메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 2, Issue 4, 1996, Pages 411-428

The morality of scientific openness

Author keywords

Ethics of science; Research ethics; Science policy; Scientific information; Scientific openness; Scientific secrecy

Indexed keywords

ARTICLE; BIOMEDICAL AND BEHAVIORAL RESEARCH; ETHICS; FREEDOM; HUMAN; INFORMATION DISSEMINATION; INFORMATION SERVICE; PATENT; PERSONAL AUTONOMY; PERSONNEL; PHILOSOPHICAL APPROACH; SCIENCE;

EID: 0030251474     PISSN: 13533452     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1007/BF02583928     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (13)

References (47)
  • 1
    • 0003651293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • report from the Committee on Science, Engineering, and Public Policy, National Academy of Sciences, National Academy of Engineering and Institute of Medicine, second edition, National Academy Press, Washington, D.C.
    • On Being a Scientist. Responsible Conduct in Research, report from the Committee on Science, Engineering, and Public Policy, National Academy of Sciences, National Academy of Engineering and Institute of Medicine, second edition, 1995, National Academy Press, Washington, D.C.
    • (1995) On Being a Scientist. Responsible Conduct in Research
  • 2
    • 84965484174 scopus 로고
    • Communication, Competition, and Secrecy: The Production and Dissemination of Research-Related Information in Genetics
    • See, for example, the overview and numerous references given in McCain, K. W. (1991) "Communication, Competition, and Secrecy: The Production and Dissemination of Research-Related Information in Genetics", Science, Technology & Human Values 16 (4): 491-516.
    • (1991) Science, Technology & Human Values , vol.16 , Issue.4 , pp. 491-516
    • McCain, K.W.1
  • 3
    • 0007247133 scopus 로고
    • The Normative Structure of Science
    • Merton, University of Chicago Press, Chicago & London
    • Merton, R. (1973) "The Normative Structure of Science", in: Merton, The Sociology of the Research Process, University of Chicago Press, Chicago & London.
    • (1973) The Sociology of the Research Process
    • Merton, R.1
  • 5
    • 0004227095 scopus 로고
    • Penguin Books, Harmondsworth
    • In some cases, scientists have even fed competitors scientific misinformation in order lead them astray. See, for example, J. D. Watson's account of how he and Crick tried to trick L. Pauling into following false trails in the race towards the first description of the structure of DNA, in Watson, J. D. (1968) The Double Helix, Penguin Books, Harmondsworth.
    • (1968) The Double Helix
    • Watson, J.D.1
  • 6
    • 84965484174 scopus 로고
    • Communication, Competition, and Secrecy: The Production and Dissemination of Research-Related Information in Genetics
    • McCain, K. W. (1991) "Communication, Competition, and Secrecy: The Production and Dissemination of Research-Related Information in Genetics", Science, Technology & Human Values 16 (4): p. 492.
    • (1991) Science, Technology & Human Values , vol.16 , Issue.4 , pp. 492
    • McCain, K.W.1
  • 12
    • 0003822524 scopus 로고
    • Routledge, London: chapters 23 & 24
    • See, for example, Popper's discussion of "mutual rational control by critical discussion" in Popper, K. R. (1966) The Open Society and its Enemies. Volume 2: The High Tide of Prophecy, 5th revised edition, Routledge, London: chapters 23 & 24. A recent formulation of this is found in Shrader-Frechette, K. (1994), Ethics of Scientific Research, Rowman & Littlefièld, Maryland: p. 76.
    • (1966) The Open Society and Its Enemies. Volume 2: The High Tide of Prophecy, 5th Revised Edition , vol.2
    • Popper, K.R.1
  • 13
    • 0004106144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rowman & Littlefièld, Maryland
    • See, for example, Popper's discussion of "mutual rational control by critical discussion" in Popper, K. R. (1966) The Open Society and its Enemies. Volume 2: The High Tide of Prophecy, 5th revised edition, Routledge, London: chapters 23 & 24. A recent formulation of this is found in Shrader-Frechette, K. (1994), Ethics of Scientific Research, Rowman & Littlefièld, Maryland: p. 76.
    • (1994) Ethics of Scientific Research , pp. 76
    • Shrader-Frechette, K.1
  • 17
    • 3343015621 scopus 로고
    • Discourse of the Arts and Sciences
    • London: Everyman's Library, 1983
    • Rousseau, J-J. (1762) "Discourse of the Arts and Sciences", in: The Social Contract and Discourses, London: Everyman's Library, 1983.
    • (1762) The Social Contract and Discourses
    • Rousseau, J.-J.1
  • 19
    • 3342941621 scopus 로고
    • Tännsjö, T. (1994), "In Defence of Science", in; Prawitz, Skyrms & Westerståhl (1994) (eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science in Uppsala. Papers from the 9th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht.
    • (1994) In Defence of Science
    • Tännsjö, T.1
  • 21
    • 3342976153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is clearly shown in both Bergstrom's and Tännsjö's papers
    • This is clearly shown in both Bergstrom's and Tännsjö's papers.
  • 22
    • 3342976156 scopus 로고
    • For discussions of this general problem, see Glover, J. (1975) "'It Makes No Difference Whether or Not I Do It'", in Singer, P. (1986) (ed.) Applied Ethics, Oxford University Press, Oxford; and Parfit, D. (1984) Reasons and Persons, Clarendon Press, Oxford: pp 75 ff.
    • (1975) It Makes No Difference Whether or Not I Do It
    • Glover, J.1
  • 23
    • 0004161580 scopus 로고
    • Oxford University Press, Oxford
    • For discussions of this general problem, see Glover, J. (1975) "'It Makes No Difference Whether or Not I Do It'", in Singer, P. (1986) (ed.) Applied Ethics, Oxford University Press, Oxford; and Parfit, D. (1984) Reasons and Persons, Clarendon Press, Oxford: pp 75 ff.
    • (1986) Applied Ethics
    • Singer, P.1
  • 24
    • 0003740191 scopus 로고
    • Clarendon Press, Oxford
    • For discussions of this general problem, see Glover, J. (1975) "'It Makes No Difference Whether or Not I Do It'", in Singer, P. (1986) (ed.) Applied Ethics, Oxford University Press, Oxford; and Parfit, D. (1984) Reasons and Persons, Clarendon Press, Oxford: pp 75 ff.
    • (1984) Reasons and Persons
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 27
    • 3343017341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, this mechanism is supported by the formal mechanisms of publication in journals after peer-review and copyright regulations
    • Of course, this mechanism is supported by the formal mechanisms of publication in journals after peer-review and copyright regulations.
  • 29
    • 84965484710 scopus 로고
    • Focus on the Uppsala Code of Ethics for Scientists
    • Gustafsson, B., et. al. (1984), "Focus on The Uppsala Code of Ethics for Scientists", Journal of Peace Research 21: 311-316.
    • (1984) Journal of Peace Research , vol.21 , pp. 311-316
    • Gustafsson, B.1
  • 30
    • 0028911125 scopus 로고
    • Predictive Ability of Meta-analyses of Randomised Controlled Trials
    • One suitable example is the above mentioned possibility to make the submission of unpublished scientific information to open repositories obligatory after a certain period of time. This may, for example, be of great value for health-care policy makers, who often base their decisions on so-called meta-studies of the results in different studies of, say, a new method of treatment. Such studies are faced with the problem that studies made by the pharmaceutical industry without producing a patentable product are kept hidden behind the shield of company secrecy. The withholding of the information obtained by these latter studies may of course seriously distort the results of the meta-studies and thereby cause fatal policy decisions within health-care. See, for example, Villar, J., Carroli, G. & Belizán, J. M. (1995) "Predictive Ability of Meta-analyses of Randomised Controlled Trials", Lancet 345: 772-76; and Egger, M. & Davey Smith, G. (1995) "Misleading Meta-analysis", Biomedical Journal 310: 752-54.
    • (1995) Lancet , vol.345 , pp. 772-776
    • Villar, J.1    Carroli, G.2    Belizán, J.M.3
  • 31
    • 0028964587 scopus 로고
    • Misleading Meta-analysis
    • One suitable example is the above mentioned possibility to make the submission of unpublished scientific information to open repositories obligatory after a certain period of time. This may, for example, be of great value for health-care policy makers, who often base their decisions on so-called meta-studies of the results in different studies of, say, a new method of treatment. Such studies are faced with the problem that studies made by the pharmaceutical industry without producing a patentable product are kept hidden behind the shield of company secrecy. The withholding of the information obtained by these latter studies may of course seriously distort the results of the meta-studies and thereby cause fatal policy decisions within health-care. See, for example, Villar, J., Carroli, G. & Belizán, J. M. (1995) "Predictive Ability of Meta-analyses of Randomised Controlled Trials", Lancet 345: 772-76; and Egger, M. & Davey Smith, G. (1995) "Misleading Meta-analysis", Biomedical Journal 310: 752-54.
    • (1995) Biomedical Journal , vol.310 , pp. 752-754
    • Egger, M.1    Davey Smith, G.2
  • 33
    • 0003691257 scopus 로고
    • Locke, J. (1690), Two Treatises of Government; Nozick, R. (1974), Anarchy, State and Utopia, Basil Blackwell, Oxford; and Gauthier, D. (1986) Morals by Agreement, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
    • (1690) Two Treatises of Government
    • Locke, J.1
  • 34
    • 0004273805 scopus 로고
    • Basil Blackwell, Oxford
    • Locke, J. (1690), Two Treatises of Government; Nozick, R. (1974), Anarchy, State and Utopia, Basil Blackwell, Oxford; and Gauthier, D. (1986) Morals by Agreement, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
    • (1974) Anarchy, State and Utopia
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 35
    • 0004274311 scopus 로고
    • Oxford University Press, Oxford
    • Locke, J. (1690), Two Treatises of Government; Nozick, R. (1974), Anarchy, State and Utopia, Basil Blackwell, Oxford; and Gauthier, D. (1986) Morals by Agreement, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
    • (1986) Morals by Agreement
    • Gauthier, D.1
  • 36
    • 0342886527 scopus 로고
    • Revised Draft, AAAS, Washington, D.C.
    • See for example American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS) (1980), Principles of Scientific Freedom and Responsibility, Revised Draft, AAAS, Washington, D.C.: p. 3; Shrader-Frechette, Ethics of Scientific Research, pp. 72 & 77; and Merton (1982) Social Research and the Practising Profession, AH Books, Cambridge, MA, p. 9.
    • (1980) Principles of Scientific Freedom and Responsibility , pp. 3
  • 37
    • 0004106144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See for example American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS) (1980), Principles of Scientific Freedom and Responsibility, Revised Draft, AAAS, Washington, D.C.: p. 3; Shrader-Frechette, Ethics of Scientific Research, pp. 72 & 77; and Merton (1982) Social Research and the Practising Profession, AH Books, Cambridge, MA, p. 9.
    • Ethics of Scientific Research , pp. 72
    • Shrader-Frechette1
  • 38
    • 0003419183 scopus 로고
    • AH Books, Cambridge, MA
    • See for example American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS) (1980), Principles of Scientific Freedom and Responsibility, Revised Draft, AAAS, Washington, D.C.: p. 3; Shrader-Frechette, Ethics of Scientific Research, pp. 72 & 77; and Merton (1982) Social Research and the Practising Profession, AH Books, Cambridge, MA, p. 9.
    • (1982) Social Research and the Practising Profession , pp. 9
    • Merton1
  • 40
    • 0009389322 scopus 로고
    • Clarendon Press, Oxford, chapters 4-8
    • Comprehensive critical discussions of the distinction are found in Bennet, J. (1995) The Act Itself, Clarendon Press, Oxford, chapters 4-8; Glover (1977) Causing Death and Saving Lives, Penguin books, Harmondsworth. chapter 7; and Kagan, S. (1989) The Limits of Morality, Clarendon Press, Oxford, chapter 3.
    • (1995) The Act Itself
    • Bennet, J.1
  • 41
    • 0003833682 scopus 로고
    • Penguin books, Harmondsworth. chapter 7
    • Comprehensive critical discussions of the distinction are found in Bennet, J. (1995) The Act Itself, Clarendon Press, Oxford, chapters 4-8; Glover (1977) Causing Death and Saving Lives, Penguin books, Harmondsworth. chapter 7; and Kagan, S. (1989) The Limits of Morality, Clarendon Press, Oxford, chapter 3.
    • (1977) Causing Death and Saving Lives
    • Glover1
  • 42
    • 0004068219 scopus 로고
    • Clarendon Press, Oxford, chapter 3
    • Comprehensive critical discussions of the distinction are found in Bennet, J. (1995) The Act Itself, Clarendon Press, Oxford, chapters 4-8; Glover (1977) Causing Death and Saving Lives, Penguin books, Harmondsworth. chapter 7; and Kagan, S. (1989) The Limits of Morality, Clarendon Press, Oxford, chapter 3.
    • (1989) The Limits of Morality
    • Kagan, S.1
  • 45
    • 0004106144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • C.f., Shrader-Frechette, Ethics of Scientific Research, pp. 72-78. However, Shrader-Frechette tends to glide from the individual moral question regarding to what extent scientists and other individual agents in the scientific community may be justified in withholding scientific information, to the political question regarding whether or not scientists are more fit than others to make science- and technology-related political decisions. We concur with Shrader-Frechette's firm negative answer to the second question. But this does not answer the first one.
    • Ethics of Scientific Research , pp. 72-78
    • Shrader-Frechette1
  • 46
    • 3342991606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This conclusion could theoretically be avoided if Mill's principle is allowed to apply also to collectives. However, not only would this seem to violate the purely individualist prerequisite of classical liberalism, it would also create several problems of which we can only give one example here. In the present case, a "Mill view" which is also applicable to collectives would seem to give the rather strange message that it is forbidden not to inform the public (seen as one collective agent) but, at the same time, permissible not to inform each of those individuals who make up the public.
  • 47
    • 3342912061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • All correspondence should be directed to Christian Munthe. We wish to thank two anonymous referees of Science and Engineering Ethics for their many helpful suggestions on the first version on this paper. A draft version was presented at the 10th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Florence, Italy, 19-25 August 1995.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.