-
1
-
-
0011696616
-
Experience, knowledge and value: A rejoinder
-
P. Schilpp (ed.), New York: Tudor
-
1 J. Dewey, 'Experience, Knowledge and Value: A Rejoinder', in P. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of John Dewey (New York: Tudor, 1939), pp. 515-608.
-
(1939)
The Philosophy of John Dewey
, pp. 515-608
-
-
Dewey, J.1
-
2
-
-
8744297726
-
Studies in logical theory
-
J. A. Boydston (ed.), [hereafter, MW] Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, see p. 310
-
2 J. Dewey, 'Studies in Logical Theory', in J. A. Boydston (ed.), John Dewey: The Middle Works, Vol. 2, 1901-1903 [hereafter, MW] (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1976), see p. 310.
-
(1976)
John Dewey: The Middle Works
, vol.2
, pp. 1901-1903
-
-
Dewey, J.1
-
3
-
-
0001112420
-
Logic: A theory of inquiry
-
J. A. Boydston (ed.), [hereafter, LW] Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press
-
3 J. Dewey, 'Logic: A Theory of Inquiry', in J. A. Boydston (ed.), John Dewey: The Later Works, Vol. 12, 1925-1953 [hereafter, LW] (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986). For example, Dewey wrote How We Think, MW: Vol. 6, pp. 177-356, to show the correspondence between thinking and inquiry. Dewey also reissued Studies in Logical Theory under the title Essays in Experimental Logic, MW: Vol. 10, pp. 317-394, including a rejoinder to criticisms of the earlier book.
-
(1986)
John Dewey: The Later Works
, vol.12
, pp. 1925-1953
-
-
Dewey, J.1
-
4
-
-
85029963397
-
-
to show the correspondence between thinking and inquiry
-
3 J. Dewey, 'Logic: A Theory of Inquiry', in J. A. Boydston (ed.), John Dewey: The Later Works, Vol. 12, 1925-1953 [hereafter, LW] (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986). For example, Dewey wrote How We Think, MW: Vol. 6, pp. 177-356, to show the correspondence between thinking and inquiry. Dewey also reissued Studies in Logical Theory under the title Essays in Experimental Logic, MW: Vol. 10, pp. 317-394, including a rejoinder to criticisms of the earlier book.
-
How We Think, MW
, vol.6
, pp. 177-356
-
-
Dewey1
-
5
-
-
85029966297
-
-
including a rejoinder to criticisms of the earlier book
-
3 J. Dewey, 'Logic: A Theory of Inquiry', in J. A. Boydston (ed.), John Dewey: The Later Works, Vol. 12, 1925-1953 [hereafter, LW] (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986). For example, Dewey wrote How We Think, MW: Vol. 6, pp. 177-356, to show the correspondence between thinking and inquiry. Dewey also reissued Studies in Logical Theory under the title Essays in Experimental Logic, MW: Vol. 10, pp. 317-394, including a rejoinder to criticisms of the earlier book.
-
Studies in Logical Theory under the Title Essays in Experimental Logic, MW
, vol.10
, pp. 317-394
-
-
Dewey1
-
6
-
-
0003845903
-
-
New York: Modern Library
-
4 Dewey scholars adopting the continuity thesis include: J. Ratner, Intelligence in the Modern World (New York: Modern Library, 1939), p. 155; J. Ratner and R. Altman (eds), John Dewey and Arthur Bentley: A Philosophical Correspondence, 1932-1951 (New Brunswick, 1964), pp. 36-39; E. Nagel, 'Introduction', LW: Vol. 12, pp. ix-xxvii; S. Hook, 'Introduction', in MW: Vol. 2, p. xvi; and R. Sleeper, The Necessity of Pragmatism (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1986), pp. 4-5.
-
(1939)
Intelligence in the Modern World
, pp. 155
-
-
Ratner, J.1
-
7
-
-
0011573337
-
-
New Brunswick
-
4 Dewey scholars adopting the continuity thesis include: J. Ratner, Intelligence in the Modern World (New York: Modern Library, 1939), p. 155; J. Ratner and R. Altman (eds), John Dewey and Arthur Bentley: A Philosophical Correspondence, 1932-1951 (New Brunswick, 1964), pp. 36-39; E. Nagel, 'Introduction', LW: Vol. 12, pp. ix-xxvii; S. Hook, 'Introduction', in MW: Vol. 2, p. xvi; and R. Sleeper, The Necessity of Pragmatism (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1986), pp. 4-5.
-
(1964)
John Dewey and Arthur Bentley: A Philosophical Correspondence, 1932-1951
, pp. 36-39
-
-
Ratner, J.1
Altman, R.2
-
8
-
-
85029963544
-
Introduction
-
4 Dewey scholars adopting the continuity thesis include: J. Ratner, Intelligence in the Modern World (New York: Modern Library, 1939), p. 155; J. Ratner and R. Altman (eds), John Dewey and Arthur Bentley: A Philosophical Correspondence, 1932-1951 (New Brunswick, 1964), pp. 36-39; E. Nagel, 'Introduction', LW: Vol. 12, pp. ix-xxvii; S. Hook, 'Introduction', in MW: Vol. 2, p. xvi; and R. Sleeper, The Necessity of Pragmatism (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1986), pp. 4-5.
-
LW
, vol.12
, pp. 9-27
-
-
Nagel, E.1
-
9
-
-
85029969635
-
Introduction
-
4 Dewey scholars adopting the continuity thesis include: J. Ratner, Intelligence in the Modern World (New York: Modern Library, 1939), p. 155; J. Ratner and R. Altman (eds), John Dewey and Arthur Bentley: A Philosophical Correspondence, 1932-1951 (New Brunswick, 1964), pp. 36-39; E. Nagel, 'Introduction', LW: Vol. 12, pp. ix-xxvii; S. Hook, 'Introduction', in MW: Vol. 2, p. xvi; and R. Sleeper, The Necessity of Pragmatism (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1986), pp. 4-5.
-
MW
, vol.2
, pp. 16
-
-
Hook, S.1
-
10
-
-
0004116756
-
-
New Haven: Yale University Press
-
4 Dewey scholars adopting the continuity thesis include: J. Ratner, Intelligence in the Modern World (New York: Modern Library, 1939), p. 155; J. Ratner and R. Altman (eds), John Dewey and Arthur Bentley: A Philosophical Correspondence, 1932-1951 (New Brunswick, 1964), pp. 36-39; E. Nagel, 'Introduction', LW: Vol. 12, pp. ix-xxvii; S. Hook, 'Introduction', in MW: Vol. 2, p. xvi; and R. Sleeper, The Necessity of Pragmatism (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1986), pp. 4-5.
-
(1986)
The Necessity of Pragmatism
, pp. 4-5
-
-
Sleeper, R.1
-
11
-
-
0347915209
-
From absolutism to experimentalism
-
R. Bernstein (ed.), New York: Bobbs-Merrill
-
5 J. Dewey, 'From Absolutism to Experimentalism', in R. Bernstein (ed.), John Dewey: On Experience, Nature and Freedom (New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1960), p. 14.
-
(1960)
John Dewey: On Experience, Nature and Freedom
, pp. 14
-
-
Dewey, J.1
-
12
-
-
85029969639
-
-
note 4
-
6 Nagel, op. cit., note 4, p. xviii.
-
LW
, pp. 18
-
-
Nagel1
-
13
-
-
0001031614
-
From absolutism to experimentalism
-
7 J. Dewey, 'From Absolutism to Experimentalism', LW: Vol. 5, p. 12.
-
LW
, vol.5
, pp. 12
-
-
Dewey, J.1
-
14
-
-
0011653717
-
-
London: Allen and Unwin
-
8 For pertinent passages from Hegel, see A. V. Miller, Hegel's Science of Logic (London: Allen and Unwin, 1969), pp. 67-71; and A. V. Miller, Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977), pp. 13-16.
-
(1969)
Hegel's Science of Logic
, pp. 67-71
-
-
Miller, A.V.1
-
15
-
-
0004232279
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press
-
8 For pertinent passages from Hegel, see A. V. Miller, Hegel's Science of Logic (London: Allen and Unwin, 1969), pp. 67-71; and A. V. Miller, Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977), pp. 13-16.
-
(1977)
Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit
, pp. 13-16
-
-
Miller, A.V.1
-
16
-
-
84924288937
-
-
note 7
-
9 Dewey, op. cit., note 7, p. 10.
-
LW
, pp. 10
-
-
Dewey1
-
17
-
-
85029967930
-
-
10 ibid. p. 12.
-
LW
, pp. 12
-
-
-
18
-
-
85029972698
-
The evolutionary method as applied to morality: Its scientific necessity
-
Dewey acknowledged his intellectual debt to Thomas H. Huxley, a nineteenth-century zoologist
-
11 Dewey speculated, for example, that the competing perspectives of morphology and physiology could be reconciled in experimental studies because biological structures and functions were linked through a common 'chemico-physical process'. See 'The Evolutionary Method as Applied to Morality: Its Scientific Necessity', MW: Vol. 2, p. 15. Dewey acknowledged his intellectual debt to Thomas H. Huxley, a nineteenth-century zoologist. See Schilpp (ed.), op. cit., note 1, p. 10. Huxley argued that experimental embryologists such as Karl von Baer were better able than Darwin to account for the developmental patterns underlying human evolution. See T. H. Huxley and A. Henfrey (eds), Scientific Memoirs (London: Taylor and Francis, 1853; reprinted New York: Johnson Corporation, 1966), and M. A. di Gregorio, T. H. Huxley's Place in Natural Science (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984), pp. 26-33.
-
MW
, vol.2
, pp. 15
-
-
-
19
-
-
85029967742
-
-
See Schilpp (ed.), note 1, Huxley argued that experimental embryologists such as Karl von Baer were better able than Darwin to account for the developmental patterns underlying human evolution
-
11 Dewey speculated, for example, that the competing perspectives of morphology and physiology could be reconciled in experimental studies because biological structures and functions were linked through a common 'chemico-physical process'. See 'The Evolutionary Method as Applied to Morality: Its Scientific Necessity', MW: Vol. 2, p. 15. Dewey acknowledged his intellectual debt to Thomas H. Huxley, a nineteenth-century zoologist. See Schilpp (ed.), op. cit., note 1, p. 10. Huxley argued that experimental embryologists such as Karl von Baer were better able than Darwin to account for the developmental patterns underlying human evolution. See T. H. Huxley and A. Henfrey (eds), Scientific Memoirs (London: Taylor and Francis, 1853; reprinted New York: Johnson Corporation, 1966), and M. A. di Gregorio, T. H. Huxley's Place in Natural Science (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984), pp. 26-33.
-
The Philosophy of John Dewey
, pp. 10
-
-
Hauxley, T.H.1
-
20
-
-
0011695747
-
-
London: Taylor and Francis; reprinted New York: Johnson Corporation
-
11 Dewey speculated, for example, that the competing perspectives of morphology and physiology could be reconciled in experimental studies because biological structures and functions were linked through a common 'chemico-physical process'. See 'The Evolutionary Method as Applied to Morality: Its Scientific Necessity', MW: Vol. 2, p. 15. Dewey acknowledged his intellectual debt to Thomas H. Huxley, a nineteenth-century zoologist. See Schilpp (ed.), op. cit., note 1, p. 10. Huxley argued that experimental embryologists such as Karl von Baer were better able than Darwin to account for the developmental patterns underlying human evolution. See T. H. Huxley and A. Henfrey (eds), Scientific Memoirs (London: Taylor and Francis, 1853; reprinted New York: Johnson Corporation, 1966), and M. A. di Gregorio, T. H. Huxley's Place in Natural Science (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984), pp. 26-33.
-
(1853)
Scientific Memoirs
-
-
Huxley, T.H.1
Henfrey, A.2
-
21
-
-
0003890698
-
-
New Haven: Yale University Press
-
11 Dewey speculated, for example, that the competing perspectives of morphology and physiology could be reconciled in experimental studies because biological structures and functions were linked through a common 'chemico-physical process'. See 'The Evolutionary Method as Applied to Morality: Its Scientific Necessity', MW: Vol. 2, p. 15. Dewey acknowledged his intellectual debt to Thomas H. Huxley, a nineteenth-century zoologist. See Schilpp (ed.), op. cit., note 1, p. 10. Huxley argued that experimental embryologists such as Karl von Baer were better able than Darwin to account for the developmental patterns underlying human evolution. See T. H. Huxley and A. Henfrey (eds), Scientific Memoirs (London: Taylor and Francis, 1853; reprinted New York: Johnson Corporation, 1966), and M. A. di Gregorio, T. H. Huxley's Place in Natural Science (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984), pp. 26-33.
-
(1984)
T. H. Huxley's Place in Natural Science
, pp. 26-33
-
-
Di Gregorio, M.A.1
-
22
-
-
0003426044
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Peirce also chided Dewey by saying: 'There is no anatomy of possibilities because no one can say in advance how pure possibilities vary or diverge from one another... What renders a comparative anatomy possible is that certain conceivable forms do not appear' (ibid.). Interestingly, McGraw anticipated this problem by devising a means to reveal the variety of behavioral forms hidden in the developmental process
-
12 American pragmatist Charles Peirce criticized Dewey's failure in Studies to show how physiology could possibly elucidate the evolution of function or how comparative anatomy could be applied to the 'anatomy of thought'. A. W. Burks (ed.) Collected Papers of C. S. Peirce (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1958), p., 181. Peirce also chided Dewey by saying: 'There is no anatomy of possibilities because no one can say in advance how pure possibilities vary or diverge from one another... What renders a comparative anatomy possible is that certain conceivable forms do not appear' (ibid.). Interestingly, McGraw anticipated this problem by devising a means to reveal the variety of behavioral forms hidden in the developmental process.
-
(1958)
Collected Papers of C. S. Peirce
, pp. 181
-
-
Burks, A.W.1
-
23
-
-
85029968369
-
-
New York City, 10 October, conducted by the Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois
-
13 Nagel found this tendency frustrating when he recalled in an interview that, 'he [Dewey] introduced fundamental questions without preparing his readers for them'. Nagel added: 'One didn't quite know what the argument was until you had the wit to discover that he was discussing a position related to the one he was advancing'. Interview with Ernest Nagel, New York City, 10 October 1966, conducted by the Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois, p. 4.
-
(1966)
Interview with Ernest Nagel
, pp. 4
-
-
-
24
-
-
85029967834
-
-
14 MW: Vol. 12.
-
MW
, vol.12
-
-
-
29
-
-
0024747484
-
Johnny's a gentleman but Jimmy's a Mug
-
Press Coverage During the 1930s of Myrtle McGraw's Study of Johnny and Jimmy Woods'
-
18 See P. Dennis, ' "Johnny's a Gentleman but Jimmy's a Mug": Press Coverage During the 1930s of Myrtle McGraw's Study of Johnny and Jimmy Woods', Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 25 (1989), 356-370.
-
(1989)
Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences
, vol.25
, pp. 356-370
-
-
Dennis, P.1
-
30
-
-
0011686341
-
The contemporary setting of the pioneer
-
Meyer wrote extensively about the latest scientific advances in the nervous system and proposed theories, which Dewey read, about the structure and function of neurons
-
19 Adolf Meyer was a close personal friend of Dewey whom Meyer first met when he lectured as a docent at the University of Chicago from 1893-1895. Meyer acknowledged C. L. Herrick's pioneering role in the study of the brain and nervous system and impressive command of philosophical and psychological issues and concepts. See A. Meyer's intellectual tribute to Herrick, 'The Contemporary Setting of the Pioneer', Journal of Comparative Neurology 74 (1941), 1-24. Meyer wrote extensively about the latest scientific advances in the nervous system and proposed theories, which Dewey read, about the structure and function of neurons. See, for example, A. Meyer, 'Critical Review of the Data and General Methods and Deductions of Modern Neurology', Journal of Comparative Neurology 8 (1898), 249-313. Dewey was familiar with Sullivan's conception of 'selective inattention', which he used in his classes when explaining the process of judgment.
-
(1941)
Journal of Comparative Neurology
, vol.74
, pp. 1-24
-
-
Meyer, A.1
-
31
-
-
0011686341
-
Critical review of the data and general methods and deductions of modern neurology
-
Dewey was familiar with Sullivan's conception of 'selective inattention', which he used in his classes when explaining the process of judgment
-
19 Adolf Meyer was a close personal friend of Dewey whom Meyer first met when he lectured as a docent at the University of Chicago from 1893-1895. Meyer acknowledged C. L. Herrick's pioneering role in the study of the brain and nervous system and impressive command of philosophical and psychological issues and concepts. See A. Meyer's intellectual tribute to Herrick, 'The Contemporary Setting of the Pioneer', Journal of Comparative Neurology 74 (1941), 1-24. Meyer wrote extensively about the latest scientific advances in the nervous system and proposed theories, which Dewey read, about the structure and function of neurons. See, for example, A. Meyer, 'Critical Review of the Data and General Methods and Deductions of Modern Neurology', Journal of Comparative Neurology 8 (1898), 249-313. Dewey was familiar with Sullivan's conception of 'selective inattention', which he used in his classes when explaining the process of judgment.
-
(1898)
Journal of Comparative Neurology
, vol.8
, pp. 249-313
-
-
Meyer, A.1
-
32
-
-
0026120653
-
Psychobiology
-
20 D. A. Dewsbury, 'Psychobiology', American Psychologist 46 (1991), 198-205. See also A. Meyer, 'The Psychobiological Point of View', in E. Winters (ed.), The Collected Papers of Adolf Meyer, Vol. 3 (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1950-1952).
-
(1991)
American Psychologist
, vol.46
, pp. 198-205
-
-
Dewsbury, D.A.1
-
33
-
-
34250366816
-
The psychobiological point of view
-
E. Winters (ed.), Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press
-
20 D. A. Dewsbury, 'Psychobiology', American Psychologist 46 (1991), 198-205. See also A. Meyer, 'The Psychobiological Point of View', in E. Winters (ed.), The Collected Papers of Adolf Meyer, Vol. 3 (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1950-1952).
-
(1950)
The Collected Papers of Adolf Meyer
, vol.3
-
-
Meyer, A.1
-
34
-
-
0011572533
-
Psychological corollaries of modern neurological discoveries
-
21 See, for example, 'Psychological Corollaries of Modern Neurological Discoveries', Journal of Comparative Neurology 7 (1896), 155-161, and 'The Vital Equilibrium and the Nervous System', Science 7 (1898), 813-818. Dewey mentioned these works and others in his three-quarter class 'Theory of Logic' taught in the 1899-1900 school year. The Joseph Ratner Papers, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois.
-
(1896)
Journal of Comparative Neurology
, vol.7
, pp. 155-161
-
-
-
35
-
-
0011697943
-
The vital equilibrium and the nervous system
-
Dewey mentioned these works and others in his three-quarter class 'Theory of Logic' taught in the 1899-1900 school year. The Joseph Ratner Papers, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois
-
21 See, for example, 'Psychological Corollaries of Modern Neurological Discoveries', Journal of Comparative Neurology 7 (1896), 155-161, and 'The Vital Equilibrium and the Nervous System', Science 7 (1898), 813-818. Dewey mentioned these works and others in his three-quarter class 'Theory of Logic' taught in the 1899-1900 school year. The Joseph Ratner Papers, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois.
-
(1898)
Science
, vol.7
, pp. 813-818
-
-
-
36
-
-
84875175729
-
-
Minneapolis, MN: S. M. Williams; reprint. New York: Arno Press. Lotze sketched the psychological principles he believed underpinned logic. Herrick took the opportunity afforded by his translation to write an afterword on the 'Structure of the Brain', identifying evidence from neuroanatomy that supported Lotze's propositions about the integrative role that consciousness, mind and memory play in human thought and understanding
-
22 H. Lotze, Outlines of Psychology (Minneapolis, MN: S. M. Williams, 1885; reprint. New York: Arno Press, 1973). Lotze sketched the psychological principles he believed underpinned logic. Herrick took the opportunity afforded by his translation to write an afterword on the 'Structure of the Brain', identifying evidence from neuroanatomy that supported Lotze's propositions about the integrative role that consciousness, mind and memory play in human thought and understanding.
-
(1885)
Outlines of Psychology
-
-
Lotze, H.1
-
37
-
-
0002507918
-
Clarence Luther Herrick: Pioneer naturalist, teacher and psychobiologist
-
23 Accounts of Herrick's career and his difficulties with the University of Chicago can be found in C. J. Herrick, 'Clarence Luther Herrick: Pioneer Naturalist, Teacher and Psychobiologist', Transactions of the American Philosophical Society 45 (1955), 1-85, and W. F. Windle, The Pioneering Role of Clarence Luther Herrick in American Neuroscience (Hicksville, NY: Exposition Press, 1979). Meyer indicated that Herrick's troubles with President Harper dissuaded him from joining the faculty at the University of Chicago, op. cit., note 19, p. 15.
-
(1955)
Transactions of the American Philosophical Society
, vol.45
, pp. 1-85
-
-
Herrick, C.J.1
-
38
-
-
0004115977
-
-
Hicksville, NY: Exposition Press
-
23 Accounts of Herrick's career and his difficulties with the University of Chicago can be found in C. J. Herrick, 'Clarence Luther Herrick: Pioneer Naturalist, Teacher and Psychobiologist', Transactions of the American Philosophical Society 45 (1955), 1-85, and W. F. Windle, The Pioneering Role of Clarence Luther Herrick in American Neuroscience (Hicksville, NY: Exposition Press, 1979). Meyer indicated that Herrick's troubles with President Harper dissuaded him from joining the faculty at the University of Chicago, op. cit., note 19, p. 15.
-
(1979)
The Pioneering Role of Clarence Luther Herrick in American Neuroscience
-
-
Windle, W.F.1
-
39
-
-
85029968878
-
-
note 19
-
23 Accounts of Herrick's career and his difficulties with the University of Chicago can be found in C. J. Herrick, 'Clarence Luther Herrick: Pioneer Naturalist, Teacher and Psychobiologist', Transactions of the American Philosophical Society 45 (1955), 1-85, and W. F. Windle, The Pioneering Role of Clarence Luther Herrick in American Neuroscience (Hicksville, NY: Exposition Press, 1979). Meyer indicated that Herrick's troubles with President Harper dissuaded him from joining the faculty at the University of Chicago, op. cit., note 19, p. 15.
-
Journal of Comparative Neurology
, pp. 15
-
-
-
40
-
-
0001416925
-
The origin and evolution of the cerebellum
-
24 C. J. Herrick, 'The Origin and Evolution of the Cerebellum', Archives of Neurology and Psychology 2 (1924), 621-652.
-
(1924)
Archives of Neurology and Psychology
, vol.2
, pp. 621-652
-
-
Herrick, C.J.1
-
41
-
-
37049234750
-
The evolution of intelligence and its origins
-
that consciousness reflected the pause between anticipation and consummation of an act during which central and peripheral reactions are coordinated
-
25 Herrick argued in 'The Evolution of Intelligence and its Origins', Science 3 (1910), 7-18, that consciousness reflected the pause between anticipation and consummation of an act during which central and peripheral reactions are coordinated. Later, in 'Some Reflections on the Origin and Significance of the Cerebral Cortex', The Journal of Animal Behavior (1913), 222-236, Herrick claimed the neurological evidence strongly supported Dewey's conception of behavior as an 'organic circuit' by saying that the "'backstroke'" action of motor discharge...may in a literal physiological sense act into the cortical stimulus complex and become an integral part of it' (p. 233).
-
(1910)
Science
, vol.3
, pp. 7-18
-
-
Herrick1
-
42
-
-
0003388838
-
Some reflections on the origin and significance of the cerebral cortex
-
Herrick claimed the neurological evidence strongly supported Dewey's conception of behavior as an 'organic circuit' by saying that the "'backstroke'" action of motor discharge...may in a literal physiological sense act into the cortical stimulus complex and become an integral part of it' (p. 233)
-
25 Herrick argued in 'The Evolution of Intelligence and its Origins', Science 3 (1910), 7-18, that consciousness reflected the pause between anticipation and consummation of an act during which central and peripheral reactions are coordinated. Later, in 'Some Reflections on the Origin and Significance of the Cerebral Cortex', The Journal of Animal Behavior (1913), 222-236, Herrick claimed the neurological evidence strongly supported Dewey's conception of behavior as an 'organic circuit' by saying that the "'backstroke'" action of motor discharge...may in a literal physiological sense act into the cortical stimulus complex and become an integral part of it' (p. 233).
-
(1913)
The Journal of Animal Behavior
, pp. 222-236
-
-
-
44
-
-
85029971616
-
-
M. B. McGraw to C. J. Herrick, 9 December 1932, Neurology Collection, C. Judson Herrick Papers, Spencer Research Library, University of Kansas, Lawrence, Kansas
-
27 M. B. McGraw to C. J. Herrick, 9 December 1932, Neurology Collection, C. Judson Herrick Papers, Spencer Research Library, University of Kansas, Lawrence, Kansas.
-
-
-
-
46
-
-
84879404911
-
-
Dewey criticized Hegel for conceiving force as external Spirit when it should be understood as internal to growth
-
29 In a class on Hegel's Logic, Dewey criticized Hegel for conceiving force as external Spirit when it should be understood as internal to growth. See J. Dewey, 'Hegel's Logic, Section 136, Dialectic of Force', at the University of Chicago, 1897, Joseph Ratner Papers, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois.
-
Logic
-
-
Hegel1
-
47
-
-
85029972564
-
-
at the University of Chicago. Joseph Ratner Papers, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois
-
29 In a class on Hegel's Logic, Dewey criticized Hegel for conceiving force as external Spirit when it should be understood as internal to growth. See J. Dewey, 'Hegel's Logic, Section 136, Dialectic of Force', at the University of Chicago, 1897, Joseph Ratner Papers, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois.
-
(1897)
Hegel's Logic, Section 136, Dialectic of Force
-
-
Dewey, J.1
-
49
-
-
0011635453
-
The relations of the central and peripheral nervous systems in phylogeny
-
31 C. J. Herrick, 'The Relations of the Central and Peripheral Nervous Systems in Phylogeny', Anatomical Record 36 (1910), 645-652.
-
(1910)
Anatomical Record
, vol.36
, pp. 645-652
-
-
Herrick, C.J.1
-
50
-
-
0039682719
-
Affective thought
-
Indeed, the 1920s marked a watershed for experimental embryology. Hans Spemann discovered the mechanisms governing the early development of the nervous system, leading to a revolution in the understanding of the development of the nervous system
-
32 Dewey grasped more fully the potential that Child and Herrick saw in experimental embryology in elucidating generic traits in 1926 when he announced rather dramatically that: 'Recent advances in some fundamental generalizations regarding biological functions in general and those of the nervous system in particular, make possible a definite conception of continuous development from the lower functions to the higher'. See Dewey, 'Affective Thought', LW: Vol. 2, p. 104. Indeed, the 1920s marked a watershed for experimental embryology. Hans Spemann discovered the mechanisms governing the early development of the nervous system, leading to a revolution in the understanding of the development of the nervous system. See H. Spemann, Embryonic Development and Induction (New York: Hafner, 1962) [Originally published, 1938]. Dewey made an intriguing observation about embryogenesis in a letter referring to works by Herrick and Child when he said: 'I have always thought that the evolution of the ectoderm and mesoderm structures has a deep significance, but I have never followed it through'. See Dewey to C. Chisholm, 28 February 1930, Rare Books and Manuscripts, Butler Library, Columbia University, New York. Significantly, the processes signified by these embryological terms provided the analogies Dewey used to characterize the process of inquiry. The outcome of inquiry, like the fate of individual cells, according to Dewey, is determined only after a process involving, 'the controlled or directed transformation of an indeterminate situation into one that is so determinate in its constituent distinctions and relations as to convert the elements of the original situation into a unified whole' (op. cit., note 3, p. 108). Moreover, Dewey sometimes seemed to be arguing that the antecedents of judgment commence in embryogenesis when he declared that: 'Integration and differentiation are biological processes foreshadowing [affirmation and negation in judgment]....They are themselves prepared for and foreshadowed in the physical processes of conjunction and separation' (ibid., p. 199).
-
LW
, vol.2
, pp. 104
-
-
Dewey1
-
51
-
-
0003704214
-
-
New York: Hafner, Originally published
-
32 Dewey grasped more fully the potential that Child and Herrick saw in experimental embryology in elucidating generic traits in 1926 when he announced rather dramatically that: 'Recent advances in some fundamental generalizations regarding biological functions in general and those of the nervous system in particular, make possible a definite conception of continuous development from the lower functions to the higher'. See Dewey, 'Affective Thought', LW: Vol. 2, p. 104. Indeed, the 1920s marked a watershed for experimental embryology. Hans Spemann discovered the mechanisms governing the early development of the nervous system, leading to a revolution in the understanding of the development of the nervous system. See H. Spemann, Embryonic Development and Induction (New York: Hafner, 1962) [Originally published, 1938]. Dewey made an intriguing observation about embryogenesis in a letter referring to works by Herrick and Child when he said: 'I have always thought that the evolution of the ectoderm and mesoderm structures has a deep significance, but I have never followed it through'. See Dewey to C. Chisholm, 28 February 1930, Rare Books and Manuscripts, Butler Library, Columbia University, New York. Significantly, the processes signified by these embryological terms provided the analogies Dewey used to characterize the process of inquiry. The outcome of inquiry, like the fate of individual cells, according to Dewey, is determined only after a process involving, 'the controlled or directed transformation of an indeterminate situation into one that is so determinate in its constituent distinctions and relations as to convert the elements of the original situation into a unified whole' (op. cit., note 3, p. 108). Moreover, Dewey sometimes seemed to be arguing that the antecedents of judgment commence in embryogenesis when he declared that: 'Integration and differentiation are biological processes foreshadowing [affirmation and negation in judgment]....They are themselves prepared for and foreshadowed in the physical processes of conjunction and separation' (ibid., p. 199).
-
(1938)
Embryonic Development and Induction
-
-
Spemann, H.1
-
52
-
-
85029963656
-
-
note 3
-
32 Dewey grasped more fully the potential that Child and Herrick saw in experimental embryology in elucidating generic traits in 1926 when he announced rather dramatically that: 'Recent advances in some fundamental generalizations regarding biological functions in general and those of the nervous system in particular, make possible a definite conception of continuous development from the lower functions to the higher'. See Dewey, 'Affective Thought', LW: Vol. 2, p. 104. Indeed, the 1920s marked a watershed for experimental embryology. Hans Spemann discovered the mechanisms governing the early development of the nervous system, leading to a revolution in the understanding of the development of the nervous system. See H. Spemann, Embryonic Development and Induction (New York: Hafner, 1962) [Originally published, 1938]. Dewey made an intriguing observation about embryogenesis in a letter referring to works by Herrick and Child when he said: 'I have always thought that the evolution of the ectoderm and mesoderm structures has a deep significance, but I have never followed it through'. See Dewey to C. Chisholm, 28 February 1930, Rare Books and Manuscripts, Butler Library, Columbia University, New York. Significantly, the processes signified by these embryological terms provided the analogies Dewey used to characterize the process of inquiry. The outcome of inquiry, like the fate of individual cells, according to Dewey, is determined only after a process involving, 'the controlled or directed transformation of an indeterminate situation into one that is so determinate in its constituent distinctions and relations as to convert the elements of the original situation into a unified whole' (op. cit., note 3, p. 108). Moreover, Dewey sometimes seemed to be arguing that the antecedents of judgment commence in embryogenesis when he declared that: 'Integration and differentiation are biological processes foreshadowing [affirmation and negation in judgment]....They are themselves prepared for and foreshadowed in the physical processes of conjunction and separation' (ibid., p. 199).
-
Studies in Logical Theory under the Title Essays in Experimental Logic, MW
, pp. 108
-
-
-
53
-
-
85029963656
-
-
32 Dewey grasped more fully the potential that Child and Herrick saw in experimental embryology in elucidating generic traits in 1926 when he announced rather dramatically that: 'Recent advances in some fundamental generalizations regarding biological functions in general and those of the nervous system in particular, make possible a definite conception of continuous development from the lower functions to the higher'. See Dewey, 'Affective Thought', LW: Vol. 2, p. 104. Indeed, the 1920s marked a watershed for experimental embryology. Hans Spemann discovered the mechanisms governing the early development of the nervous system, leading to a revolution in the understanding of the development of the nervous system. See H. Spemann, Embryonic Development and Induction (New York: Hafner, 1962) [Originally published, 1938]. Dewey made an intriguing observation about embryogenesis in a letter referring to works by Herrick and Child when he said: 'I have always thought that the evolution of the ectoderm and mesoderm structures has a deep significance, but I have never followed it through'. See Dewey to C. Chisholm, 28 February 1930, Rare Books and Manuscripts, Butler Library, Columbia University, New York. Significantly, the processes signified by these embryological terms provided the analogies Dewey used to characterize the process of inquiry. The outcome of inquiry, like the fate of individual cells, according to Dewey, is determined only after a process involving, 'the controlled or directed transformation of an indeterminate situation into one that is so determinate in its constituent distinctions and relations as to convert the elements of the original situation into a unified whole' (op. cit., note 3, p. 108). Moreover, Dewey sometimes seemed to be arguing that the antecedents of judgment commence in embryogenesis when he declared that: 'Integration and differentiation are biological processes foreshadowing [affirmation and negation in judgment]....They are themselves prepared for and foreshadowed in the physical processes of conjunction and separation' (ibid., p. 199).
-
Studies in Logical Theory under the Title Essays in Experimental Logic, MW
, pp. 199
-
-
-
55
-
-
0000341786
-
The neuro-embryologic study of behavior: Principles, perspectives, and aims
-
34 G. E. Coghill, 'The Neuro-Embryologic Study of Behavior: Principles, Perspectives, and Aims', Science 78 (1933), 131-136. See also Herrick, ibid.
-
(1933)
Science
, vol.78
, pp. 131-136
-
-
Coghill, G.E.1
-
56
-
-
0000341786
-
-
34 G. E. Coghill, 'The Neuro-Embryologic Study of Behavior: Principles, Perspectives, and Aims', Science 78 (1933), 131-136. See also Herrick, ibid.
-
Science
-
-
Herrick1
-
58
-
-
85029968216
-
-
note
-
36 Dewey acknowledged Maxwell's influence in a letter to Arthur Bentley in 1946 saying: 'Years ago I had a copy of Maxwell's little book [Matter in Motion] - I think when I was at Ann Arbor, [University of Michigan] I remember thinking it was the only thing on physical science principles I could understand'. Dewey to Bentley, 22 January 1946, Arthur Bentley Papers, Manuscripts Department, Lilly Library, Indiana University, Bloomington, Indiana.
-
-
-
-
59
-
-
85029960594
-
-
Amsterdam: New Holland. Jane Dewey corresponded with her father during this time, keeping him informed about her work with personal anecdotes about Bohr. Dewey visited Jane at Bohr's Institute in Copenhagen in the summer of 1926 as Jane noted in a letter to her father, 17 August 1926, John Dewey Papers, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois
-
37 See L. Rosenfeld (ed.), Niels Bohr, 1885-1962: Collected Works (Amsterdam: New Holland, 1972). Jane Dewey corresponded with her father during this time, keeping him informed about her work with personal anecdotes about Bohr. Dewey visited Jane at Bohr's Institute in Copenhagen in the summer of 1926 as Jane noted in a letter to her father, 17 August 1926, John Dewey Papers, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois.
-
(1972)
Niels Bohr, 1885-1962: Collected Works
-
-
Rosenfeld, L.1
-
60
-
-
0000165293
-
Life and light
-
38 N. Bohr, 'Life and Light', Nature 131 (1937), 421-423; 457-459.
-
(1937)
Nature
, vol.131
, pp. 421-423
-
-
Bohr, N.1
-
61
-
-
0003509805
-
-
New York: Oxford University Press
-
39 L. von Bertalanffy, Modern Theories of Development (New York: Oxford University Press, 1933); J. H. Woodger, The Axiomatic Method in Biology (London: Cambridge University Press, 1937). A. Lotka, Elements of Mathematical Biology (New York: Dover, 1956). Dewey also found population biologist Alfred Lotka's attempt to understand the energetics of consciousness and growth a complementary way to translate into biological terms physicist James Clerk Maxwell's idea that all matter is motion. Lotka proposed that the evolution of biological systems could be understood best by conceiving of life forms as 'moving equlibria' whose position and vector depends upon energy transformations and displacements from collisions that occur during development (ibid., p. 388). Lotka contended that consciousness evolved as a mechanism to simplify the processes involved in the transformation of an organism from one state to another, by enabling it to control the timing, scope, and expenditure of energy (through adjustments in metabolic rate) in response to factors impinging on its growth and development (ibid., pp. 388-345). Dewey first mentions Lotka's book in a letter to Chisholm on 28 October 1932, op. cit., note 32, p. 2. Dewey indicates in correspondence with Corinne Chisholm, 12 April 1942, op. cit., note 32, that he began a preliminary attempt to sketch a notational system that identifies the different forms energy might assume through their interaction - a move indicative of his continual efforts to conceptually integrate neurodynamic and neuroembryological perspectives. Dewey clearly demonstrates, with this notational system, his belief that consciousness (allied with memory) possesses the energy necessary to modify structures sufficiently to displace old behavior patterns and form new ones.
-
(1933)
Modern Theories of Development
-
-
Von Bertalanffy, L.1
-
62
-
-
0004148709
-
-
London: Cambridge University Press
-
39 L. von Bertalanffy, Modern Theories of Development (New York: Oxford University Press, 1933); J. H. Woodger, The Axiomatic Method in Biology (London: Cambridge University Press, 1937). A. Lotka, Elements of Mathematical Biology (New York: Dover, 1956). Dewey also found population biologist Alfred Lotka's attempt to understand the energetics of consciousness and growth a complementary way to translate into biological terms physicist James Clerk Maxwell's idea that all matter is motion. Lotka proposed that the evolution of biological systems could be understood best by conceiving of life forms as 'moving equlibria' whose position and vector depends upon energy transformations and displacements from collisions that occur during development (ibid., p. 388). Lotka contended that consciousness evolved as a mechanism to simplify the processes involved in the transformation of an organism from one state to another, by enabling it to control the timing, scope, and expenditure of energy (through adjustments in metabolic rate) in response to factors impinging on its growth and development (ibid., pp. 388-345). Dewey first mentions Lotka's book in a letter to Chisholm on 28 October 1932, op. cit., note 32, p. 2. Dewey indicates in correspondence with Corinne Chisholm, 12 April 1942, op. cit., note 32, that he began a preliminary attempt to sketch a notational system that identifies the different forms energy might assume through their interaction - a move indicative of his continual efforts to conceptually integrate neurodynamic and neuroembryological perspectives. Dewey clearly demonstrates, with this notational system, his belief that consciousness (allied with memory) possesses the energy necessary to modify structures sufficiently to displace old behavior patterns and form new ones.
-
(1937)
The Axiomatic Method in Biology
-
-
Woodger, J.H.1
-
63
-
-
0004075481
-
-
New York: Dover
-
39 L. von Bertalanffy, Modern Theories of Development (New York: Oxford University Press, 1933); J. H. Woodger, The Axiomatic Method in Biology (London: Cambridge University Press, 1937). A. Lotka, Elements of Mathematical Biology (New York: Dover, 1956). Dewey also found population biologist Alfred Lotka's attempt to understand the energetics of consciousness and growth a complementary way to translate into biological terms physicist James Clerk Maxwell's idea that all matter is motion. Lotka proposed that the evolution of biological systems could be understood best by conceiving of life forms as 'moving equlibria' whose position and vector depends upon energy transformations and displacements from collisions that occur during development (ibid., p. 388). Lotka contended that consciousness evolved as a mechanism to simplify the processes involved in the transformation of an organism from one state to another, by enabling it to control the timing, scope, and expenditure of energy (through adjustments in metabolic rate) in response to factors impinging on its growth and development (ibid., pp. 388-345). Dewey first mentions Lotka's book in a letter to Chisholm on 28 October 1932, op. cit., note 32, p. 2. Dewey indicates in correspondence with Corinne Chisholm, 12 April 1942, op. cit., note 32, that he began a preliminary attempt to sketch a notational system that identifies the different forms energy might assume through their interaction - a move indicative of his continual efforts to conceptually integrate neurodynamic and neuroembryological perspectives. Dewey clearly demonstrates, with this notational system, his belief that consciousness (allied with memory) possesses the energy necessary to modify structures sufficiently to displace old behavior patterns and form new ones.
-
(1956)
Elements of Mathematical Biology
-
-
Lotka, A.1
-
64
-
-
85029968797
-
-
39 L. von Bertalanffy, Modern Theories of Development (New York: Oxford University Press, 1933); J. H. Woodger, The Axiomatic Method in Biology (London: Cambridge University Press, 1937). A. Lotka, Elements of Mathematical Biology (New York: Dover, 1956). Dewey also found population biologist Alfred Lotka's attempt to understand the energetics of consciousness and growth a complementary way to translate into biological terms physicist James Clerk Maxwell's idea that all matter is motion. Lotka proposed that the evolution of biological systems could be understood best by conceiving of life forms as 'moving equlibria' whose position and vector depends upon energy transformations and displacements from collisions that occur during development (ibid., p. 388). Lotka contended that consciousness evolved as a mechanism to simplify the processes involved in the transformation of an organism from one state to another, by enabling it to control the timing, scope, and expenditure of energy (through adjustments in metabolic rate) in response to factors impinging on its growth and development (ibid., pp. 388-345). Dewey first mentions Lotka's book in a letter to Chisholm on 28 October 1932, op. cit., note 32, p. 2. Dewey indicates in correspondence with Corinne Chisholm, 12 April 1942, op. cit., note 32, that he began a preliminary attempt to sketch a notational system that identifies the different forms energy might assume through their interaction - a move indicative of his continual efforts to conceptually integrate neurodynamic and neuroembryological perspectives. Dewey clearly demonstrates, with this notational system, his belief that consciousness (allied with memory) possesses the energy necessary to modify structures sufficiently to displace old behavior patterns and form new ones.
-
Elements of Mathematical Biology
, pp. 388
-
-
-
65
-
-
85029968797
-
-
39 L. von Bertalanffy, Modern Theories of Development (New York: Oxford University Press, 1933); J. H. Woodger, The Axiomatic Method in Biology (London: Cambridge University Press, 1937). A. Lotka, Elements of Mathematical Biology (New York: Dover, 1956). Dewey also found population biologist Alfred Lotka's attempt to understand the energetics of consciousness and growth a complementary way to translate into biological terms physicist James Clerk Maxwell's idea that all matter is motion. Lotka proposed that the evolution of biological systems could be understood best by conceiving of life forms as 'moving equlibria' whose position and vector depends upon energy transformations and displacements from collisions that occur during development (ibid., p. 388). Lotka contended that consciousness evolved as a mechanism to simplify the processes involved in the transformation of an organism from one state to another, by enabling it to control the timing, scope, and expenditure of energy (through adjustments in metabolic rate) in response to factors impinging on its growth and development (ibid., pp. 388-345). Dewey first mentions Lotka's book in a letter to Chisholm on 28 October 1932, op. cit., note 32, p. 2. Dewey indicates in correspondence with Corinne Chisholm, 12 April 1942, op. cit., note 32, that he began a preliminary attempt to sketch a notational system that identifies the different forms energy might assume through their interaction - a move indicative of his continual efforts to conceptually integrate neurodynamic and neuroembryological perspectives. Dewey clearly demonstrates, with this notational system, his belief that consciousness (allied with memory) possesses the energy necessary to modify structures sufficiently to displace old behavior patterns and form new ones.
-
Elements of Mathematical Biology
, pp. 388-345
-
-
-
66
-
-
85029963656
-
-
note 32
-
39 L. von Bertalanffy, Modern Theories of Development (New York: Oxford University Press, 1933); J. H. Woodger, The Axiomatic Method in Biology (London: Cambridge University Press, 1937). A. Lotka, Elements of Mathematical Biology (New York: Dover, 1956). Dewey also found population biologist Alfred Lotka's attempt to understand the energetics of consciousness and growth a complementary way to translate into biological terms physicist James Clerk Maxwell's idea that all matter is motion. Lotka proposed that the evolution of biological systems could be understood best by conceiving of life forms as 'moving equlibria' whose position and vector depends upon energy transformations and displacements from collisions that occur during development (ibid., p. 388). Lotka contended that consciousness evolved as a mechanism to simplify the processes involved in the transformation of an organism from one state to another, by enabling it to control the timing, scope, and expenditure of energy (through adjustments in metabolic rate) in response to factors impinging on its growth and development (ibid., pp. 388-345). Dewey first mentions Lotka's book in a letter to Chisholm on 28 October 1932, op. cit., note 32, p. 2. Dewey indicates in correspondence with Corinne Chisholm, 12 April 1942, op. cit., note 32, that he began a preliminary attempt to sketch a notational system that identifies the different forms energy might assume through their interaction - a move indicative of his continual efforts to conceptually integrate neurodynamic and neuroembryological perspectives. Dewey clearly demonstrates, with this notational system, his belief that consciousness (allied with memory) possesses the energy necessary to modify structures sufficiently to displace old behavior patterns and form new ones.
-
Studies in Logical Theory under the Title Essays in Experimental Logic, MW
, pp. 2
-
-
-
67
-
-
84924288937
-
-
note 32, that he began a preliminary attempt to sketch a notational system that identifies the different forms energy might assume through their interaction - a move indicative of his continual efforts to conceptually integrate neurodynamic and neuroembryological perspectives. Dewey clearly demonstrates, with this notational system, his belief that consciousness (allied with memory) possesses the energy necessary to modify structures sufficiently to displace old behavior patterns and form new ones
-
39 L. von Bertalanffy, Modern Theories of Development (New York: Oxford University Press, 1933); J. H. Woodger, The Axiomatic Method in Biology (London: Cambridge University Press, 1937). A. Lotka, Elements of Mathematical Biology (New York: Dover, 1956). Dewey also found population biologist Alfred Lotka's attempt to understand the energetics of consciousness and growth a complementary way to translate into biological terms physicist James Clerk Maxwell's idea that all matter is motion. Lotka proposed that the evolution of biological systems could be understood best by conceiving of life forms as 'moving equlibria' whose position and vector depends upon energy transformations and displacements from collisions that occur during development (ibid., p. 388). Lotka contended that consciousness evolved as a mechanism to simplify the processes involved in the transformation of an organism from one state to another, by enabling it to control the timing, scope, and expenditure of energy (through adjustments in metabolic rate) in response to factors impinging on its growth and development (ibid., pp. 388-345). Dewey first mentions Lotka's book in a letter to Chisholm on 28 October 1932, op. cit., note 32, p. 2. Dewey indicates in correspondence with Corinne Chisholm, 12 April 1942, op. cit., note 32, that he began a preliminary attempt to sketch a notational system that identifies the different forms energy might assume through their interaction - a move indicative of his continual efforts to conceptually integrate neurodynamic and neuroembryological perspectives. Dewey clearly demonstrates, with this notational system, his belief that consciousness (allied with memory) possesses the energy necessary to modify structures sufficiently to displace old behavior patterns and form new ones.
-
LW
-
-
Dewey1
-
68
-
-
0001855995
-
Principles of mental development as illustrated in early infancy
-
J. A. Boydston (ed.), [hereafter EW] Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press
-
40 D. J. Dewey, 'Principles of Mental Development as Illustrated in Early Infancy', in J. A. Boydston (ed.), John Dewey: The Early Works, Vol. 1: 1899-1901 [hereafter EW] (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1976), pp. 175-191. See also K. Mayhew and A. Edwards, The Dewey School (New York: Appleton Century Co., 1936; reprinted, New York: Atherton, 1976). For an intriguing discussion of Dewey's psychology of education within the broader context of educational reforms advanced by turn-of-the-century educators G. Stanley Hall and Edward L. Thorndike, see S. H. White, 'Three Visions of a Psychology of Education', in L. T. Landsmann (ed.), Culture, Schooling and Psychological Development (Norwood, NJ: Ablex), pp. 1-39.
-
(1976)
John Dewey: The Early Works
, vol.1
, pp. 1899-1901
-
-
Dewey, D.J.1
-
69
-
-
0004200491
-
-
New York: Appleton Century Co.; reprinted, New York: Atherton
-
40 D. J. Dewey, 'Principles of Mental Development as Illustrated in Early Infancy', in J. A. Boydston (ed.), John Dewey: The Early Works, Vol. 1: 1899-1901 [hereafter EW] (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1976), pp. 175-191. See also K. Mayhew and A. Edwards, The Dewey School (New York: Appleton Century Co., 1936; reprinted, New York: Atherton, 1976). For an intriguing discussion of Dewey's psychology of education within the broader context of educational reforms advanced by turn-of-the-century educators G. Stanley Hall and Edward L. Thorndike, see S. H. White, 'Three Visions of a Psychology of Education', in L. T. Landsmann (ed.), Culture, Schooling and Psychological Development (Norwood, NJ: Ablex), pp. 1-39.
-
(1936)
The Dewey School
-
-
Mayhew, K.1
Edwards, A.2
-
70
-
-
0011570431
-
Three visions of a psychology of education
-
L. T. Landsmann (ed.), Norwood, NJ: Ablex
-
40 D. J. Dewey, 'Principles of Mental Development as Illustrated in Early Infancy', in J. A. Boydston (ed.), John Dewey: The Early Works, Vol. 1: 1899-1901 [hereafter EW] (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1976), pp. 175-191. See also K. Mayhew and A. Edwards, The Dewey School (New York: Appleton Century Co., 1936; reprinted, New York: Atherton, 1976). For an intriguing discussion of Dewey's psychology of education within the broader context of educational reforms advanced by turn-of-the-century educators G. Stanley Hall and Edward L. Thorndike, see S. H. White, 'Three Visions of a Psychology of Education', in L. T. Landsmann (ed.), Culture, Schooling and Psychological Development (Norwood, NJ: Ablex), pp. 1-39.
-
Culture, Schooling and Psychological Development
, pp. 1-39
-
-
White, S.H.1
-
72
-
-
85029964969
-
-
New York: D. Appleton and Co., The Hegelian W. T. Harris wrote an editor's preface saying that the authors had captured the fundamentally qualitative, functional attributes involved in the use of quantitative measures and methods. Dewey and McLellan argued that every form of mathematical calculation involved the same objective, namely of distributing parts in some order and assigning value in relation to the whole
-
42 J. Dewey and J. McLellan, The Psychology of Number and Its Application to Methods of Teaching (New York: D. Appleton and Co., 1898). The Hegelian W. T. Harris wrote an editor's preface saying that the authors had captured the fundamentally qualitative, functional attributes involved in the use of quantitative measures and methods. Dewey and McLellan argued that every form of mathematical calculation involved the same objective, namely of distributing parts in some order and assigning value in relation to the whole. Hegel made precisely the same argument in his analysis of measurement in Science of Logic. See Miller, op. cit., note 8, pp. 314-385.
-
(1898)
The Psychology of Number and Its Application to Methods of Teaching
-
-
Dewey, J.1
McLellan, J.2
-
73
-
-
0004226456
-
-
42 J. Dewey and J. McLellan, The Psychology of Number and Its Application to Methods of Teaching (New York: D. Appleton and Co., 1898). The Hegelian W. T. Harris wrote an editor's preface saying that the authors had captured the fundamentally qualitative, functional attributes involved in the use of quantitative measures and methods. Dewey and McLellan argued that every form of mathematical calculation involved the same objective, namely of distributing parts in some order and assigning value in relation to the whole. Hegel made precisely the same argument in his analysis of measurement in Science of Logic. See Miller, op. cit., note 8, pp. 314-385.
-
Science of Logic
-
-
Hegel1
-
74
-
-
0004232279
-
-
note 8
-
42 J. Dewey and J. McLellan, The Psychology of Number and Its Application to Methods of Teaching (New York: D. Appleton and Co., 1898). The Hegelian W. T. Harris wrote an editor's preface saying that the authors had captured the fundamentally qualitative, functional attributes involved in the use of quantitative measures and methods. Dewey and McLellan argued that every form of mathematical calculation involved the same objective, namely of distributing parts in some order and assigning value in relation to the whole. Hegel made precisely the same argument in his analysis of measurement in Science of Logic. See Miller, op. cit., note 8, pp. 314-385.
-
Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit
, pp. 314-385
-
-
Miller1
-
76
-
-
0000144261
-
Progressive education and the scientific study of the child: An analysis of the Bureau of Educational Experiments
-
Evelyn Dewey was a member of the working council and held various research positions from 1916-1920. Although John Dewey served as an honorary member of the working council, his participation and influence extended well beyond his formal title as indicated by Wesley Mitchell's diary and the Bank Street Archives. See Wesley Mitchell Papers, Rare Books and Manuscripts, Butler Library, Columbia University, New York
-
44 See J. Antler, 'Progressive Education and the Scientific Study of the Child: An Analysis of the Bureau of Educational Experiments', Teachers College Record 83 (1982), 559-591. Evelyn Dewey was a member of the working council and held various research positions from 1916-1920. Although John Dewey served as an honorary member of the working council, his participation and influence extended well beyond his formal title as indicated by Wesley Mitchell's diary and the Bank Street Archives. See Wesley Mitchell Papers, Rare Books and Manuscripts, Butler Library, Columbia University, New York.
-
(1982)
Teachers College Record
, vol.83
, pp. 559-591
-
-
Antler, J.1
-
78
-
-
85029968020
-
-
note
-
46 In a grant application to the Laura Spelman Rockefeller Memorial, Lucy Mitchell insisted that her methods were comparable but superior to Gesell's because, she said, 'our conception of growth is not based on formal tests but on natural behavior in a carefully standardized situation of a much broader scope than that arranged by Gesell'. Mitchell to Trustees, 6 May 1925, Laura Spelman Rockefeller Memorial Record Group I, Series 3.5, Box 27, Folder 279, Rockefeller Archive Center, Tarrytown, New York [Hereinafter RAC-LSRM].
-
-
-
-
79
-
-
0011570136
-
-
New York: McGraw-Hill
-
47 A. Gesell, Infant Behavior: Its Genesis and Growth (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1934). See also E. Thelen and K. E. Adolf, 'Arnold L. Gesell: The Paradox of Nature and Nurture', Developmental Psychology 28 (1992), 368-380.
-
(1934)
Infant Behavior: Its Genesis and Growth
-
-
Gesell, A.1
-
80
-
-
0011570136
-
Arnold L. Gesell: The paradox of nature and nurture
-
47 A. Gesell, Infant Behavior: Its Genesis and Growth (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1934). See also E. Thelen and K. E. Adolf, 'Arnold L. Gesell: The Paradox of Nature and Nurture', Developmental Psychology 28 (1992), 368-380.
-
(1992)
Developmental Psychology
, vol.28
, pp. 368-380
-
-
Thelen, E.1
Adolf, K.E.2
-
81
-
-
0011571290
-
-
New York: Paul F. Hoeber
-
48 See C. Eisberg, The Story of a Hospital: The Neurological Institute of New York, 1909-1938 (New York: Paul F. Hoeber, 1944), and Lawrence Pool, The Neurological Institute of New York, 1909-1974 (Lakeville, CT: Pocketknife Press, 1975), for historical studies.
-
(1944)
The Story of a Hospital: The Neurological Institute of New York, 1909-1938
-
-
Elsberg, C.1
-
82
-
-
0011575563
-
-
Lakeville, CT: Pocketknife Press, for historical studies
-
48 See C. Eisberg, The Story of a Hospital: The Neurological Institute of New York, 1909-1938 (New York: Paul F. Hoeber, 1944), and Lawrence Pool, The Neurological Institute of New York, 1909-1974 (Lakeville, CT: Pocketknife Press, 1975), for historical studies.
-
(1975)
The Neurological Institute of New York, 1909-1974
-
-
Pool, L.1
-
83
-
-
0000230794
-
Genesis of cerebellar functions
-
49 F. Tilney, 'Genesis of Cerebellar Functions', Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry 9 (1923), 137-169; F. Tilney and L. Casamajor, 'Myelinogeny as Applied to the Study of Behavior', Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry 12 (1924), 1-66; and F. Tilney and L. Kubie, 'Behavior in its Relation to the Development of the Brain', Bulletin of the Neurological Institute 1 (1931), 226-213.
-
(1923)
Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry
, vol.9
, pp. 137-169
-
-
Tilney, F.1
-
84
-
-
0002441247
-
Myelinogeny as applied to the study of behavior
-
49 F. Tilney, 'Genesis of Cerebellar Functions', Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry 9 (1923), 137-169; F. Tilney and L. Casamajor, 'Myelinogeny as Applied to the Study of Behavior', Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry 12 (1924), 1-66; and F. Tilney and L. Kubie, 'Behavior in its Relation to the Development of the Brain', Bulletin of the Neurological Institute 1 (1931), 226-213.
-
(1924)
Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry
, vol.12
, pp. 1-66
-
-
Tilney, F.1
Casamajor, L.2
-
85
-
-
0000230794
-
Behavior in its relation to the development of the brain
-
49 F. Tilney, 'Genesis of Cerebellar Functions', Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry 9 (1923), 137-169; F. Tilney and L. Casamajor, 'Myelinogeny as Applied to the Study of Behavior', Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry 12 (1924), 1-66; and F. Tilney and L. Kubie, 'Behavior in its Relation to the Development of the Brain', Bulletin of the Neurological Institute 1 (1931), 226-213.
-
(1931)
Bulletin of the Neurological Institute
, vol.1
, pp. 226-1213
-
-
Tilney, F.1
Kubie, L.2
-
86
-
-
85029961507
-
-
Tilney to F. P. Keppel, The Normal Child Development Project, Carnegie Corporation, 22 March 1933, and J. Merriam to F. P. Keppel, 15 March 1943, Carnegie Corporation Papers
-
50 See Tilney to F. P. Keppel, The Normal Child Development Project, Carnegie Corporation, 22 March 1933, and J. Merriam to F. P. Keppel, 15 March 1943, Carnegie Corporation Papers.
-
-
-
-
88
-
-
0004287250
-
-
New York: Hoeber; reprinted New York: Doubleday
-
52 F. Tilney, Master of Destiny (New York: Hoeber, 1929; reprinted New York: Doubleday, 1968), pp. 281-290.
-
(1929)
Master of Destiny
, pp. 281-290
-
-
Tilney, F.1
-
90
-
-
0003304150
-
Memories, deliberate recall and speculation
-
54 See M. McGraw, 'Memories, Deliberate Recall and Speculation', American Psychologist 45 (1990) 936.
-
(1990)
American Psychologist
, vol.45
, pp. 936
-
-
McGraw, M.1
-
91
-
-
85029964725
-
-
note
-
55 Telephone interview with Katherine Agate Heyl, Norwich, Vermont, 23 December 1989. Heyl shared an apartment with McGraw and worked as a laboratory assistant for three years until she married a neurosurgeon from the Institute. Heyl noted that Dewey used to come over for dinner (or take McGraw out to dinner) every Wednesday evening. Heyl was not privy to their conversations but was generally under the impression that Dewey had originated the NCDS study.
-
-
-
-
92
-
-
85029972247
-
-
Milton Senn Collection, History of Medicine Division, National Library of Medicine, Bethesda, MD
-
56 See M. Senn, Interview with Myrtle McGraw, Hastings-on-Hudson, New York, 9 May 1972. Milton Senn Collection, History of Medicine Division, National Library of Medicine, Bethesda, MD, p. 41.
-
(1972)
Interview with Myrtle Mcgraw, Hastings-on-Hudson, New York, 9 May 1972
, pp. 41
-
-
Senn, M.1
-
93
-
-
85029966031
-
-
Columbia Medical Center, 13 March, RAC-GEB, Record Group I., Series 1.3, Box 370, Folder 3858
-
57 Memorandum of an interview with M. McGraw at Babies Hospital, Columbia Medical Center, by L. K. Frank, 13 March 1933, RAC-GEB, Record Group I., Series 1.3, Box 370, Folder 3858.
-
(1933)
Memorandum of an Interview with M. Mcgraw at Babies Hospital
-
-
Frank, L.K.1
-
94
-
-
0000442794
-
Structure, function, and growth
-
58 See for example, L. K. Frank, 'Structure, Function, and Growth', Philosophy of Science 2 (1935), 210-235, and 'The Problem of Child Development', Child Development 1 (1935), 7-18.
-
(1935)
Philosophy of Science
, vol.2
, pp. 210-235
-
-
Frank, L.K.1
-
95
-
-
0011636835
-
The problem of child development
-
58 See for example, L. K. Frank, 'Structure, Function, and Growth', Philosophy of Science 2 (1935), 210-235, and 'The Problem of Child Development', Child Development 1 (1935), 7-18.
-
(1935)
Child Development
, vol.1
, pp. 7-18
-
-
-
96
-
-
0011571291
-
The beginnings of child development and family life education in the twentieth century
-
59 L. K. Frank, 'The Beginnings of Child Development and Family Life Education in the Twentieth Century', Merrill-Palmer Quarterly of Behavior and Development 8 (1962), 207-228; see also H. Cravens, Before Head Start: The Iowa Station and America's Children (Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press, 1993). For an alternative account to Cravens that singles out Dewey's influence in child study and attaches more significance to McGraw's research at Columbia than Iowa, see T. C. Dalton, 'Challenging the Group Bias of American Culture', Journal of Contemporary Psychology, March, 1995.
-
(1962)
Merrill-Palmer Quarterly of Behavior and Development
, vol.8
, pp. 207-228
-
-
Frank, L.K.1
-
97
-
-
0004143327
-
-
Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press
-
59 L. K. Frank, 'The Beginnings of Child Development and Family Life Education in the Twentieth Century', Merrill-Palmer Quarterly of Behavior and Development 8 (1962), 207-228; see also H. Cravens, Before Head Start: The Iowa Station and America's Children (Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press, 1993). For an alternative account to Cravens that singles out Dewey's influence in child study and attaches more significance to McGraw's research at Columbia than Iowa, see T. C. Dalton, 'Challenging the Group Bias of American Culture', Journal of Contemporary Psychology, March, 1995.
-
(1993)
Before Head Start: The Iowa Station and America's Children
-
-
Cravens, H.1
-
98
-
-
0011686343
-
Challenging the group bias of American culture
-
March
-
59 L. K. Frank, 'The Beginnings of Child Development and Family Life Education in the Twentieth Century', Merrill-Palmer Quarterly of Behavior and Development 8 (1962), 207-228; see also H. Cravens, Before Head Start: The Iowa Station and America's Children (Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press, 1993). For an alternative account to Cravens that singles out Dewey's influence in child study and attaches more significance to McGraw's research at Columbia than Iowa, see T. C. Dalton, 'Challenging the Group Bias of American Culture', Journal of Contemporary Psychology, March, 1995.
-
(1995)
Journal of Contemporary Psychology
-
-
Dalton, T.C.1
-
99
-
-
0011691109
-
-
New York: Josiah Macy, Jr Foundation
-
60 Dewey is listed as a past founding member of the Board of Directors in a report by Willard Rappleye, President from 1941-1964, titled The Josiah Macy, Jr Foundation: Twentieth Anniversary Review, 1930-1955 (New York: Josiah Macy, Jr Foundation, 1955), p. ix. McGraw's research is also described in this report (see p. 25). Ludwig Kast (1930-1941), describes funded research in growth including McGraw and Coghill's studies in a report titled A Review by the President of Activities for the Six Years Ending December 31, 1936 (New York: Josiah Macy, Jr Foundation, 1937), pp., 34-37. Dr. Thomas Meikle, Executive Director of the Macy Foundation, indicated to the authors that all minutes of trustee meetings and other memoranda concerning grant awards in the foundation's early years, including material documenting Dewey's involvement, had been destroyed due to limited storage space. Interview with Meikle, New York City, 27 April 1992).
-
(1955)
The Josiah Macy, Jr Foundation: Twentieth Anniversary Review, 1930-1955
, pp. 9
-
-
Rappleye, W.1
-
100
-
-
85029963571
-
-
New York: Josiah Macy, Jr Foundation. Dr. Thomas Meikle, Executive Director of the Macy Foundation, indicated to the authors that all minutes of trustee meetings and other memoranda concerning grant awards in the foundation's early years, including material documenting Dewey's involvement, had been destroyed due to limited storage space. Interview with Meikle, New York City, 27 April 1992
-
60 Dewey is listed as a past founding member of the Board of Directors in a report by Willard Rappleye, President from 1941-1964, titled The Josiah Macy, Jr Foundation: Twentieth Anniversary Review, 1930-1955 (New York: Josiah Macy, Jr Foundation, 1955), p. ix. McGraw's research is also described in this report (see p. 25). Ludwig Kast (1930-1941), describes funded research in growth including McGraw and Coghill's studies in a report titled A Review by the President of Activities for the Six Years Ending December 31, 1936 (New York: Josiah Macy, Jr Foundation, 1937), pp., 34-37. Dr. Thomas Meikle, Executive Director of the Macy Foundation, indicated to the authors that all minutes of trustee meetings and other memoranda concerning grant awards in the foundation's early years, including material documenting Dewey's involvement, had been destroyed due to limited storage space. Interview with Meikle, New York City, 27 April 1992).
-
(1937)
A Review by the President of Activities for the Six Years Ending December 31, 1936
, pp. 34-37
-
-
McGraw1
Coghill2
-
101
-
-
0003511174
-
-
New York: Columbia University Press; reprint, New York: Arno
-
61 E. Dewey, Behavior Development in Infants: A Survey of the Literature on Prenatal and Postnatal Activity, 1920-1924 (New York: Columbia University Press, 1935; reprint, New York: Arno, 1972), pp. 354-356.
-
(1935)
Behavior Development in Infants: A Survey of the Literature on Prenatal and Postnatal Activity, 1920-1924
, pp. 354-356
-
-
Dewey, E.1
-
102
-
-
85029963409
-
-
Letter to M. McGraw, 15 September 1935, and 16 November 1936, Center for Dewey Studies and Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, IL
-
62 Letter to M. McGraw, 15 September 1935, and 16 November 1936, Center for Dewey Studies and Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, IL.
-
-
-
-
103
-
-
85029962988
-
-
op. cit., note 36, and Letter to McGraw, 31 May 1934 and 1 September 1935
-
63 See L. Kast, op. cit., note 36, pp. 11, 34-37, and Letter to McGraw, 31 May 1934 and 1 September 1935, ibid.
-
-
-
Kast, L.1
-
105
-
-
85029967919
-
-
Letter to McGraw, Sat. ca. 1933; Wednesday ca. 1935; 20 July 1935; 16 November 1936
-
64 Letter to McGraw, Sat. ca. 1933; Wednesday ca. 1935; 20 July 1935; 16 November 1936, ibid.
-
-
-
-
107
-
-
0011575564
-
-
note 54
-
66 M. McGraw, op cit., note 54, see p. 934. For a more detailed account of McGraw's career and contributions to developmental psychology see V. W. Bergenn, T. C. Dalton and L. P. Lipsitt, 'Myrtle McGraw: A Growth Scientist', Developmental Psychology 28 (1992), 381-395.
-
American Psychologist
, pp. 934
-
-
McGraw, M.1
-
108
-
-
0011575564
-
Myrtle Mcgraw: A growth scientist
-
66 M. McGraw, op cit., note 54, see p. 934. For a more detailed account of McGraw's career and contributions to developmental psychology see V. W. Bergenn, T. C. Dalton and L. P. Lipsitt, 'Myrtle McGraw: A Growth Scientist', Developmental Psychology 28 (1992), 381-395.
-
(1992)
Developmental Psychology
, vol.28
, pp. 381-395
-
-
Bergenn, V.W.1
Dalton, T.C.2
Lipsitt, L.P.3
-
109
-
-
85029969255
-
Interview with Myrtle Mcgraw
-
9 February New York, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois
-
67 K. Duckett, 'Interview with Myrtle McGraw', 9 February 1967, p. 6. Hastings-on-Hudson, New York, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois.
-
(1967)
Hastings-on-Hudson
, pp. 6
-
-
Duckett, K.1
-
112
-
-
0009451905
-
-
McGraw's research was comparable to Faraday's in the sense that she used biological and physical analogues to understand human behavior in a new way just as Faraday did to create a new perspective about the properties of electricity
-
70 New York Times 1935, p. 19. McGraw's research was comparable to Faraday's in the sense that she used biological and physical analogues to understand human behavior in a new way just as Faraday did to create a new perspective about the properties of electricity.
-
(1935)
New York Times
, pp. 19
-
-
-
113
-
-
0011691110
-
Introduction
-
M. B. McGraw, New York: Appleton Century; reprinted, New York: Arno
-
71 Dewey, 'Introduction', in M. B. McGraw, Growth: A Study of Johnny and Jimmy (New York: Appleton Century, 1935; reprinted, New York: Arno, 1975), p. xiii.
-
(1935)
Growth: A Study of Johnny and Jimmy
, pp. 13
-
-
Dewey1
-
114
-
-
85029965099
-
-
op. cit., note 62
-
72 See McGraw, op. cit., note 62.
-
-
-
McGraw1
-
115
-
-
85029967833
-
-
Letter to A. Bentley, 26 July 1935, Arthur Bentley Papers, Manuscripts Department, Lilly Library, Indiana University, Bloomington, Indiana
-
73 Letter to A. Bentley, 26 July 1935, Arthur Bentley Papers, Manuscripts Department, Lilly Library, Indiana University, Bloomington, Indiana.
-
-
-
-
116
-
-
85029968008
-
Textual commentary
-
74 K. Poulos, 'Textual Commentary', LW: Vol. 12, pp. 533-549.
-
LW
, vol.12
, pp. 533-549
-
-
Poulos, K.1
-
117
-
-
85029960949
-
-
Letter to C. Chisholm, 1 July 1930, Rare Books and Manuscripts, Butler Library, Columbia University, New York
-
75 Letter to C. Chisholm, 1 July 1930, Rare Books and Manuscripts, Butler Library, Columbia University, New York.
-
-
-
-
119
-
-
85029965365
-
-
See W. Rappleye to L. K. Frank, 2 December 1935, RAC-GEB., Record Group I, Series 1.3, Box 370, Folder 3858
-
77 See W. Rappleye to L. K. Frank, 2 December 1935, RAC-GEB., Record Group I, Series 1.3, Box 370, Folder 3858.
-
-
-
-
120
-
-
0004277257
-
-
New York: Cambridge University Press; reprinted, New York: Hafner Publishing Co
-
78 G. E. Coghill, Anatomy and the Problem of Behavior (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1929; reprinted, New York: Hafner Publishing Co., 1964), p. 38.
-
(1929)
Anatomy and the Problem of Behavior
, pp. 38
-
-
Coghill, G.E.1
-
121
-
-
0345330075
-
Individuation verses integration in the development of behavior
-
79 G. E. Coghill, 'Individuation Verses Integration in the Development of Behavior', Journal of Genetic Psychology 3 (1930), 432-433, see p. 432.
-
(1930)
Journal of Genetic Psychology
, vol.3
, pp. 432-433
-
-
Coghill, G.E.1
-
124
-
-
0011635455
-
Total pattern or local reflexes?
-
82 Z. Y. Kuo, 'Total Pattern or Local Reflexes?' Psychological Review 46 (1939), 93-122; W. F. Windle, 'Correlation Between the Development of Local Reflexes and the Reflex Arcs in the Spinal Cord of Cat Embryos', Journal of Comparative Neurology 59 (1934), 487-505; and see Oppenheim, op. cit., note 83, pp. 55-56.
-
(1939)
Psychological Review
, vol.46
, pp. 93-122
-
-
Kuo, Z.Y.1
-
125
-
-
84981839913
-
Correlation between the development of local reflexes and the reflex arcs in the spinal cord of cat embryos
-
82 Z. Y. Kuo, 'Total Pattern or Local Reflexes?' Psychological Review 46 (1939), 93-122; W. F. Windle, 'Correlation Between the Development of Local Reflexes and the Reflex Arcs in the Spinal Cord of Cat Embryos', Journal of Comparative Neurology 59 (1934), 487-505; and see Oppenheim, op. cit., note 83, pp. 55-56.
-
(1934)
Journal of Comparative Neurology
, vol.59
, pp. 487-505
-
-
Windle, W.F.1
-
126
-
-
0011635455
-
-
note 83
-
82 Z. Y. Kuo, 'Total Pattern or Local Reflexes?' Psychological Review 46 (1939), 93-122; W. F. Windle, 'Correlation Between the Development of Local Reflexes and the Reflex Arcs in the Spinal Cord of Cat Embryos', Journal of Comparative Neurology 59 (1934), 487-505; and see Oppenheim, op. cit., note 83, pp. 55-56.
-
Perspectives in Biology and Medicine
, pp. 55-56
-
-
Oppenheim1
-
127
-
-
0018016812
-
G. E. Coghill (1872-1941): Pioneer neuroembryologist and developmental psychobiologist
-
83 R. W. Oppenheim, 'G. E. Coghill (1872-1941): Pioneer Neuroembryologist and Developmental Psychobiologist', Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 22 (1978) 45-64.
-
(1978)
Perspectives in Biology and Medicine
, vol.22
, pp. 45-64
-
-
Oppenheim, R.W.1
-
128
-
-
85029962931
-
-
Letter to C. J. Herrick, 27 October 1933, Neurology Collection, Herrick Papers, Spencer Research Library, University of Kansas, Lawrence, Kansas
-
84 Letter to C. J. Herrick, 27 October 1933, Neurology Collection, Herrick Papers, Spencer Research Library, University of Kansas, Lawrence, Kansas.
-
-
-
-
130
-
-
85029970776
-
-
Letter to R. Oppenheim, 31 December 1979, Myrtle B. McGraw Papers, Leonia, NJ
-
86 Letter to R. Oppenheim, 31 December 1979, Myrtle B. McGraw Papers, Leonia, NJ.
-
-
-
-
131
-
-
85029960796
-
-
note 67
-
87 See Duckett, op. cit., note 67, p. 16. The discourse Dewey employs in Art As Experience, LW: Vol. 10, pp. 1-366, is dominated by embryological metaphors such as the terms 'impulsion' and 'compression' to describe the release of energy involved in artistic expression. These terms are used by developmental biologists to describe how mesoderm and ectoderm interact during the early stages of gastrulation to form presumptive tissue and organic functions.
-
Hastings-on-Hudson
, pp. 16
-
-
Duckett1
-
132
-
-
85029967685
-
-
is dominated by embryological metaphors such as the terms 'impulsion' and 'compression' to describe the release of energy involved in artistic expression. These terms are used by developmental biologists to describe how mesoderm and ectoderm interact during the early stages of gastrulation to form presumptive tissue and organic functions
-
87 See Duckett, op. cit., note 67, p. 16. The discourse Dewey employs in Art As Experience, LW: Vol. 10, pp. 1-366, is dominated by embryological metaphors such as the terms 'impulsion' and 'compression' to describe the release of energy involved in artistic expression. These terms are used by developmental biologists to describe how mesoderm and ectoderm interact during the early stages of gastrulation to form presumptive tissue and organic functions.
-
Art as Experience, LW
, vol.10
, pp. 1-366
-
-
Dewey1
-
135
-
-
85029963195
-
-
op. cit., note 86
-
90 See McGraw, op. cit., note 86.
-
-
-
McGraw1
-
138
-
-
85029960746
-
Can logic be divorced from ontology?
-
S. Morgenbesser (ed.), New York: Journal of Philosophy Press
-
93 E. Nagel, 'Can Logic be Divorced from Ontology?', in S. Morgenbesser (ed.), Dewey and His Critics (New York: Journal of Philosophy Press, 1977), pp. 507-514. See also Nagel, op cit., note 4.
-
(1977)
Dewey and His Critics
, pp. 507-514
-
-
Nagel, E.1
-
139
-
-
85029969639
-
-
New York: Journal of Philosophy Press, note 4
-
93 E. Nagel, 'Can Logic be Divorced from Ontology?', in S. Morgenbesser (ed.), Dewey and His Critics (New York: Journal of Philosophy Press, 1977), pp. 507-514. See also Nagel, op cit., note 4.
-
LW
-
-
Nagel1
-
141
-
-
0000933396
-
Swimming behavior of the human infant
-
95 M. B. McGraw, 'Swimming Behavior of the Human Infant', Journal of Pediatrics 15 (1939), 485-490.
-
(1939)
Journal of Pediatrics
, vol.15
, pp. 485-490
-
-
McGraw, M.B.1
-
146
-
-
85029969797
-
-
100 Ibid., p. 277. McGraw's associates Livingston Welch and Louis Long (both psychologists) also demonstrated how children rely on suggestive ideas in demarcating the boundaries of generic concepts involving geometric objects. Significantly, the experimental subjects were better able, as Dewey supposed, to accurately identify the shapes at the opposing ends of a scale (i.e. comprehending the limits of the universe of objects) than to properly differentiate shapes towards the middle. Discriminating accurately between these shapes occurred only after the children had sufficient time rearranging the sequence of objects in an order that best highlighted the differences. These studies by McGraw and her associates provided the ground that Dewey sought for his argument in Logic that reasoning with concepts is subject to the same alternating forces of expansion and contraction as are the processes of neuromuscular growth and development in that disputes about meaning stem from uncertainty over the boundaries or applicability of terms and hypotheses. Accordingly, Dewey says that the extensiveness or intensiveness (i.e. connotation and denotation) of a term depend ultimately on whether objects designated by terms share the same qualitative attributes.
-
The Neuromuscular Maturation of the Human Infant
, pp. 277
-
-
-
152
-
-
0010789950
-
The theory of emotion
-
106 J. Dewey, 'The Theory of Emotion', EW: Vol. 4, pp. 152-188.
-
EW
, vol.4
, pp. 152-188
-
-
Dewey, J.1
-
154
-
-
0010789948
-
Hegel's philosophy of spirit
-
Joseph Ratner Papers, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois
-
108 J. Dewey, 'Hegel's Philosophy of Spirit', Lectures given at the University of Chicago, 1897, p. 3; Joseph Ratner Papers, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois.
-
(1897)
Lectures Given at the University of Chicago
, pp. 3
-
-
Dewey, J.1
-
156
-
-
85029960467
-
Theory of logic
-
University of Chicago, transcribed by H. H. Bawden, Jr., Joseph Ratner Papers, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois
-
110 J. Dewey, 'Theory of Logic', Lecture notes, Autumn Quarter, 1899, p. 74, University of Chicago, transcribed by H. H. Bawden, Jr., Joseph Ratner Papers, Center for Dewey Studies, Morris Library, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, Illinois.
-
(1899)
Lecture Notes, Autumn Quarter
, pp. 74
-
-
Dewey, J.1
-
157
-
-
85029969876
-
-
Letter to McGraw, 6 June, note 62
-
111 Dewey urged McGraw to devise methods to determine how infants use gestures to communicate their feelings and reason, by writing: 'I have a hunch that the beginning of language is your best problem now. It doesn't seem like the work that has been done gets very far. Your general principles of development ought to be well exemplified in control both of sounds and ideas and it is the best field it seems to me for studying relations of sensory and motor control'. Letter to McGraw, 6 June 1934, pp. 3-4, see note 62.
-
(1934)
, pp. 3-4
-
-
-
158
-
-
85029967133
-
-
note 21
-
112 J. Dewey, op. cit., note 21, p. 3.
-
Science
, pp. 3
-
-
Dewey, J.1
-
159
-
-
85029968946
-
-
113 LW: Vol. 1, pp. 132-145.
-
LW
, vol.1
, pp. 132-145
-
-
-
160
-
-
85029960385
-
-
114 Ibid., p. 293; LW: Vol. 12, pp. 285; 291-293.
-
LW
, pp. 293
-
-
-
161
-
-
85029965772
-
-
114 Ibid., p. 293; LW: Vol. 12, pp. 285; 291-293.
-
LW
, vol.12
, pp. 285
-
-
-
162
-
-
85029972607
-
-
115 Dewey, MW: Vol. 12, p. 70.
-
MW
, vol.12
, pp. 70
-
-
Dewey1
-
163
-
-
85029966240
-
-
116 Ibid., p. 253. See also H. S. Harris, Hegel's Development (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), pp. 238-255; 419-427, for the significance of free-falling bodies in Hegel's philosophy of Spirit and understanding.
-
MW
, pp. 253
-
-
-
164
-
-
0011570976
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press, for the significance of free-falling bodies in Hegel's philosophy of Spirit and understanding
-
116 Ibid., p. 253. See also H. S. Harris, Hegel's Development (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), pp. 238-255; 419-427, for the significance of free-falling bodies in Hegel's philosophy of Spirit and understanding.
-
(1983)
Hegel's Development
, pp. 238-255
-
-
Harris, H.S.1
-
165
-
-
85029972129
-
-
Dewey thought Owens' work particularly admirable because it involved the collaboration between a philosopher and biologist. Dewey to Herrick, 29 November; 5 and 11 December (see note 58)
-
117 Dewey exchanged ideas with Herrick about biological mechanisms governing human development when stimulated by a manuscript they read by Owens (first name unknown) titled 'The Principles and Mechanisms of Evolution'. Dewey thought Owens' work particularly admirable because it involved the collaboration between a philosopher and biologist. Dewey to Herrick, 29 November; 5 and 11 December 1941 (see note 58).
-
(1941)
The Principles and Mechanisms of Evolution
-
-
Owens1
-
168
-
-
85029969053
-
-
Dewey's letters to C. Chisholm, 1 July 1930; 6 January 1932; 26 July 1936; and 25 June 1937 (see note 32)
-
120 See, for example, Dewey's letters to C. Chisholm, 1 July 1930; 6 January 1932; 26 July 1936; and 25 June 1937 (see note 32).
-
-
-
-
169
-
-
0003317895
-
Neuro-motor maturation of anti-gravity functions as reflected in the development of a sitting posture
-
121 Myrtle B. McGraw, 'Neuro-Motor Maturation of Anti-Gravity Functions as Reflected in the Development of a Sitting Posture', Journal of Genetic Psychology 59 (1941), 160-172.
-
(1941)
Journal of Genetic Psychology
, vol.59
, pp. 160-172
-
-
McGraw, M.B.1
-
170
-
-
84958344843
-
The electroencephalogram during normal infancy and childhood: Rhythmic activities present in the neonate and their subsequent development
-
122 J. Roy Smith, 'The Electroencephalogram During Normal Infancy and Childhood: Rhythmic Activities Present in the Neonate and their Subsequent Development', Journal of Genetic Psychology 53 (1938), 431-453; J. Roy Smith, 'The Electroencephalogram During Normal Infancy and Childhood: The Nature of the Growth of the Alpha Waves', Journal of Genetic Psychology 53 (1938), 455-459.
-
(1938)
Journal of Genetic Psychology
, vol.53
, pp. 431-453
-
-
Smith, J.R.1
-
171
-
-
84951388113
-
The electroencephalogram during normal infancy and childhood: The nature of the growth of the alpha waves
-
122 J. Roy Smith, 'The Electroencephalogram During Normal Infancy and Childhood: Rhythmic Activities Present in the Neonate and their Subsequent Development', Journal of Genetic Psychology 53 (1938), 431-453; J. Roy Smith, 'The Electroencephalogram During Normal Infancy and Childhood: The Nature of the Growth of the Alpha Waves', Journal of Genetic Psychology 53 (1938), 455-459.
-
(1938)
Journal of Genetic Psychology
, vol.53
, pp. 455-459
-
-
Smith, J.R.1
-
172
-
-
0000495039
-
The "occipital" and "pre-central" alpha rhythms during the first two years
-
123 J. Roy Smith, 'The "Occipital" and "Pre-Central" Alpha Rhythms During the First Two Years', Journal of Psychology 7 (1939), 223-227.
-
(1939)
Journal of Psychology
, vol.7
, pp. 223-227
-
-
Smith, J.R.1
-
173
-
-
0001112420
-
-
124 Dewey, LW: Vol. 12, p. 12.
-
LW
, vol.12
, pp. 12
-
-
Dewey1
-
174
-
-
85029962563
-
-
125 Ibid., p. 220.
-
LW
, pp. 220
-
-
-
175
-
-
85029970155
-
-
126 Ibid., p. 35.
-
LW
, pp. 35
-
-
-
176
-
-
85029963993
-
-
127 Ibid., pp. 32-33.
-
LW
, pp. 32-33
-
-
-
177
-
-
85029963982
-
-
Dewey is explicit about this when he says: Integration is more fundamental than is the distinction designated by interaction of organism and environment. The latter is indicative of a partial disintegration of a prior integration, but one which is of such a dynamic nature that it moves (as long as life continues) toward reintegration (p. 40)
-
128 Ibid., p. 40. Dewey is explicit about this when he says: Integration is more fundamental than is the distinction designated by interaction of organism and environment. The latter is indicative of a partial disintegration of a prior integration, but one which is of such a dynamic nature that it moves (as long as life continues) toward reintegration (p. 40).
-
LW
, pp. 40
-
-
-
178
-
-
85029968763
-
-
129 Ibid., pp. 452-453.
-
LW
, pp. 452-453
-
-
-
179
-
-
85029960598
-
-
130 Ibid., pp. 211-213.
-
LW
, pp. 211-213
-
-
-
180
-
-
85029963656
-
-
note 3
-
131 Dewey also told Sidney Hook in early 1938 that he would further delay revisions on mathematics chapters, picking up work a month later (see Poulos, op.cit., note 3, p. 540). The NCDS annual progress report documenting preliminary findings by McGraw's associates, Weinbach, Smith, and Weech was available in June 1938. Report of the Normal Child Development Study, July 1937-June 1938, GEB-RAC, Record Group I, Series 1.3, Box 370, Folder 3859. Dewey sent his manuscript to the publisher in early June 1938, after making extensive revisions in the mathematics chapters. In addition, Dewey made additional extensive changes in the galleys in July before sending them back to the publisher in September (see Poulos, ibid., p. 543).
-
Studies in Logical Theory under the Title Essays in Experimental Logic, MW
, pp. 540
-
-
Poulos1
-
181
-
-
85029963743
-
-
July-June, GEB-RAC, Record Group I, Series 1.3, Box 370, Folder 3859. Dewey sent his manuscript to the publisher in early June 1938, after making extensive revisions in the mathematics chapters.
-
131 Dewey also told Sidney Hook in early 1938 that he would further delay revisions on mathematics chapters, picking up work a month later (see Poulos, op.cit., note 3, p. 540). The NCDS annual progress report documenting preliminary findings by McGraw's associates, Weinbach, Smith, and Weech was available in June 1938. Report of the Normal Child Development Study, July 1937-June 1938, GEB-RAC, Record Group I, Series 1.3, Box 370, Folder 3859. Dewey sent his manuscript to the publisher in early June 1938, after making extensive revisions in the mathematics chapters. In addition, Dewey made additional extensive changes in the galleys in July before sending them back to the publisher in September (see Poulos, ibid., p. 543).
-
(1937)
Report of the Normal Child Development Study
-
-
Weinbach1
Smith2
Weech3
-
182
-
-
85029963749
-
-
131 Dewey also told Sidney Hook in early 1938 that he would further delay revisions on mathematics chapters, picking up work a month later (see Poulos, op.cit., note 3, p. 540). The NCDS annual progress report documenting preliminary findings by McGraw's associates, Weinbach, Smith, and Weech was available in June 1938. Report of the Normal Child Development Study, July 1937-June 1938, GEB-RAC, Record Group I, Series 1.3, Box 370, Folder 3859. Dewey sent his manuscript to the publisher in early June 1938, after making extensive revisions in the mathematics chapters. In addition, Dewey made additional extensive changes in the galleys in July before sending them back to the publisher in September (see Poulos, ibid., p. 543).
-
Report of the Normal Child Development Study
, pp. 543
-
-
Poulos1
-
183
-
-
0015190030
-
Psychology and evolutionary naturalism in American thought, 1890-1940
-
132 H. Cravens and J. C. Burnham, 'Psychology and Evolutionary Naturalism in American Thought, 1890-1940', American Quarterly 23 (1971), 635-657; G. W. Stockings, 'Lamarckianism in American Social Science, 1890-1915', Journal of the History of Ideas 23 (1962), 239-256.
-
(1971)
American Quarterly
, vol.23
, pp. 635-657
-
-
Cravens, H.1
Burnham, J.C.2
-
184
-
-
0015190030
-
Lamarckianism in American social science, 1890-1915
-
132 H. Cravens and J. C. Burnham, 'Psychology and Evolutionary Naturalism in American Thought, 1890-1940', American Quarterly 23 (1971), 635-657; G. W. Stockings, 'Lamarckianism in American Social Science, 1890-1915', Journal of the History of Ideas 23 (1962), 239-256.
-
(1962)
Journal of the History of Ideas
, vol.23
, pp. 239-256
-
-
Stockings, G.W.1
-
185
-
-
0000442794
-
Structure, function and growth
-
133 Lawrence K. Frank, 'Structure, Function and Growth', Philosophy of Science 2 (1935), 210-235, see p. 213.
-
(1935)
Philosophy of Science
, vol.2
, pp. 210-235
-
-
Frank, L.K.1
-
187
-
-
0009182394
-
-
135 Ibid., p. 220. See also: Lawrence Frank, 'The Management of Tensions' (first published in 1928), in his collection of essays, Society as the Patient (New Brunswick NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1949), pp. 11-142.
-
Philosophy of Science
, pp. 220
-
-
-
188
-
-
85029968502
-
The management of tensions
-
first published in New Brunswick NJ: Rutgers University Press
-
135 Ibid., p. 220. See also: Lawrence Frank, 'The Management of Tensions' (first published in 1928), in his collection of essays, Society as the Patient (New Brunswick NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1949), pp. 11-142.
-
(1928)
Society as the Patient
, pp. 11-142
-
-
Frank, L.1
-
189
-
-
85029960934
-
-
Letter to McGraw, October 1935, p. 2 (no day) (see note 64)
-
136 Letter to McGraw, October 1935, p. 2 (no day) (see note 64).
-
-
-
-
190
-
-
85029965028
-
-
Dewey stresses that: 'Locomotion is a function, not a process, the processes are all the changes, muscular, nervous, skeletal etc., that come together to do the walking'. Frank argued that the value assigned to any specific structural and functional properties of an organism was relative to the field in which they were situated and that therefore, the energetics of each field possessed incommensurate magnitudes. See Frank to Brody, 4 August 1938, Lawrence K. Frank Papers, MS C, 280b, Box 1, General Correspondence, History of Medicine Division, National Library of Medicine, Bethesda, Maryland. In contrast, Dewey believed that energy was a form of motion that could be assigned a common value despite differences in the attributes of energy characteristic of any single organic field. Thus, differences in the velocity of the growth of energy complexes were evened out by rhythms issuing from a central neural mechanism
-
137 Ibid. Dewey stresses that: 'Locomotion is a function, not a process, the processes are all the changes, muscular, nervous, skeletal etc., that come together to do the walking'. Frank argued that the value assigned to any specific structural and functional properties of an organism was relative to the field in which they were situated and that therefore, the energetics of each field possessed incommensurate magnitudes. See Frank to Brody, 4 August 1938, Lawrence K. Frank Papers, MS C, 280b, Box 1, General Correspondence, History of Medicine Division, National Library of Medicine, Bethesda, Maryland. In contrast, Dewey believed that energy was a form of motion that could be assigned a common value despite differences in the attributes of energy characteristic of any single organic field. Thus, differences in the velocity of the growth of energy complexes were evened out by rhythms issuing from a central neural mechanism. See N. C. Wetzel, 'On the Motion of Growth, XVII. Theoretical Foundations', Growth 1 (1937), 6-59, for a complete elaboration of the principles underpinning Dewey's position. Dewey discusses the evolutionary implications of this conception of entropy with Chisholm. See Dewey to Chisholm, 22 July 1935, note 75.
-
Society as the Patient
-
-
-
191
-
-
0002881315
-
On the motion of growth, XVII. Theoretical foundations
-
for a complete elaboration of the principles underpinning Dewey's position. Dewey discusses the evolutionary implications of this conception of entropy with Chisholm. See Dewey to Chisholm, 22 July 1935, note 75
-
137 Ibid. Dewey stresses that: 'Locomotion is a function, not a process, the processes are all the changes, muscular, nervous, skeletal etc., that come together to do the walking'. Frank argued that the value assigned to any specific structural and functional properties of an organism was relative to the field in which they were situated and that therefore, the energetics of each field possessed incommensurate magnitudes. See Frank to Brody, 4 August 1938, Lawrence K. Frank Papers, MS C, 280b, Box 1, General Correspondence, History of Medicine Division, National Library of Medicine, Bethesda, Maryland. In contrast, Dewey believed that energy was a form of motion that could be assigned a common value despite differences in the attributes of energy characteristic of any single organic field. Thus, differences in the velocity of the growth of energy complexes were evened out by rhythms issuing from a central neural mechanism. See N. C. Wetzel, 'On the Motion of Growth, XVII. Theoretical Foundations', Growth 1 (1937), 6-59, for a complete elaboration of the principles underpinning Dewey's position. Dewey discusses the evolutionary implications of this conception of entropy with Chisholm. See Dewey to Chisholm, 22 July 1935, note 75.
-
(1937)
Growth
, vol.1
, pp. 6-59
-
-
Wetzel, N.C.1
-
193
-
-
85029963241
-
Quantitative measures in studying development of behavior patterns (Erect Locomotion)
-
The problem of recurrence was of foremost concern to Dewey at the time as indicated in his correspondence with Chisholm (see note 120)
-
139 M. B. McGraw and A. P. Weinbach, 'Quantitative Measures in Studying Development of Behavior Patterns (Erect Locomotion)', Bulletin of the Neurological Institute of New York 4 (1936), 553-571, see p. 553. The problem of recurrence was of foremost concern to Dewey at the time as indicated in his correspondence with Chisholm (see note 120).
-
(1936)
Bulletin of the Neurological Institute of New York
, vol.4
, pp. 553-571
-
-
McGraw, M.B.1
Weinbach, A.P.2
-
194
-
-
85029971487
-
-
note
-
140 Several memoranda document differences between McGraw and Frank as to the roles of additional researchers recruited to the NCDS, who included a pediatrician, a biochemist and a neurophysiologist. See, for example: Frank memorandum of interview with McGraw and Tilney, 8 May 1935; McGraw to Frank, 11 June 1935; McGraw to Frank, 12 June 1935; and Frank memorandum of interview with McGraw 18 August 18, 1935 (RAC-GEB, Record Group I, Series 1.3, Box 370, Folder 3859). The research that McGraw's associates eventually completed differed significantly from what McGraw proposed to the Advisory Council 17 May 1935. For example, although designated to assist McGraw in the study of bladder control and enuresis, biochemist A. P. Weinbach derived an acceleration constant with which to calculate the growth curve over the life span. Similarly, although neurophysiologist Ray Smith was assigned to determine how brain waves affect the development of vision and contribute to nystigmus, he actually completed a series of studies differentiating the source and effects of brain waves on sensori-motor development. These diversions of effort did not cost McGraw her job. Rockefeller officials offered to extend her grant if she focused on growth dysfunctions contributing to brain abnormalities. McGraw refused to take this approach because she did not feel that enough was understood yet about early developmental processes.
-
-
-
-
195
-
-
0011576075
-
-
London: Allen and Unwin
-
141 M. J. Petry (ed.), Hegel's Philosophy of Nature, Vol. 1 (London: Allen and Unwin, 1970). pp. 242-248.
-
(1970)
Hegel's Philosophy of Nature
, vol.1
, pp. 242-248
-
-
Petry, M.J.1
-
196
-
-
85029971171
-
Hegel's Logic
-
Section 160, at the University of Chicago, just before the turn of the century
-
142 Dewey made this argument in a class he taught on 'Hegel's Logic' (op. cit., note 29), Section 160, at the University of Chicago, just before the turn of the century.
-
Logic
-
-
Dewey1
-
198
-
-
85029971193
-
-
op. cit., note 36
-
144 Maxwell, op. cit., note 36.
-
-
-
Maxwell1
-
199
-
-
84895723429
-
-
note 115
-
145 Dewey, op. cit., note 115, p. 29.
-
MW
, pp. 29
-
-
Dewey1
-
200
-
-
0011566696
-
Contour maps, center of gravity, moment of inertia and surface of the human body
-
146 A. P. Weinbach, 'Contour Maps, Center of Gravity, Moment of Inertia and Surface of the Human Body', Human Biology 10 (1938), 356-371.
-
(1938)
Human Biology
, vol.10
, pp. 356-371
-
-
Weinbach, A.P.1
-
202
-
-
0001383156
-
Quantitative studies in the development of erect locomotion
-
Although unable to develop a behavior constant, they overcame technical difficulties by adapting projectile theory to measure key variables. They believed that the stages of erect locomotion were analogous to the trajectory taken by a projectile through a viscous medium. The speed of the projectile is slowed as it encounters resistance and its energy is dissipated, causing it to assume a parabolic trajectory. Similarly, McGraw found that at the outset, a baby will spend a disproportionate amount of time and energy in moving with characteristic staccato-like steps, contributing to sudden bursts of forward movement. Over time, however, as the center of gravity shifts with the lengthening of the legs and movement in the lower body is brought under increased cortical control, a greater amount of time is consumed on the ground stroke, reducing energy input and stabilizing the gait
-
148 M. McGraw and K. Breeze, 'Quantitative Studies in the Development of Erect Locomotion', Child Development 12 (1941), 267-303, see p. 286. Although unable to develop a behavior constant, they overcame technical difficulties by adapting projectile theory to measure key variables. They believed that the stages of erect locomotion were analogous to the trajectory taken by a projectile through a viscous medium. The speed of the projectile is slowed as it encounters resistance and its energy is dissipated, causing it to assume a parabolic trajectory. Similarly, McGraw found that at the outset, a baby will spend a disproportionate amount of time and energy in moving with characteristic staccato-like steps, contributing to sudden bursts of forward movement. Over time, however, as the center of gravity shifts with the lengthening of the legs and movement in the lower body is brought under increased cortical control, a greater amount of time is consumed on the ground stroke, reducing energy input and stabilizing the gait.
-
(1941)
Child Development
, vol.12
, pp. 267-303
-
-
McGraw, M.1
Breeze, K.2
-
203
-
-
0000315443
-
Some physiological phenomena fitted to growth equations IV. Time and power relations for a human infant climbing inclines of various slopes
-
149 A. P. Weinbach, 'Some Physiological Phenomena Fitted to Growth Equations IV. Time and Power Relations for a Human Infant Climbing Inclines of Various Slopes', Growth 4 (1938), 123-134.
-
(1938)
Growth
, vol.4
, pp. 123-134
-
-
Weinbach, A.P.1
-
204
-
-
0000496479
-
Developmental changes in attitudes as one factor determining energy output in a motor performance
-
150 V. T. Dammann, 'Developmental Changes in Attitudes as one Factor Determining Energy Output in a Motor Performance', Child Development 12 (1941), 241-246.
-
(1941)
Child Development
, vol.12
, pp. 241-246
-
-
Dammann, V.T.1
-
205
-
-
0011570977
-
Some physiological phenomena fitted to growth equations I. Moro reflex
-
151 See also, A. P. Weinbach, 'Some Physiological Phenomena Fitted to Growth Equations I. Moro Reflex', Human Biology 9 (1937), 549-555; 'Some Physiological Phenomena Fitted to Growth Equations II. Brain Potentials', Human Biology 10 (1938), 145-150; and 'Some Physiological Phenomena fitted to Growth Equations III. Rate of Growth of Brain Potentials (Alpha Frequency) Compared with Rate of Growth of the Brain', Growth 2 (1938), 247-251. See also A. P. Weinbach, 'The Human Growth Curve: I. Prenatal', Growth 5 (1941), 217-233, and 'The Human Growth Curve: II. Birth to Puberty', Growth 5 (1941), 233-255. Davenport's longitudinal skeletal studies of a sample of babies from the NCDS further supported Weinbach's growth equations. See C. B. Davenport, 'Interpretation of Certain Infantile Growth Curves', Growth 1 (1937), 279-283.
-
(1937)
Human Biology
, vol.9
, pp. 549-555
-
-
Weinbach, A.P.1
-
206
-
-
0001615259
-
Some physiological phenomena fitted to growth equations II. Brain potentials
-
151 See also, A. P. Weinbach, 'Some Physiological Phenomena Fitted to Growth Equations I. Moro Reflex', Human Biology 9 (1937), 549-555; 'Some Physiological Phenomena Fitted to Growth Equations II. Brain Potentials', Human Biology 10 (1938), 145-150; and 'Some Physiological Phenomena fitted to Growth Equations III. Rate of Growth of Brain Potentials (Alpha Frequency) Compared with Rate of Growth of the Brain', Growth 2 (1938), 247-251. See also A. P. Weinbach, 'The Human Growth Curve: I. Prenatal', Growth 5 (1941), 217-233, and 'The Human Growth Curve: II. Birth to Puberty', Growth 5 (1941), 233-255. Davenport's longitudinal skeletal studies of a sample of babies from the NCDS further supported Weinbach's growth equations. See C. B. Davenport, 'Interpretation of Certain Infantile Growth Curves', Growth 1 (1937), 279-283.
-
(1938)
Human Biology
, vol.10
, pp. 145-150
-
-
-
207
-
-
0000315444
-
Some physiological phenomena fitted to growth equations III. Rate of growth of brain potentials (alpha frequency) compared with rate of growth of the brain
-
151 See also, A. P. Weinbach, 'Some Physiological Phenomena Fitted to Growth Equations I. Moro Reflex', Human Biology 9 (1937), 549-555; 'Some Physiological Phenomena Fitted to Growth Equations II. Brain Potentials', Human Biology 10 (1938), 145-150; and 'Some Physiological Phenomena fitted to Growth Equations III. Rate of Growth of Brain Potentials (Alpha Frequency) Compared with Rate of Growth of the Brain', Growth 2 (1938), 247-251. See also A. P. Weinbach, 'The Human Growth Curve: I. Prenatal', Growth 5 (1941), 217-233, and 'The Human Growth Curve: II. Birth to Puberty', Growth 5 (1941), 233-255. Davenport's longitudinal skeletal studies of a sample of babies from the NCDS further supported Weinbach's growth equations. See C. B. Davenport, 'Interpretation of Certain Infantile Growth Curves', Growth 1 (1937), 279-283.
-
(1938)
Growth
, vol.2
, pp. 247-251
-
-
-
208
-
-
0001279597
-
The human growth curve: I. Prenatal
-
151 See also, A. P. Weinbach, 'Some Physiological Phenomena Fitted to Growth Equations I. Moro Reflex', Human Biology 9 (1937), 549-555; 'Some Physiological Phenomena Fitted to Growth Equations II. Brain Potentials', Human Biology 10 (1938), 145-150; and 'Some Physiological Phenomena fitted to Growth Equations III. Rate of Growth of Brain Potentials (Alpha Frequency) Compared with Rate of Growth of the Brain', Growth 2 (1938), 247-251. See also A. P. Weinbach, 'The Human Growth Curve: I. Prenatal', Growth 5 (1941), 217-233, and 'The Human Growth Curve: II. Birth to Puberty', Growth 5 (1941), 233-255. Davenport's longitudinal skeletal studies of a sample of babies from the NCDS further supported Weinbach's growth equations. See C. B. Davenport, 'Interpretation of Certain Infantile Growth Curves', Growth 1 (1937), 279-283.
-
(1941)
Growth
, vol.5
, pp. 217-233
-
-
Weinbach, A.P.1
-
209
-
-
0001279596
-
The human growth curve: II. Birth to puberty
-
Davenport's longitudinal skeletal studies of a sample of babies from the NCDS further supported Weinbach's growth equations
-
151 See also, A. P. Weinbach, 'Some Physiological Phenomena Fitted to Growth Equations I. Moro Reflex', Human Biology 9 (1937), 549-555; 'Some Physiological Phenomena Fitted to Growth Equations II. Brain Potentials', Human Biology 10 (1938), 145-150; and 'Some Physiological Phenomena fitted to Growth Equations III. Rate of Growth of Brain Potentials (Alpha Frequency) Compared with Rate of Growth of the Brain', Growth 2 (1938), 247-251. See also A. P. Weinbach, 'The Human Growth Curve: I. Prenatal', Growth 5 (1941), 217-233, and 'The Human Growth Curve: II. Birth to Puberty', Growth 5 (1941), 233-255. Davenport's longitudinal skeletal studies of a sample of babies from the NCDS further supported Weinbach's growth equations. See C. B. Davenport, 'Interpretation of Certain Infantile Growth Curves', Growth 1 (1937), 279-283.
-
(1941)
Growth
, vol.5
, pp. 233-255
-
-
-
210
-
-
0011635457
-
Interpretation of certain infantile growth curves
-
151 See also, A. P. Weinbach, 'Some Physiological Phenomena Fitted to Growth Equations I. Moro Reflex', Human Biology 9 (1937), 549-555; 'Some Physiological Phenomena Fitted to Growth Equations II. Brain Potentials', Human Biology 10 (1938), 145-150; and 'Some Physiological Phenomena fitted to Growth Equations III. Rate of Growth of Brain Potentials (Alpha Frequency) Compared with Rate of Growth of the Brain', Growth 2 (1938), 247-251. See also A. P. Weinbach, 'The Human Growth Curve: I. Prenatal', Growth 5 (1941), 217-233, and 'The Human Growth Curve: II. Birth to Puberty', Growth 5 (1941), 233-255. Davenport's longitudinal skeletal studies of a sample of babies from the NCDS further supported Weinbach's growth equations. See C. B. Davenport, 'Interpretation of Certain Infantile Growth Curves', Growth 1 (1937), 279-283.
-
(1937)
Growth
, vol.1
, pp. 279-283
-
-
Davenport, C.B.1
-
211
-
-
85029962631
-
-
Noteworthy in this regard is Herrick's argument that the cerebral cortex consists of 'projection centers' that enable humans to adapt to new circumstances through the continuous correlation and translation of unfamiliar stimuli into familiar terms
-
152 Dewey, LW: Vol. 12, pp. 397-399. Noteworthy in this regard is Herrick's argument that the cerebral cortex consists of 'projection centers' that enable humans to adapt to new circumstances through the continuous correlation and translation of unfamiliar stimuli into familiar terms. See Herrick, op.cit., note 26, p. 273).
-
LW
, vol.12
, pp. 397-399
-
-
Dewey1
-
212
-
-
84981645166
-
-
note 26
-
152 Dewey, LW: Vol. 12, pp. 397-399. Noteworthy in this regard is Herrick's argument that the cerebral cortex consists of 'projection centers' that enable humans to adapt to new circumstances through the continuous correlation and translation of unfamiliar stimuli into familiar terms. See Herrick, op.cit., note 26, p. 273).
-
The Evolution of Human Nature
, pp. 273
-
-
Herrick1
-
213
-
-
0011623733
-
Dewey's theory of natural science
-
Sidney Hook (ed.), New York: Dial Press
-
153 Stuart Nagel, 'Dewey's Theory of Natural Science', in Sidney Hook (ed.), John Dewey: Philosopher of Science and Freedom (New York: Dial Press, 1950), pp. 247-248).
-
(1950)
John Dewey: Philosopher of Science and Freedom
, pp. 247-248
-
-
Nagel, S.1
-
215
-
-
0011639956
-
Professional and personal blunders in child development research
-
McGraw also complained that a prejudice against subjective judgments favored established methods that 'precluded the evolvement of new techniques which could adequately handle the type of data obtained only through the mental integration of the trained observer'
-
155 M. B. McGraw, 'Professional and Personal Blunders in Child Development Research', Psychological Record 35 (1985), 165-170, see p. 170. McGraw also complained that a prejudice against subjective judgments favored established methods that 'precluded the evolvement of new techniques which could adequately handle the type of data obtained only through the mental integration of the trained observer'. McGraw, 'Appraising Test Responses of Infants and Young Children', The Journal of Psychology 14 (1942), 89-100, see p. 99.
-
(1985)
Psychological Record
, vol.35
, pp. 165-170
-
-
McGraw, M.B.1
-
216
-
-
0011571293
-
Appraising test responses of infants and young children
-
155 M. B. McGraw, 'Professional and Personal Blunders in Child Development Research', Psychological Record 35 (1985), 165-170, see p. 170. McGraw also complained that a prejudice against subjective judgments favored established methods that 'precluded the evolvement of new techniques which could adequately handle the type of data obtained only through the mental integration of the trained observer'. McGraw, 'Appraising Test Responses of Infants and Young Children', The Journal of Psychology 14 (1942), 89-100, see p. 99.
-
(1942)
The Journal of Psychology
, vol.14
, pp. 89-100
-
-
McGraw1
-
217
-
-
0004089989
-
-
Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press
-
156 For an analysis of the factors contributing to misinterpretations of McGraw's work and an examination by contemporary researchers of why her discoveries and Dewey's ideas about inquiry remain pertinent today see T. C. Dalton and V. W. Bergenn (eds), Beyond Heredity and Environment: Myrtle McGraw and the Maturation Controversy (Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press, 1995.
-
(1995)
Beyond Heredity and Environment: Myrtle Mcgraw and the Maturation Controversy
-
-
Dalton, T.C.1
Bergenn, V.W.2
-
218
-
-
85029960795
-
-
note 18
-
157 The widely reported fact that Johnny's special stimulation did not result in any significant differences in ultimate performance, since Jimmy eventually was able to complete the same tasks as Johnny, overshadowed the significant qualitative differences in Johny's capacity for problem solving. See Dennis, op. cit., note 18, pp. 362-363.
-
Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences
, pp. 362-363
-
-
Dennis1
-
219
-
-
84883949201
-
-
was consumed largely by responding to challenges posed about the validity of the psychological premises underpinning his theory of knowledge. Dewey's frequent but perfunctory appeals to the 'facts' of sensori-motor processes and oblique reference to the term 'integration' seemed insufficient gestures to support the psychological validity of theory of inquiry. These rhetorical skirmishes left little opportunity for Dewey to demonstrate the transformational nature of inquiry, or to illustrate in more detail the principles he proposed to replace the traditional canons of formal logic
-
158 Dewey's defense of Logic was consumed largely by responding to challenges posed about the validity of the psychological premises underpinning his theory of knowledge. Dewey's frequent but perfunctory appeals to the 'facts' of sensori-motor processes and oblique reference to the term 'integration' seemed insufficient gestures to support the psychological validity of theory of inquiry. These rhetorical skirmishes left little opportunity for Dewey to demonstrate the transformational nature of inquiry, or to illustrate in more detail the principles he proposed to replace the traditional canons of formal logic. See Dewey, op. cit., note 1.
-
Logic
-
-
Dewey1
-
220
-
-
0003738544
-
-
note 1
-
158 Dewey's defense of Logic was consumed largely by responding to challenges posed about the validity of the psychological premises underpinning his theory of knowledge. Dewey's frequent but perfunctory appeals to the 'facts' of sensori-motor processes and oblique reference to the term 'integration' seemed insufficient gestures to support the psychological validity of theory of inquiry. These rhetorical skirmishes left little opportunity for Dewey to demonstrate the transformational nature of inquiry, or to illustrate in more detail the principles he proposed to replace the traditional canons of formal logic. See Dewey, op. cit., note 1.
-
The Philosophy of John Dewey
-
-
Dewey1
-
222
-
-
0039947634
-
Science as solidarity
-
J. Nelson (ed.), Madison: University of Wisconsin Press
-
160 R. Rorty, 'Science as Solidarity', in J. Nelson (ed.), The Rhetoric of the Human Sciences (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1987).
-
(1987)
The Rhetoric of the Human Sciences
-
-
Rorty, R.1
|