메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 27, Issue 2, 1996, Pages 251-269

Aristotelian chemistry: A prelude to Duhemian metaphysics

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0030160861     PISSN: 00393681     EISSN: 18792510     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1016/0039-3681(95)00047-X     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (8)

References (36)
  • 1
    • 0011408834 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's conception of chemical combination
    • 1 Harold H. Joachim, 'Aristotle's Conception of Chemical Combination', Journal of Philology 29 (1904), 72-86.
    • (1904) Journal of Philology , vol.29 , pp. 72-86
    • Joachim, H.H.1
  • 2
    • 84976651895 scopus 로고
    • Chemical combination according to Aristotle
    • and references cited therein
    • 2 e.g. J. E. Bolzan, 'Chemical Combination According to Aristotle', Ambix 23 (1976), 134-144, and references cited therein.
    • (1976) Ambix , vol.23 , pp. 134-144
    • Bolzan, J.E.1
  • 3
    • 0003780563 scopus 로고
    • Paris: C. Naud, reprinted Paris: Fayard
    • 3 Pierre Duhem, Le mixte et la combinaison chimique: Essai sur l'évolution d'une idée (Paris: C. Naud, 1902; reprinted Paris: Fayard, 1985). Originally published as 'La notion de mixte: Essai historique et critique', Revue de Philosophie 1 (1900), 69-99, 167-197, 331-357, 430-467, 730-745.
    • (1902) Le Mixte et la Combinaison Chimique: Essai sur L'évolution D'une Idée
    • Duhem, P.1
  • 4
    • 29544449277 scopus 로고
    • La notion de mixte: Essai historique et critique
    • 3 Pierre Duhem, Le mixte et la combinaison chimique: Essai sur l'évolution d'une idée (Paris: C. Naud, 1902; reprinted Paris: Fayard, 1985). Originally published as 'La notion de mixte: Essai historique et critique', Revue de Philosophie 1 (1900), 69-99, 167-197, 331-357, 430-467, 730-745.
    • (1900) Revue de Philosophie , vol.1 , pp. 69-99
  • 5
    • 85029961913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 1, pp. 74-75
    • 4 Op. cit., note 1, pp. 74-75.
  • 6
    • 85029961269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 3, p. 12
    • 5 Op. cit., note 3, p. 12.
  • 7
    • 0011404089 scopus 로고
    • Semantics for mass terms with quantifiers
    • 6 Peter Röper, 'Semantics for Mass Terms With Quantifiers', Nous 17 (1983), 251-265, calls this the distributive reference condition and defines a homogeneous predicate as one which satisfies, in addition, a cumulative reference condition (φ(π) ∧ φ(ρ)) ⊃ φ(π∪ρ).
    • (1983) Nous , vol.17 , pp. 251-265
    • Röper, P.1
  • 8
    • 0011495708 scopus 로고
    • translated by E. S. Forster Loeb Classical Library, London: Heinemann
    • 7 Aristotle, On Coming-to-be and Passing-away, translated by E. S. Forster (Loeb Classical Library, London: Heinemann, 1955), I. 10.
    • (1955) On Coming-to-be and Passing-away , vol.1 , pp. 10
    • Aristotle1
  • 9
    • 85029972130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 1, p. 74
    • 8 Op. cit., note 1, p. 74.
  • 10
    • 85029963861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 1, p. 75
    • 9 Op. cit., note 1, p. 75.
  • 11
    • 85029968980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 10 Cf. Metaphysics, VIII.5: 'There is ... a certain problem over why it is that wine is not the matter of vinegar, nor is it potentially vinegar, even though vinegar comes from it; ... it is not the wine but the water that is the matter of the vinegar.... All things that change into one another ... must revert to their matter ... vinegar first turns to water and from there becomes wine', translated by David Bostock, Aristotle's Metaphysics, Books Z and H (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994). Bostock suggests there is an unintended temporal implication here, and continues 'There is no more need for an intermediate stage here (if wine is to come from vinegar) than there was in the change from wine to vinegar. All that needs to be insisted upon is that neither is made of the other though there is a common matter that both are made of' (p. 278). It is argued in the paper that mixts cannot be said to have water as a component element if this does not mean that the mixt can come from, or can become, water. As for Aristotle's initial problem in this passage, perhaps wine is not potentially vinegar because this possibility is not encompassed by what Sarah Waterlow describes as 'the power of the natural substance to attain structure ... there (being) only one type of change that depends on the specific structure, namely that which results in the latter's full development. Aristotle ... identifies the behaviour that manifests substantial nature with a mere sub-class of all behavings of which the substance in question is physically capable', Nature, Change, and Agency in Aristotle's Physics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), pp. 36-37.
    • Metaphysics , vol.8 , pp. 5
  • 12
    • 0011495709 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • 10 Cf. Metaphysics, VIII.5: 'There is ... a certain problem over why it is that wine is not the matter of vinegar, nor is it potentially vinegar, even though vinegar comes from it; ... it is not the wine but the water that is the matter of the vinegar.... All things that change into one another ... must revert to their matter ... vinegar first turns to water and from there becomes wine', translated by David Bostock, Aristotle's Metaphysics, Books Z and H (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994). Bostock suggests there is an unintended temporal implication here, and continues 'There is no more need for an intermediate stage here (if wine is to come from vinegar) than there was in the change from wine to vinegar. All that needs to be insisted upon is that neither is made of the other though there is a common matter that both are made of' (p. 278). It is argued in the paper that mixts cannot be said to have water as a component element if this does not mean that the mixt can come from, or can become, water. As for Aristotle's initial problem in this passage, perhaps wine is not potentially vinegar because this possibility is not encompassed by what Sarah Waterlow describes as 'the power of the natural substance to attain structure ... there (being) only one type of change that depends on the specific structure, namely that which results in the latter's full development. Aristotle ... identifies the behaviour that manifests substantial nature with a mere sub-class of all behavings of which the substance in question is physically capable', Nature, Change, and Agency in Aristotle's Physics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), pp. 36-37.
    • (1994) Aristotle's Metaphysics, Books Z and H , pp. 278
    • Bostock, D.1
  • 13
    • 0003871297 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • 10 Cf. Metaphysics, VIII.5: 'There is ... a certain problem over why it is that wine is not the matter of vinegar, nor is it potentially vinegar, even though vinegar comes from it; ... it is not the wine but the water that is the matter of the vinegar.... All things that change into one another ... must revert to their matter ... vinegar first turns to water and from there becomes wine', translated by David Bostock, Aristotle's Metaphysics, Books Z and H (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994). Bostock suggests there is an unintended temporal implication here, and continues 'There is no more need for an intermediate stage here (if wine is to come from vinegar) than there was in the change from wine to vinegar. All that needs to be insisted upon is that neither is made of the other though there is a common matter that both are made of' (p. 278). It is argued in the paper that mixts cannot be said to have water as a component element if this does not mean that the mixt can come from, or can become, water. As for Aristotle's initial problem in this passage, perhaps wine is not potentially vinegar because this possibility is not encompassed by what Sarah Waterlow describes as 'the power of the natural substance to attain structure ... there (being) only one type of change that depends on the specific structure, namely that which results in the latter's full development. Aristotle ... identifies the behaviour that manifests substantial nature with a mere sub-class of all behavings of which the substance in question is physically capable', Nature, Change, and Agency in Aristotle's Physics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), pp. 36-37.
    • (1982) Nature, Change, and Agency in Aristotle's Physics , pp. 36-37
  • 14
    • 85029960545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Duhem, op. cit., note 3, p. 25
    • 11 Duhem, op. cit., note 3, p. 25.
  • 15
    • 85029971128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 1, p. 77
    • 12 Op. cit., note 1, p. 77.
  • 16
    • 85029970557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 1, p. 81
    • 13 Op. cit., note 1, p. 81.
  • 17
    • 85029963394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, op. cit., note 7, II.3
    • 14 Aristotle, op. cit., note 7, II.3.
  • 18
    • 85029970476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 7, II.3
    • 15 Op. cit., note 7, II.3.
  • 19
    • 85029962987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 1, p. 81
    • 16 Op. cit., note 1, p. 81.
  • 20
    • 85029966501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Joachim, op. cit., note 1, pp. 81-82
    • 17 Joachim, op. cit., note 1, pp. 81-82.
  • 21
    • 85029969543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Joachim, op cit., note 1, p. 82
    • 18 Joachim, op cit., note 1, p. 82.
  • 22
    • 85029961638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 1, pp. 82-83
    • 19 Op. cit., note 1, pp. 82-83.
  • 23
    • 0004182806 scopus 로고
    • reprinted, London: Dent
    • 20 Robert Boyle, The Sceptical Chymist (1661; reprinted, London: Dent, 1911), p. 81.
    • (1661) The Sceptical Chymist , pp. 81
    • Boyle, R.1
  • 24
    • 0011447931 scopus 로고
    • Paris: A. Joanin, reprinted Paris: Vrin
    • 21 Pierre Duhem, L'evolution de la mécanique (Paris: A. Joanin, 1903; reprinted Paris: Vrin, 1992), p. 8.
    • (1903) L'evolution de la Mécanique , pp. 8
    • Duhem, P.1
  • 25
    • 85029965334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Macroscopic objects: An exercise in Duhemian Ontology
    • I discuss this distinction in more detail in forthcoming in
    • 22 I discuss this distinction in more detail in 'Macroscopic Objects: An Exercise in Duhemian Ontology', forthcoming in Philosophy of Science.
    • Philosophy of Science
  • 26
    • 85029964578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Röper, op. cit., note 6, p. 261, who also lays down an appropriate analogue for the cumulative reference condition
    • 23 Cf. Röper, op. cit., note 6, p. 261, who also lays down an appropriate analogue for the cumulative reference condition.
  • 27
    • 85029963838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 20, p. 82
    • 24 Op. cit., note 20, p. 82.
  • 28
    • 85029968921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 3, p. 183
    • 25 Op. cit., note 3, p. 183.
  • 29
    • 85029964156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 7, I.10
    • 26 Op. cit., note 7, I.10.
  • 30
    • 85029960922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op. cit., note 2, p. 141
    • 27 Op. cit., note 2, p. 141.
  • 31
    • 85029965839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Op cit., note 1, p.76, fn 4
    • 28 Op cit., note 1, p.76, fn 4.
  • 32
    • 85029962048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or at least not necessarily discrete. There might not actually be a quantity whose degree of some quality is intermediate between two given degrees. A proper formulation would have to take account of the temporal factor, and is not pursued here
    • 29 Or at least not necessarily discrete. There might not actually be a quantity whose degree of some quality is intermediate between two given degrees. A proper formulation would have to take account of the temporal factor, and is not pursued here.
  • 33
    • 85029963910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Waterlow, op. cit., note 10, p. 85
    • 30 Waterlow, op. cit., note 10, p. 85.
  • 34
    • 85029964907 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Waterlow, op. cit., note 10, p. 87, fn.
    • 31 Waterlow, op. cit., note 10, p. 87, fn.
  • 35
    • 85029962400 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 32 Stated in terms of the theory of mass predicates, what is possible is the mass disjunction of being water and being sugar. Mass disjunction involves existential quantification over the parts, but this existential quantification cannot be moved outside the scope of the possibility operator. There are no two mutually separate and jointly exhaustive parts of the sugared water one of which is possibly water and the other possibly sugar.
  • 36
    • 85029962095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 33 A view more like the Stoic conception of mixture is offered in the article mentioned in note 22. Whether some alternative formulation can be found which does not rely on the predication of a distinct domain of quantities persisting through change - for example, in terms, of states applying to spatial regions at various times - remains to be seen. Note that spatial regions considered in the traditional Newtonian way persist through time.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.