism, Laissezfaire and Collectivism," Journal of the History of Ideas 9 (1950), 357-63, and Greenleaf, The British Political Tradition, Vol. 1, note the conflicting "libertarian" and "collectivist" tendencies in Bentham's thought.
    • (1965) The Pursuit of Certainty: David Hume, Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill, Beatrice Webb , pp. 188
    • Letwin, S.R.1
  • 42
    • 0040353087 scopus 로고
    • Benthamism, laissezfaire and collectivism
    • Naturally, not all commentators accept that Bentham's thought is as systematic as he supposed. For example, in the context of Bentham's panopticon scheme, Letwin points to the adoption of means which lead to ends contrary to those desired, see Shirley Robin Letwin, The Pursuit of Certainty: David Hume, Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill, Beatrice Webb (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965), 188; and both W. H. Coatcs, "Benthamism, Laissezfaire and Collectivism," Journal of the History of Ideas 9 (1950), 357-63, and Greenleaf, The British Political Tradition, Vol. 1, note the conflicting "libertarian" and "collectivist" tendencies in Bentham's thought.
    • (1950) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.9 , pp. 357-363
    • Coatcs, W.H.1
  • 43
    • 0039761064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Naturally, not all commentators accept that Bentham's thought is as systematic as he supposed. For example, in the context of Bentham's panopticon scheme, Letwin points to the adoption of means which lead to ends contrary to those desired, see Shirley Robin Letwin, The Pursuit of Certainty: David Hume, Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill, Beatrice Webb (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965), 188; and both W. H. Coatcs, "Benthamism, Laissezfaire and Collectivism," Journal of the History of Ideas 9 (1950), 357-63, and Greenleaf, The British Political Tradition, Vol. 1, note the conflicting "libertarian" and "collectivist" tendencies in Bentham's thought.
    • The British Political Tradition , vol.1
    • Greenleaf1
  • 45
    • 0011246859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dinwiddy, "The Classical Economists," 20; see also J. R. Dinwiddy, "Bentham on Private Ethics and the Principle of Utility," in Radicalism and Reform in Britain, 1780-1850 (London: Hambledon Press, 1992), 315-38.
    • The Classical Economists , pp. 20
    • Dinwiddy1
  • 46
    • 0039761059 scopus 로고
    • Bentham on private ethics and the principle of utility
    • London: Hambledon Press
    • Dinwiddy, "The Classical Economists," 20; see also J. R. Dinwiddy, "Bentham on Private Ethics and the Principle of Utility," in Radicalism and Reform in Britain, 1780-1850 (London: Hambledon Press, 1992), 315-38.
    • (1992) Radicalism and Reform in Britain, 1780-1850 , pp. 315-338
    • Dinwiddy, J.R.1
  • 48
    • 0011246859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 21. Dinwiddy's references are to Bentham's Principles of Penal Law and The Book of Fallacies, in The Works of Jeremy Bentham, Published under the Superintendence of his Executor, John Bowring (henceforth Works) (11 vols.; Edinburgh: William Tait, 1838-43), Vol. 1, 568, and Vol. 2, 424.
    • The Classical Economists , pp. 21
  • 50
    • 0011246859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dinwiddy, "The Classical Economists," 21, and Jeremy Bentham, Panopticon: Or, The Inspection House (1791), in Works, Vol. 4, 64 (emphasis in original).
    • The Classical Economists , pp. 21
    • Dinwiddy1
  • 51
    • 0348103817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Panopticon: Or, the inspection house
    • emphasis in original
    • Dinwiddy, "The Classical Economists," 21, and Jeremy Bentham, Panopticon: Or, The Inspection House (1791), in Works, Vol. 4, 64 (emphasis in original).
    • (1791) Works , vol.4 , pp. 64
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 52
    • 0040126586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Bentham's panopticon - a penitentiary for "grinding rogues honest and idle men industrious" (Works, Vol. 4, 342), see Himmelfarb, "The Haunted House of Jeremy Bentham," chap. 2; L. J. Hume, "Bentham's Panopticon: An Administrative History," in two parts, Historical Studies 15 and 16 (1973-74), 703-21 and 36-54; and Janet Semple, Bentham's Prison: A Study of the Panopticon Penitentiary (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993). For critical accounts of Bentham's poor law proposals see Gertrude Himmelfarb, "Bentham's Utopia: The National Charity Company," The Journal of British Studies 10 (1970), 80-125, and Bahmueller, The National Charity Company.
    • Works , vol.4 , pp. 342
    • Bentham1
  • 53
    • 0011463138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 2
    • On Bentham's panopticon - a penitentiary for "grinding rogues honest and idle men industrious" (Works, Vol. 4, 342), see Himmelfarb, "The Haunted House of Jeremy Bentham," chap. 2; L. J. Hume, "Bentham's Panopticon: An Administrative History," in two parts, Historical Studies 15 and 16 (1973-74), 703-21 and 36-54; and Janet Semple, Bentham's Prison: A Study of the Panopticon Penitentiary (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993). For critical accounts of Bentham's poor law proposals see Gertrude Himmelfarb, "Bentham's Utopia: The National Charity Company," The Journal of British Studies 10 (1970), 80-125, and Bahmueller, The National Charity Company.
    • The Haunted House of Jeremy Bentham
    • Himmelfarb1
  • 54
    • 0040947076 scopus 로고
    • Bentham's panopticon: An administrative history
    • On Bentham's panopticon - a penitentiary for "grinding rogues honest and idle men industrious" (Works, Vol. 4, 342), see Himmelfarb, "The Haunted House of Jeremy Bentham," chap. 2; L. J. Hume, "Bentham's Panopticon: An Administrative History," in two parts, Historical Studies 15 and 16 (1973-74), 703-21 and 36-54; and Janet Semple, Bentham's Prison: A Study of the Panopticon Penitentiary (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993). For critical accounts of Bentham's poor law proposals see Gertrude Himmelfarb, "Bentham's Utopia: The National Charity Company," The Journal of British Studies 10 (1970), 80-125, and Bahmueller, The National Charity Company.
    • (1973) Historical Studies , vol.15-16 , pp. 703-721
    • Hume, L.J.1
  • 55
    • 0003708805 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • On Bentham's panopticon - a penitentiary for "grinding rogues honest and idle men industrious" (Works, Vol. 4, 342), see Himmelfarb, "The Haunted House of Jeremy Bentham," chap. 2; L. J. Hume, "Bentham's Panopticon: An Administrative History," in two parts, Historical Studies 15 and 16 (1973-74), 703-21 and 36-54; and Janet Semple, Bentham's Prison: A Study of the Panopticon Penitentiary (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993). For critical accounts of Bentham's poor law proposals see Gertrude Himmelfarb, "Bentham's Utopia: The National Charity Company," The Journal of British Studies 10 (1970), 80-125, and Bahmueller, The National Charity Company.
    • (1993) Bentham's Prison: A Study of the Panopticon Penitentiary
    • Semple, J.1
  • 56
    • 0011513074 scopus 로고
    • Bentham's utopia: The national charity company
    • On Bentham's panopticon - a penitentiary for "grinding rogues honest and idle men industrious" (Works, Vol. 4, 342), see Himmelfarb, "The Haunted House of Jeremy Bentham," chap. 2; L. J. Hume, "Bentham's Panopticon: An Administrative History," in two parts, Historical Studies 15 and 16 (1973-74), 703-21 and 36-54; and Janet Semple, Bentham's Prison: A Study of the Panopticon Penitentiary (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993). For critical accounts of Bentham's poor law proposals see Gertrude Himmelfarb, "Bentham's Utopia: The National Charity Company," The Journal of British Studies 10 (1970), 80-125, and Bahmueller, The National Charity Company.
    • (1970) The Journal of British Studies , vol.10 , pp. 80-125
    • Himmelfarb, G.1
  • 57
    • 0004040154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Bentham's panopticon - a penitentiary for "grinding rogues honest and idle men industrious" (Works, Vol. 4, 342), see Himmelfarb, "The Haunted House of Jeremy Bentham," chap. 2; L. J. Hume, "Bentham's Panopticon: An Administrative History," in two parts, Historical Studies 15 and 16 (1973-74), 703-21 and 36-54; and Janet Semple, Bentham's Prison: A Study of the Panopticon Penitentiary (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993). For critical accounts of Bentham's poor law proposals see Gertrude Himmelfarb, "Bentham's Utopia: The National Charity Company," The Journal of British Studies 10 (1970), 80-125, and Bahmueller, The National Charity Company.
    • The National Charity Company
    • Bahmueller1
  • 59
    • 0040353101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • UC 152b/332-333 (1797), quoted in Long, "Bentham on Property," 244; see also Bahmueller, The National Charity Company.
    • Bentham on Property , pp. 244
    • Long1
  • 61
    • 0040353100 scopus 로고
    • ed. by J. H. Burns and H. L. A. Hart London: Athlone Press, 1970
    • Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, ed. by J. H. Burns and H. L. A. Hart (1789; London: Athlone Press, 1970), 290, and Jeremy Bentham, Method and Leading Features of an Institute of Political Economy, in Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings: Critical Edition Based on His Printed Works and Unprinted Manuscripts, ed. by W. Stark (3 vols.; London: Allen and Unwin, 1952-1954), Vol. 3, 333. See Allison Dube, "Hayek on Bentham," Utilitas 2 (1990), 12, and Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 345.
    • (1789) An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation , pp. 290
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 62
    • 0039168519 scopus 로고
    • Method and leading features of an institute of political economy
    • ed. by W. Stark 3 vols.; London: Allen and Unwin
    • Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, ed. by J. H. Burns and H. L. A. Hart (1789; London: Athlone Press, 1970), 290, and Jeremy Bentham, Method and Leading Features of an Institute of Political Economy, in Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings: Critical Edition Based on His Printed Works and Unprinted Manuscripts, ed. by W. Stark (3 vols.; London: Allen and Unwin, 1952-1954), Vol. 3, 333. See Allison Dube, "Hayek on Bentham," Utilitas 2 (1990), 12, and Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 345.
    • (1952) Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings: Critical Edition Based on His Printed Works and Unprinted Manuscripts , vol.3 , pp. 333
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 63
    • 84971761852 scopus 로고
    • Hayek on bentham
    • Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, ed. by J. H. Burns and H. L. A. Hart (1789; London: Athlone Press, 1970), 290, and Jeremy Bentham, Method and Leading Features of an Institute of Political Economy, in Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings: Critical Edition Based on His Printed Works and Unprinted Manuscripts, ed. by W. Stark (3 vols.; London: Allen and Unwin, 1952-1954), Vol. 3, 333. See Allison Dube, "Hayek on Bentham," Utilitas 2 (1990), 12, and Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 345.
    • (1990) Utilitas , vol.2 , pp. 12
    • Dube, A.1
  • 64
    • 0039761062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, ed. by J. H. Burns and H. L. A. Hart (1789; London: Athlone Press, 1970), 290, and Jeremy Bentham, Method and Leading Features of an Institute of Political Economy, in Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings: Critical Edition Based on His Printed Works and Unprinted Manuscripts, ed. by W. Stark (3 vols.; London: Allen and Unwin, 1952-1954), Vol. 3, 333. See Allison Dube, "Hayek on Bentham," Utilitas 2 (1990), 12, and Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 345.
    • The Theme of Acquisitiveness , pp. 345
    • Dube1
  • 65
    • 0040353099 scopus 로고
    • Aldershot: Avebury
    • Jacobs concedes that the panopticon and poor law proposals are an aberration from the general "liberal" character of Bentham's thought, and suggests that they can be defended, at least in part, in terms of liberal principles. Unfortunately, he contents himself with rehearsing a list of specific liberal proposals in Bentham's writings, from which he uncritically concludes that "Bentham is most of the time in the liberal camp"; Bentham supported some state interventions in the economy, as did Adam Smith, "but these are qualifications of liberal economics, not a rejection of it" (Struan Jacobs, Science and British Liberalism: Locke, Bentham, Mill and Popper [Aldershot: Avebury, 1991], 90, 100, but see chap. 6 for the complete account).
    • (1991) Science and British Liberalism: Locke, Bentham, Mill and Popper , pp. 90
    • Jacobs, S.1
  • 69
    • 0039761065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 311, 146. Dube associates Bentham and Hayek more directly in the individualist camp of the liberal tradition when he states that for both "freedom in the economic sphere is inseparable from political freedom" (ibid., 250). For the full discussion see chaps. 5-7.
    • The Theme of Acquisitiveness , vol.311 , pp. 146
  • 70
    • 0040947083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 311, 146. Dube associates Bentham and Hayek more directly in the individualist camp of the liberal tradition when he states that for both "freedom in the economic sphere is inseparable from political freedom" (ibid., 250). For the full discussion see chaps. 5-7.
    • The Theme of Acquisitiveness , pp. 250
  • 74
    • 0040947083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Other difficulties attend Dube's "reconstruction," not the least of which is the suggestion that those who do not recognize that their individual interests are enhanced by pursuing the greatest happiness are in error in calculating their individual interest (ibid., 197) , even though he uncritically quotes Bentham to the effect that the individual alone is in a position to estimate what is and what is not in his own interest (ibid., 213).
    • The Theme of Acquisitiveness , pp. 197
  • 75
    • 0040947083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Other difficulties attend Dube's "reconstruction," not the least of which is the suggestion that those who do not recognize that their individual interests are enhanced by pursuing the greatest happiness are in error in calculating their individual interest (ibid., 197) , even though he uncritically quotes Bentham to the effect that the individual alone is in a position to estimate what is and what is not in his own interest (ibid., 213).
    • The Theme of Acquisitiveness , pp. 213
  • 84
    • 0009127841 scopus 로고
    • Foucault and bentham: A defence of panopticism
    • Janet Semple, "Foucault and Bentham: A Defence of Panopticism," Utilitas 4 (1992), 105-20.
    • (1992) Utilitas , vol.4 , pp. 105-120
    • Semple, J.1
  • 85
  • 86
    • 0039761055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, ibid., 157.
    • Utilitas , pp. 157
  • 87
    • 84972218462 scopus 로고
    • From bentham to benthamism
    • Perhaps David Lieberman strikes the appropriate discordant note when he observes that Bentham's panopticon "was a society in which his basic legislative strategy was inoperable" (David Lieberman, "From Bentham to Benthamism," The Historical Journal 28 [1985], 214).
    • (1985) The Historical Journal , vol.28 , pp. 214
    • Lieberman, D.1
  • 88
    • 0039168528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the influence of time and place in matters of legislation" and "of indirect legislation
    • have been edited by C. Bahmueller and H. Weiting, Jr., (Oxford, forthcoming)
    • Bentham's essays "On the Influence of Time and Place in Matters of Legislation" and "Of Indirect Legislation" have been edited by C. Bahmueller and H. Weiting, Jr., for The Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham (Oxford, forthcoming). There is an incomplete essay on the subject "Of Indirect Means of Preventing Crimes" included as part 3 of Bentham's Principles of Penal Law, in Works, Vol. 1, 533-80. For a discussion see Long, Bentham on Liberty, 136ff; pp. 142-45 focus on indirect checks on the unwarranted interference by government in the lives of law-abiding citizens, such as freedom of the press and freedom of association.
    • The Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham
    • Bentham1
  • 89
    • 0040353082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles of penal law
    • Bentham's essays "On the Influence of Time and Place in Matters of Legislation" and "Of Indirect Legislation" have been edited by C. Bahmueller and H. Weiting, Jr., for The Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham (Oxford, forthcoming). There is an incomplete essay on the subject "Of Indirect Means of Preventing Crimes" included as part 3 of Bentham's Principles of Penal Law, in Works, Vol. 1, 533-80. For a discussion see Long, Bentham on Liberty, 136ff; pp. 142-45 focus on indirect checks on the unwarranted interference by government in the lives of law-abiding citizens, such as freedom of the press and freedom of association.
    • Works , vol.1 , pp. 533-580
    • Bentham's1
  • 90
    • 0009386564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 136ff
    • Bentham's essays "On the Influence of Time and Place in Matters of Legislation" and "Of Indirect Legislation" have been edited by C. Bahmueller and H. Weiting, Jr., for The Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham (Oxford, forthcoming). There is an incomplete essay on the subject "Of Indirect Means of Preventing Crimes" included as part 3 of Bentham's Principles of Penal Law, in Works, Vol. 1, 533-80. For a discussion see Long, Bentham on Liberty, 136ff; pp. 142-45 focus on indirect checks on the unwarranted interference by government in the lives of law-abiding citizens, such as freedom of the press and freedom of association.
    • Bentham on Liberty , pp. 142-145
    • Long1
  • 91
    • 0348103817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Panopticon
    • Bentham, Panopticon, in Works, Vol. 4, 39.
    • Works , vol.4 , pp. 39
    • Bentham1
  • 92
    • 0040947072 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • See the mss. quotation to this effect in Charles Warren Everett, The Education of Jeremy Bentham (New York: Columbia University Press, 1931), 190-91.
    • (1931) The Education of Jeremy Bentham , pp. 190-191
    • Everett, C.W.1
  • 93
    • 0040947074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An essay on the promulgation of laws
    • Bentham, "An Essay on the Promulgation of Laws," in Works, Vol. 1, 161.
    • Works , vol.1 , pp. 161
    • Bentham1
  • 97
    • 0039761062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dube puts this construction upon Bentham's intentions in the context of the panopticon proposals (The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 315).
    • The Theme of Acquisitiveness , pp. 315
    • Dube1
  • 99
    • 77949744350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Manual of political economy
    • Jeremy Bentham, Manual of Political Economy, in Works, Vol. 3, 49 (not in the version in Bentham, Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings, Vol. 1, 219-73).
    • Works , vol.3 , pp. 49
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 100
    • 0039168523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jeremy Bentham, Manual of Political Economy, in Works, Vol. 3, 49 (not in the version in Bentham, Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings, Vol. 1, 219-73).
    • Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings , vol.1 , pp. 219-273
    • Bentham1
  • 102
    • 0039168522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bentham, Defence of Usury, Manual of Political Economy, Method and Leading Features of an Institute of Political Economy and Observations on the Restrictive and Prohibitory Commercial System, all in Bentham, Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings, Vol. 1, 121-207, 219-73, and Vol. 3, 303-80, 381-417.
    • Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings , vol.1 , pp. 121-207
    • Bentham1
  • 103
    • 0040947071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bentham, Defence of Usury, Manual of Political Economy, Method and Leading Features of an Institute of Political Economy and Observations on the Restrictive and Prohibitory Commercial System, all in Bentham, Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings, Vol. 1, 121-207, 219-73, and Vol. 3, 303-80, 381-417.
    • Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings , vol.3 , pp. 303-380
  • 109
    • 0039535048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At least one economist has argued that in Defence of a Maximum Bentham returned to a version of mercantilism (T. W. Hutchison, "Bentham as an Economist," Journal of Economics 66 [1956], 288-306). For Stark's discussion of this essay see editor's introduction in Bentham, Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings, Vol. 3, 30-37.
    • Defence of a Maximum
    • Bentham1
  • 110
    • 0039761031 scopus 로고
    • Bentham as an economist
    • At least one economist has argued that in Defence of a Maximum Bentham returned to a version of mercantilism (T. W. Hutchison, "Bentham as an Economist," Journal of Economics 66 [1956], 288-306). For Stark's discussion of this essay see editor's introduction in Bentham, Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings, Vol. 3, 30-37.
    • (1956) Journal of Economics , vol.66 , pp. 288-306
    • Hutchison, T.W.1
  • 111
    • 0040353079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At least one economist has argued that in Defence of a Maximum Bentham returned to a version of mercantilism (T. W. Hutchison, "Bentham as an Economist," Journal of Economics 66 [1956], 288-306). For Stark's discussion of this essay see editor's introduction in Bentham, Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings, Vol. 3, 30-37.
    • Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings , vol.3 , pp. 30-37
    • Bentham1
  • 113
    • 0040353065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Parekh misses the point entirely when he writes: "The general import of his laissez-faire economic theory is that as long as no one in the community starves, it does not matter to Bentham who owns how much" ("Bentham's Theory of Equality," 492).
    • Bentham's Theory of Equality , pp. 492
    • Parekh1
  • 114
    • 84974220374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Editor's introduction in Bentham, Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings, Vol. 3, 33. This understanding of Defence of a Maximum is reiterated by P. J. Kelly, "Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: The Civil Law and the Foundations of Bentham's Economic Thought," Utilitas 1 (1989), 81 note.
    • Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings , vol.3 , pp. 33
    • Bentham1
  • 115
    • 84974220374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Editor's introduction in Bentham, Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings, Vol. 3, 33. This understanding of Defence of a Maximum is reiterated by P. J. Kelly, "Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: The Civil Law and the Foundations of Bentham's Economic Thought," Utilitas 1 (1989), 81 note.
    • Defence of a Maximum
  • 116
    • 84974220374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism and distributive justice: The civil law and the foundations of Bentham's economic thought
    • note
    • Editor's introduction in Bentham, Jeremy Bentham's Economic Writings, Vol. 3, 33. This understanding of Defence of a Maximum is reiterated by P. J. Kelly, "Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: The Civil Law and the Foundations of Bentham's Economic Thought," Utilitas 1 (1989), 81 note.
    • (1989) Utilitas , vol.1 , pp. 81
    • Kelly, P.J.1
  • 118
    • 0003472348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Rosen, Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy, 55-75; Rosen, Bentham, Byron and Greece, 4; and Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 71-103.
    • Bentham, Byron and Greece , pp. 4
    • Rosen1
  • 119
    • 0039168509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Rosen, Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy, 55-75; Rosen, Bentham, Byron and Greece, 4; and Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 71-103.
    • Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice , pp. 71-103
    • Kelly1
  • 124
    • 0039168509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 8
    • UC 100/96-186. Other important manuscripts identified by Kelly, although written far later (in the 1820s), are UC 61/9-10, 19-21, 26-66, 83-97 and BL Add. MS 33550/48-144 (Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 73, note 8). The civil law manuscripts are also discussed by Long, Bentham on Liberty, chap. 10, where some of the same points are made about the relationship between the principle of utility and its subordinate principles as one finds in Kelly.
    • Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice , pp. 73
    • Kelly1
  • 125
    • 0009386564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 10
    • UC 100/96-186. Other important manuscripts identified by Kelly, although written far later (in the 1820s), are UC 61/9-10, 19-21, 26-66, 83-97 and BL Add. MS 33550/48-144 (Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 73, note 8). The civil law manuscripts are also discussed by Long, Bentham on Liberty, chap. 10, where some of the same points are made about the relationship between the principle of utility and its subordinate principles as one finds in Kelly.
    • Bentham on Liberty
    • Long1
  • 126
    • 0039761030 scopus 로고
    • "A Commentary on Mr. Humphrey's Real Property Code"
    • The "disappointment-preventing principle" first appeared in "A Commentary on Mr. Humphrey's Real Property Code" (1826), in Works, Vol. 5, 387-416, and later in the Constitutional Code , the "Article on Utilitarianism" (a revised version appears in Deontology), manuscripts incorporated into "Pannomial Fragments," in Works, Vol. 3, 211-30, and the Equity Dispatch Court Proposal (1830), in ibid., 297-317. In the latter, Bentham refers to "the Disappointment preventive, or say Non-disappointment principle" which, he says, "next to the Greatest Happiness principle . . . is the immediate lineal descendent of that same parent principle" (ibid., 312, quoted by Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 146). Kelly's references for the "security-providing principle" are UC 61/47 (1828) and BL Add. MS 33550/55 (Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 174-75, 138, note 5).
    • (1826) Works , vol.5 , pp. 387-416
  • 127
    • 0003543966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The "disappointment-preventing principle" first appeared in "A Commentary on Mr. Humphrey's Real Property Code" (1826), in Works, Vol. 5, 387-416, and later in the Constitutional Code , the "Article on Utilitarianism" (a revised version appears in Deontology), manuscripts incorporated into "Pannomial Fragments," in Works, Vol. 3, 211-30, and the Equity Dispatch Court Proposal (1830), in ibid., 297-317. In the latter, Bentham refers to "the Disappointment preventive, or say Non-disappointment principle" which, he says, "next to the Greatest Happiness principle . . . is the immediate lineal descendent of that same parent principle" (ibid., 312, quoted by Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 146). Kelly's references for the "security-providing principle" are UC 61/47 (1828) and BL Add. MS 33550/55 (Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 174-75, 138, note 5).
    • Constitutional Code
  • 128
    • 0040353061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Article on utilitarianism
    • a revised version appears
    • The "disappointment-preventing principle" first appeared in "A Commentary on Mr. Humphrey's Real Property Code" (1826), in Works, Vol. 5, 387-416, and later in the Constitutional Code , the "Article on Utilitarianism" (a revised version appears in Deontology), manuscripts incorporated into "Pannomial Fragments," in Works, Vol. 3, 211-30, and the Equity Dispatch Court Proposal (1830), in ibid., 297-317. In the latter, Bentham refers to "the Disappointment preventive, or say Non-disappointment principle" which, he says, "next to the Greatest Happiness principle . . . is the immediate lineal descendent of that same parent principle" (ibid., 312, quoted by Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 146). Kelly's references for the "security-providing principle" are UC 61/47 (1828) and BL Add. MS 33550/55 (Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 174-75, 138, note 5).
    • Deontology
  • 129
    • 0039535117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pannomial fragments
    • The "disappointment-preventing principle" first appeared in "A Commentary on Mr. Humphrey's Real Property Code" (1826), in Works, Vol. 5, 387-416, and later in the Constitutional Code , the "Article on Utilitarianism" (a revised version appears in Deontology), manuscripts incorporated into "Pannomial Fragments," in Works, Vol. 3, 211-30, and the Equity Dispatch Court Proposal (1830), in ibid., 297-317. In the latter, Bentham refers to "the Disappointment preventive, or say Non-disappointment principle" which, he says, "next to the Greatest Happiness principle . . . is the immediate lineal descendent of that same parent principle" (ibid., 312, quoted by Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 146). Kelly's references for the "security-providing principle" are UC 61/47 (1828) and BL Add. MS 33550/55 (Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 174-75, 138, note 5).
    • Works , vol.3 , pp. 211-230
  • 130
    • 0039168504 scopus 로고
    • Equity dispatch court proposal
    • The "disappointment-preventing principle" first appeared in "A Commentary on Mr. Humphrey's Real Property Code" (1826), in Works, Vol. 5, 387-416, and later in the Constitutional Code , the "Article on Utilitarianism" (a revised version appears in Deontology), manuscripts incorporated into "Pannomial Fragments," in Works, Vol. 3, 211-30, and the Equity Dispatch Court Proposal (1830), in ibid., 297-317. In the latter, Bentham refers to "the Disappointment preventive, or say Non-disappointment principle" which, he says, "next to the Greatest Happiness principle . . . is the immediate lineal descendent of that same parent principle" (ibid., 312, quoted by Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 146). Kelly's references for the "security-providing principle" are UC 61/47 (1828) and BL Add. MS 33550/55 (Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 174-75, 138, note 5).
    • (1830) Works , pp. 297-317
  • 131
    • 0345463361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The "disappointment-preventing principle" first appeared in "A Commentary on Mr. Humphrey's Real Property Code" (1826), in Works, Vol. 5, 387-416, and later in the Constitutional Code , the "Article on Utilitarianism" (a revised version appears in Deontology), manuscripts incorporated into "Pannomial Fragments," in Works, Vol. 3, 211-30, and the Equity Dispatch Court Proposal (1830), in ibid., 297-317. In the latter, Bentham refers to "the Disappointment preventive, or say Non-disappointment principle" which, he says, "next to the Greatest Happiness principle . . . is the immediate lineal descendent of that same parent principle" (ibid., 312, quoted by Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 146). Kelly's references for the "security-providing principle" are UC 61/47 (1828) and BL Add. MS 33550/55 (Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 174-75, 138, note 5).
    • Works , pp. 312
    • Bentham1
  • 132
    • 0039761062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The "disappointment-preventing principle" first appeared in "A Commentary on Mr. Humphrey's Real Property Code" (1826), in Works, Vol. 5, 387-416, and later in the Constitutional Code , the "Article on Utilitarianism" (a revised version appears in Deontology), manuscripts incorporated into "Pannomial Fragments," in Works, Vol. 3, 211-30, and the Equity Dispatch Court Proposal (1830), in ibid., 297-317. In the latter, Bentham refers to "the Disappointment preventive, or say Non-disappointment principle" which, he says, "next to the Greatest Happiness principle . . . is the immediate lineal descendent of that same parent principle" (ibid., 312, quoted by Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 146). Kelly's references for the "security-providing principle" are UC 61/47 (1828) and BL Add. MS 33550/55 (Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 174-75, 138, note 5).
    • The Theme of Acquisitiveness , pp. 146
    • Dube1
  • 133
    • 0039168509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 5
    • The "disappointment-preventing principle" first appeared in "A Commentary on Mr. Humphrey's Real Property Code" (1826), in Works, Vol. 5, 387-416, and later in the Constitutional Code , the "Article on Utilitarianism" (a revised version appears in Deontology), manuscripts incorporated into "Pannomial Fragments," in Works, Vol. 3, 211-30, and the Equity Dispatch Court Proposal (1830), in ibid., 297-317. In the latter, Bentham refers to "the Disappointment preventive, or say Non-disappointment principle" which, he says, "next to the Greatest Happiness principle . . . is the immediate lineal descendent of that same parent principle" (ibid., 312, quoted by Dube, The Theme of Acquisitiveness, 146). Kelly's references for the "security-providing principle" are UC 61/47 (1828) and BL Add. MS 33550/55 (Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 174-75, 138, note 5).
    • Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice , pp. 174-175
    • Kelly's1
  • 134
    • 0039168509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 171; see also Rosen, Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy, 15. Postema discusses the disappointment-preventing principle in the context of Bentham's mature theory of adjudication (Bentham and the Common Law Tradition, 413-21).
    • Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice , pp. 171
    • Kelly1
  • 135
    • 0004164867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 171; see also Rosen, Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy, 15. Postema discusses the disappointment-preventing principle in the context of Bentham's mature theory of adjudication (Bentham and the Common Law Tradition, 413-21).
    • Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy , pp. 15
    • Rosen1
  • 136
    • 0003883951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 171; see also Rosen, Jeremy Bentham and Representative Democracy, 15. Postema discusses the disappointment-preventing principle in the context of Bentham's mature theory of adjudication (Bentham and the Common Law Tradition, 413-21).
    • Bentham and the Common Law Tradition , pp. 413-421
    • Postema1
  • 142
    • 0010001016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles of the civil code
    • Jeremy Bentham, Principles of the Civil Code, in Works, Vol. 1, 322, quoted by Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 95 (emphasis in original).
    • Works , vol.1 , pp. 322
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 143
    • 0039168509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis in original
    • Jeremy Bentham, Principles of the Civil Code, in Works, Vol. 1, 322, quoted by Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 95 (emphasis in original).
    • Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice , pp. 95
    • Kelly1
  • 147
    • 84971721865 scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism, rights and equality
    • David J. Crossley, "Utilitarianism, Rights and Equality," Utilitas 2 (1990), 53.
    • (1990) Utilitas , vol.2 , pp. 53
    • Crossley, D.J.1
  • 149
    • 33846548864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bentham printed most of An Introduction in 1780, but did not publish it until 1789; chapter 2 contains Bentham's dismissal of principles contrary to that of utility. Even earlier, in the "Preparatory Principles" manuscripts of the mid-1770s, Bentham had developed a sophisticated analysis of the "fictions" that bedeviled legal, political and philosophical understanding, and both A Fragment on Government (1776) and its parent text, the posthumously published A Comment on the Commentaries, illustrate this aversion. For a discussion see James E. Crimmins, Secular Utilitarianism: Social Science and the Critique of Religion in the Thought of Jeremy Bentham (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 40-52.
    • (1780) An Introduction
    • Bentham1
  • 150
    • 85054799728 scopus 로고
    • Bentham printed most of An Introduction in 1780, but did not publish it until 1789; chapter 2 contains Bentham's dismissal of principles contrary to that of utility. Even earlier, in the "Preparatory Principles" manuscripts of the mid-1770s, Bentham had developed a sophisticated analysis of the "fictions" that bedeviled legal, political and philosophical understanding, and both A Fragment on Government (1776) and its parent text, the posthumously published A Comment on the Commentaries, illustrate this aversion. For a discussion see James E. Crimmins, Secular Utilitarianism: Social Science and the Critique of Religion in the Thought of Jeremy Bentham (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 40-52.
    • (1770) Preparatory Principles
    • Bentham's1
  • 151
    • 0004293083 scopus 로고
    • Bentham printed most of An Introduction in 1780, but did not publish it until 1789; chapter 2 contains Bentham's dismissal of principles contrary to that of utility. Even earlier, in the "Preparatory Principles" manuscripts of the mid-1770s, Bentham had developed a sophisticated analysis of the "fictions" that bedeviled legal, political and philosophical understanding, and both A Fragment on Government (1776) and its parent text, the posthumously published A Comment on the Commentaries, illustrate this aversion. For a discussion see James E. Crimmins, Secular Utilitarianism: Social Science and the Critique of Religion in the Thought of Jeremy Bentham (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 40-52.
    • (1776) A Fragment on Government
    • Bentham1
  • 152
    • 84880582508 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bentham printed most of An Introduction in 1780, but did not publish it until 1789; chapter 2 contains Bentham's dismissal of principles contrary to that of utility. Even earlier, in the "Preparatory Principles" manuscripts of the mid-1770s, Bentham had developed a sophisticated analysis of the "fictions" that bedeviled legal, political and philosophical understanding, and both A Fragment on Government (1776) and its parent text, the posthumously published A Comment on the Commentaries, illustrate this aversion. For a discussion see James E. Crimmins, Secular Utilitarianism: Social Science and the Critique of Religion in the Thought of Jeremy Bentham (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 40-52.
    • Comment on the Commentaries
  • 153
    • 0007031010 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Bentham printed most of An Introduction in 1780, but did not publish it until 1789; chapter 2 contains Bentham's dismissal of principles contrary to that of utility. Even earlier, in the "Preparatory Principles" manuscripts of the mid-1770s, Bentham had developed a sophisticated analysis of the "fictions" that bedeviled legal, political and philosophical understanding, and both A Fragment on Government (1776) and its parent text, the posthumously published A Comment on the Commentaries, illustrate this aversion.
    • (1990) Secular Utilitarianism: Social Science and the Critique of Religion in the Thought of Jeremy Bentham , pp. 40-52
    • Crimmins, J.E.1
  • 155
    • 0040947053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In Kelly's account this is what Bentham intended to achieve by what he came to call the "disappointment-preventing principle," but it might be queried how the utilitarian legislator could do otherwise than count costs as well as benefits when calculating general utility.
  • 157
    • 0009304994 scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism
    • J. M. Robson, ed., Essays on Ethics, Religion and Society, Toronto: University of Toronto Press
    • See J. S. Mill, Utilitarianism, in J. M. Robson, ed., Essays on Ethics, Religion and Society, Vol. 10 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1969), 257. Mill may have imbibed the premise from his father, who frequently referred to it (see James Mill: Political Writings, ed. by Terence Ball [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992], editor's introduction, xxii).
    • (1969) The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill , vol.10 , pp. 257
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 158
    • 0039168497 scopus 로고
    • ed. by Terence Ball Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See J. S. Mill, Utilitarianism, in J. M. Robson, ed., Essays on Ethics, Religion and Society, Vol. 10 of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1969), 257. Mill may have imbibed the premise from his father, who frequently referred to it (see James Mill: Political Writings, ed. by Terence Ball [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992], editor's introduction, xxii).
    • (1992) James Mill: Political Writings
    • Mill1
  • 159
    • 84906300121 scopus 로고
    • Mill
    • Q. Skinner, et al., eds., Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • William Thomas, Mill, in Q. Skinner, et al., eds., Great Political Thinkers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), 257.
    • (1992) Great Political Thinkers , pp. 257
    • Thomas, W.1
  • 160
    • 0003445959 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, note
    • For example, James Griffin, Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Importance (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), 168, 371 note. Among those who have dealt extensively with Bentham's moral theory, Baumgardt is one of the few to avoid reference to the dictum (David Baumgardt, Bentham and the Ethics of Today [New York: Princeton University Press, 1952]).
    • (1986) Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Importance , pp. 168
    • Griffin, J.1
  • 161
    • 0012845096 scopus 로고
    • New York: Princeton University Press
    • For example, James Griffin, Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Importance (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), 168, 371 note. Among those who have dealt extensively with Bentham's moral theory, Baumgardt is one of the few to avoid reference to the dictum (David Baumgardt, Bentham and the Ethics of Today [New York: Princeton University Press, 1952]).
    • (1952) Bentham and the Ethics of Today
    • Baumgardt, D.1
  • 162
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971), 27.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 27
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 163
    • 84972017288 scopus 로고
    • Could kant have been a utilitarian?
    • For the complete argument see R. M. Hare, "Could Kant Have Been a Utilitarian?" Utilitas 5 (1993), 1-16, esp. 4-5. Hare ignores the fact that Bentham's utilitarianism was developed primarily in the form of legal theory and as a guide for the legislative pursuit of general utility. Ideally, the moral reasoning of private individuals should coincide with the prescriptions of utility. Bentham's theory of human nature, however, was that of a psychological egoist; thus his utilitarianism required the active participation of the legislator in the production of general well-being. To what degree and at what cost is the central issue.
    • (1993) Utilitas , vol.5 , pp. 1-16
    • Hare, R.M.1
  • 165
    • 0004293486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That individual autonomy is an essential component of human existence with a value of its own is central to Griffin's broadly conceived utilitarian account of "well-being" (Griffin, Well-Being, 67-68, 131, 144-45).
    • Well-Being , pp. 67-68
    • Griffin1
  • 166
    • 0039168495 scopus 로고
    • Bentham, utilitarianism, and distribution
    • David Lyons, "Bentham, Utilitarianism, and Distribution," Utilitas 4 (1992), 325.
    • (1992) Utilitas , vol.4 , pp. 325
    • Lyons, D.1
  • 167
    • 0040947060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kelly cites UC 100/186 (ca. 1776), Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 188, but acknowledges that most of the discussion of this principle occurs in the context of Bentham's later writings on constitutional reform.
    • Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice , pp. 188
  • 168
    • 0041702381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At one point Kelly suggests that the earlier civil law mss. (UC 100/96-186) reveal that Bentham was not as committed to the absolute protection of any given distribution of property as some passages from the Principles of the Civil Code might suggest (see, for example, Works, Vol. 1, 311, cited by Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 180).
    • Principles of the Civil Code
    • Kelly1
  • 169
    • 0041957537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At one point Kelly suggests that the earlier civil law mss. (UC 100/96-186) reveal that Bentham was not as committed to the absolute protection of any given distribution of property as some passages from the Principles of the Civil Code might suggest (see, for example, Works, Vol. 1, 311, cited by Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 180).
    • Works , vol.1 , pp. 311
  • 170
    • 0039168509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At one point Kelly suggests that the earlier civil law mss. (UC 100/96-186) reveal that Bentham was not as committed to the absolute protection of any given distribution of property as some passages from the Principles of the Civil Code might suggest (see, for example, Works, Vol. 1, 311, cited by Kelly, Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice, 180).
    • Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice , pp. 180
    • Kelly1
  • 171
    • 0039761024 scopus 로고
    • For example, Plan of Parliamentary Reform (1818), Radical Reform Bill (1819) and Radicalism Not Dangerous (written 1819-20), in Works, Vol. 3, 433-622; see also note 101 above.
    • (1818) Plan of Parliamentary Reform
  • 172
    • 0040353050 scopus 로고
    • For example, Plan of Parliamentary Reform (1818), Radical Reform Bill (1819) and Radicalism Not Dangerous (written 1819-20), in Works, Vol. 3, 433-622; see also note 101 above.
    • (1819) Radical Reform Bill
  • 173
    • 0039168498 scopus 로고
    • For example, Plan of Parliamentary Reform (1818), Radical Reform Bill (1819) and Radicalism Not Dangerous (written 1819-20), in Works, Vol. 3, 433-622; see also note 101 above.
    • (1819) Radicalism Not Dangerous
  • 174
    • 0039168496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Plan of Parliamentary Reform (1818), Radical Reform Bill (1819) and Radicalism Not Dangerous (written 1819-20), in Works, Vol. 3, 433-622; see also note 101 above.
    • Works , vol.3 , pp. 433-622
  • 175
    • 0039168491 scopus 로고
    • Bentham's political radicalism reexamined
    • Unpublished papers, dated 1788-90; UC 170/87-121, 126/8-16, 126/1-7 and 127/6-19, respectively. For a discussion see James E. Crimmins, "Bentham's Political Radicalism Reexamined," Journal of the History of Ideas 55 (1994), 259-81.
    • (1994) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.55 , pp. 259-281
    • Crimmins, J.E.1
  • 176
    • 84972591393 scopus 로고
    • Public interest and majority rule in bentham's democratic theory
    • A point well made by M. H. James, "Public Interest and Majority Rule in Bentham's Democratic Theory," Political Theory 9 (1981), 56-61.
    • (1981) Political Theory , vol.9 , pp. 56-61
    • James, M.H.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.