메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 10, Issue 4, 1996, Pages 292-309

Experimenting with embryos: Can philosophy help?

(1)  Heyd, David a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords

ANALYTICAL APPROACH; ARTICLE; ATTITUDE; BIOMEDICAL AND BEHAVIORAL RESEARCH; EMBRYO; EMBRYO DISPOSITION; EMBRYO RESEARCH; ETHICS; FETAL TISSUE TRANSPLANTATION; FETAL WELL BEING; GENETICS AND REPRODUCTION; HUMAN; HUMAN EXPERIMENT; INDIVIDUALITY; INFERTILITY THERAPY; INTERDISCIPLINARY COMMUNICATION; MORALITY; PEDIGREE; PERSONHOOD; PHILOSOPHICAL APPROACH; PHILOSOPHY; POLICY; POLITICS; PRENATAL DEVELOPMENT; PSYCHOLOGY; PUBLIC RELATIONS; RESEARCH; RESEARCH SUBJECT; RISK; RISK ASSESSMENT; SOCIAL BEHAVIOR; SOCIAL CONTROL; SOCIOECONOMICS;

EID: 0030257087     PISSN: 02699702     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/1467-8519.00030     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (12)

References (21)
  • 1
    • 18044386481 scopus 로고
    • The Warnock Report on Human Fertilisation and Embryology
    • reprinted in M. Warnock, Oxford: Blackwell
    • See, for instance, "The Warnock Report on Human Fertilisation and Embryology", reprinted in M. Warnock, A Question of Life, Oxford: Blackwell, 1985; and the Israeli Report of the Public-Professional Commission on IVF, Jerusalem: The Ministry of Health, 1994 (in Hebrew).
    • (1985) A Question of Life
  • 2
    • 18044392312 scopus 로고
    • Jerusalem: The Ministry of Health, (in Hebrew)
    • See, for instance, "The Warnock Report on Human Fertilisation and Embryology", reprinted in M. Warnock, A Question of Life, Oxford: Blackwell, 1985; and the Israeli Report of the Public-Professional Commission on IVF, Jerusalem: The Ministry of Health, 1994 (in Hebrew).
    • (1994) Report of the Public-Professional Commission on IVF
  • 3
    • 0343677778 scopus 로고
    • Australia: The National Bioethics Consultative Committee
    • K. Dawson, Human Embryo Experimentation, Australia: The National Bioethics Consultative Committee, 1990, p. 34.
    • (1990) Human Embryo Experimentation , pp. 34
    • Dawson, K.1
  • 4
    • 0001059647 scopus 로고
    • Which Slopes Are Slippery?
    • M. Lockwood (ed.), Oxford University Press
    • I am referring to the slippery slope argument as a psychological source of our intuitive objection to embryo experimentation, since despite its popularity in ethical debates on the topic, I believe that it is not a valid philosophical argument. The most balanced analysis of slippery slope arguments and their fallacious applications is B. Williams, "Which Slopes Are Slippery?", in M. Lockwood (ed.), Moral Dilemmas in Modern Medicine, Oxford University Press, 1985, pp. 126-37.
    • (1985) Moral Dilemmas in Modern Medicine , pp. 126-137
    • Williams, B.1
  • 5
    • 0025508047 scopus 로고
    • The Ethics of Ex Utero Research on Spare 'Non-Viable' Human Embryos
    • It has also been noted that the viability test might lead to the paradoxical conclusion that experimentation with in vitro embryos should be allowed only after the first fourteen days, since only at that stage they become non-viable! For a view which supports the viability criterion as superior to the fourteen-day limit, see F. Baylis, "The Ethics of Ex Utero Research on Spare 'Non-Viable' Human Embryos", Bioethics 4, 1990, 311-29. The "logical oddity" in the concept of viability is also noted by LeRoy Walters in his "Ethical Issues in Experimentation on the Human Fetus" Bioethics (ed. T.A. Shannon), New York: Paulist Press, 1976, p. 276.
    • (1990) Bioethics , vol.4 , pp. 311-329
    • Baylis, F.1
  • 6
    • 0025508047 scopus 로고
    • Ethical Issues in Experimentation on the Human Fetus
    • (ed. T.A. Shannon), New York: Paulist Press
    • It has also been noted that the viability test might lead to the paradoxical conclusion that experimentation with in vitro embryos should be allowed only after the first fourteen days, since only at that stage they become non-viable! For a view which supports the viability criterion as superior to the fourteen-day limit, see F. Baylis, "The Ethics of Ex Utero Research on Spare 'Non-Viable' Human Embryos", Bioethics 4, 1990, 311-29. The "logical oddity" in the concept of viability is also noted by LeRoy Walters in his "Ethical Issues in Experimentation on the Human Fetus" Bioethics (ed. T.A. Shannon), New York: Paulist Press, 1976, p. 276.
    • (1976) Bioethics , pp. 276
    • Walters, L.1
  • 7
    • 0042853993 scopus 로고
    • When Does Life Begin?
    • M. Lockwood (ed.), Oxford University Press
    • I believe that the third criterion mentioned above, brain activity or sentience, might prove equally "self-defeating" once we reach better knowledge about it in the future. The nature of primitive brain activity in the developing fetus might turn out to be detached from any form of sentience in the subjective sense of "feeling pain". And will the mind-body gap ever allow us to observe the moment at which the fetus starts feeling pain (rather than exhibiting mere "pain-behaviour")? For the view that brain activity marks the beginning of life and its implications for the morality of embryo research, see M. Lockwood, "When Does Life Begin?" in M. Lockwood (ed.), Moral Dilemmas in Modern Medicine, Oxford University Press, 1985, pp. 29-31. Lockwood allows for experimentation on embryos even after the development of the brain, as long as they are not viable, do not suffer pain and were not created deliberately for the purpose of research. The criterion of viability is, I believe, problematic, as is the criterion of deliberate creation (see below); but the test of feeling pain seems to be valid.
    • (1985) Moral Dilemmas in Modern Medicine , pp. 29-31
    • Lockwood, M.1
  • 8
    • 0003683199 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • For a detailed and systematic discussion of the whole complex of the moral standing of "potential" people and the paradoxes in ascribing rights or interests to them, see my Genethics: Moral Issues in the Creation of People, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992, particularly chap.
    • (1992) Genethics: Moral Issues in the Creation of People
  • 9
    • 18044389441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The radical thesis which denies the ascription of rights to potential people is of course philosophically contested, and of course much of the force of the argument in this section depends on the validity of the "person-affecting" view defended in the book and followed here.
  • 10
    • 18044385287 scopus 로고
    • Who Is the Subject of Research?
    • P. Singer et al. (eds.), Cambridge University Press
    • Some research which is risky in terms of the embryo's chances of survival is aimed at reducing the risk for the mother in the course of IVF treatment. This is a case in which the health of the mother (rather than her wish to have a baby) is promoted through embryo experimentation. Cf. B. Gaze and K. Dawson, "Who Is the Subject of Research?" in P. Singer et al. (eds.), Embryo Experimentation Cambridge University Press, 1990, pp. 109-124.
    • (1990) Embryo Experimentation , pp. 109-124
    • Gaze, B.1    Dawson, K.2
  • 11
    • 0023967617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • IVF Technology and the Argument from Potential
    • P. Singer and K. Dawson, "IVF Technology and the Argument from Potential" in Embryo Experimentation (quoted above). Singer and Dawson add to these challenges to the potentiality principle that if potentiality is understood in terms of natural development (rather than the probability of actualization), then embryos in vitro have no moral standing since they cannot survive without deliberate human intervention (p. 87).
    • Embryo Experimentation
    • Singer, P.1    Dawson, K.2
  • 12
    • 0024047486 scopus 로고
    • Arguing from Potential
    • This claim is very clearly articulated in S. Buckle, "Arguing from Potential" Bioethics 2, 1988, 227-53. Buckle distinguishes between x's potential to become y (which assumes x=y) and x's potential to produce y (which does not assume such identity). Now, if y is the entity which has moral standing, there is no moral duty to respect x, either because it is not identical with y (which is the case in the first fourteen days of the pre-embryo), or because it has no moral standing of its own but only the capacity to produce an entity with such a standing.
    • (1988) Bioethics , vol.2 , pp. 227-253
    • Buckle, S.1
  • 13
    • 0004150971 scopus 로고
    • London: Harper Collins
    • R. Dworkin, Life's Dominion, London: Harper Collins, 1993. Dworkin does not discuss embryo experimentation specifically, but his argument concerning the abortion of fetuses at a later stage directly bears upon our topic.
    • (1993) Life's Dominion
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 14
    • 18044399101 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • D. Parfit, Reasons and Persons, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, part IV; and D. Heyd, Genethics (quoted above), pp. 80-90.
    • (1984) Reasons and Persons , Issue.4 PART
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 15
    • 0003975958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • quoted above
    • D. Parfit, Reasons and Persons, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, part IV; and D. Heyd, Genethics (quoted above), pp. 80-90.
    • Genethics , pp. 80-90
    • Heyd, D.1
  • 16
    • 0023355977 scopus 로고
    • Ethics and New Reproductive Technologies: An International Review of Committee Statements
    • June
    • In a useful study of the way various ethical committees throughout the world have addressed the problems of the regulation of new reproductive technologies LeRoy Walters found that four committees recommended a total ban on embryo research and eleven allowed for some forms of research. Of this latter group, most committees favoured research only on "spare" embryos, i.e. those left over in clinical treatment, while other committees (like the Warnock) allowed research on embryos deliberately created for this purpose. LeRoy Walters, "Ethics and New Reproductive Technologies: An International Review of Committee Statements" Hastings Center Report, June 1987, p. 8.
    • (1987) Hastings Center Report , pp. 8
    • Walters, L.1
  • 17
    • 18044382649 scopus 로고
    • Research on Early Human Embryos in vitro
    • G.R. Dunstan and E.A. Shinebourne (eds.), Oxford University Press
    • For a different objection to the distinction between spare and deliberately created embryos, see P. Braude, "Research on Early Human Embryos in vitro", in G.R. Dunstan and E.A. Shinebourne (eds.), Doctors 'Decisions, Oxford University Press, 1989, pp. 39-40. Braude observes the alternative to experimentation with spare embryos is their freezing (with the goal of ultimately finding a "host" for them). But this option is no less problematic from an ethical point of view, since we do not know how freezing affects the viability and health of the future embryo. The important general point raised by Braude is that it is unethical to submit an embryo to a clinical ("therapeutic") procedure on the basis of a method of trial and error rather than on the basis of a systematic and scientifically guided research.
    • (1989) Doctors 'Decisions , pp. 39-40
    • Braude, P.1
  • 18
    • 0041851846 scopus 로고
    • Embryos and Hedgehogs: On the Moral Status of the Embryo
    • A. Dyson and J. Harris (eds.), London: Routledge
    • J. Harris, "Embryos and Hedgehogs: On the Moral Status of the Embryo" in A. Dyson and J. Harris (eds.), Experiments on Embryos, London: Routledge, 1990, pp. 65-81. Harris makes a good case for the equal standing of "spare-"and "research embryos" (pp. 77-8).
    • (1990) Experiments on Embryos , pp. 65-81
    • Harris, J.1
  • 19
    • 18044379851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • quoted above
    • This is a good reason for including a philosopher in bioethical committees. Mary Warnock, whose contribution as a philosopher to the working of ethical committees has been of much significance, expresses a modest view of the function of ethical committees and the unavoidably compromising nature of their recommendations. A Question of Life (quoted above), pp. 95-100.
    • A Question of Life , pp. 95-100
  • 20
    • 18044374564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ethics and Embryology: The Case for Experimentation
    • A. Dyson and J. Harris (eds.), quoted above
    • A typical example is Dr. Edwards, one of the two pioneers of IVF. Edwards takes a straightforward utilitarian stand regarding experiments on embryos, arguing that the chance of preventing abortions of five-months old fetuses justifies conducting experiments on one-week old pre-embryos. See his "Ethics and Embryology: The Case for Experimentation", in A. Dyson and J. Harris (eds.), Experiments on Embryos (quoted above), pp. 48f.
    • Experiments on Embryos
  • 21
    • 18044389043 scopus 로고
    • Moral Philosophy and Public Policy
    • For an illuminating discussion of the role of the philosopher in ethical committees see W. Kymlicka, "Moral Philosophy and Public Policy", Bioethics 7, 1993, 20-22. Kymlicka argues that the importance of philosophical fine-tuning should not be exaggerated, and that sometimes, as in the case of the fourteen-day limit, behind the philosophically fallacious arguments there might be sound moral sensitivity.
    • (1993) Bioethics , vol.7 , pp. 20-22
    • Kymlicka, W.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.