-
3
-
-
0020185689
-
Darwin's Conversion: The Beagle Voyage and Its Aftermath
-
See Frank J. Sulloway, "Darwin's Conversion: The Beagle Voyage and Its Aftermath," J. Hist. Biol., 15 (1982), 325-396.
-
(1982)
J. Hist. Biol.
, vol.15
, pp. 325-396
-
-
Sulloway, F.J.1
-
4
-
-
25844461082
-
-
Darwin, autobiography (above, n. 1), p. 48
-
Darwin, autobiography (above, n. 1), p. 48.
-
-
-
-
5
-
-
0003458407
-
-
Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press
-
See Notebook D, in Charles Darwin's Notebooks, 1836-1844, eds. Paul H. Barrett et al., (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1987), pp. 134-135 (subsequent references to the notebooks will be to this edition) ; cf. Darwin, autobiography, p. 71.
-
(1987)
Charles Darwin's Notebooks, 1836-1844
, pp. 134-135
-
-
Barrett, P.H.1
-
6
-
-
25844485130
-
-
Darwin, autobiography, p. 74
-
Darwin, autobiography, p. 74.
-
-
-
-
7
-
-
0003867942
-
-
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
-
See Ernst Mayr, The Growth of Biological Thought (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1982), p. 266.
-
(1982)
The Growth of Biological Thought
, pp. 266
-
-
Mayr, E.1
-
8
-
-
25844511698
-
-
Cf. Darwin, Notebook C, p. 152
-
Cf. Darwin, Notebook C, p. 152.
-
-
-
-
10
-
-
25844466494
-
-
Darwin, Notebook M, p. 84
-
Darwin, Notebook M, p. 84.
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
2442589823
-
-
London: Paladin
-
Antony Flew, Darwinian Evolution (London: Paladin, 1984), pp. 46-47.
-
(1984)
Darwinian Evolution
, pp. 46-47
-
-
Flew, A.1
-
12
-
-
0003718037
-
-
New York: W. W. Norton, according to Desmond and Moore
-
But see Adrian Desmond and James Moore, Darwin: The Life of a Tormented Evolutionist (New York: W. W. Norton, 1994): according to Desmond and Moore (pp. 87-88), among the works that Darwin was examined on in his final examination at Cambridge (January 1831) was Locke's Essay.
-
(1994)
Darwin: The Life of a Tormented Evolutionist
, pp. 87-88
-
-
Desmond, A.1
Moore, J.2
-
13
-
-
25844494125
-
Introduction to Notebook M
-
Barrett et al., above, n. 5
-
Sandra Herbert and Paul H. Barrett, "Introduction to Notebook M," in Barrett et al., Darwin's Notebooks (above, n. 5), p. 518.
-
Darwin's Notebooks
, pp. 518
-
-
Herbert, S.1
Barrett, P.H.2
-
14
-
-
84865843753
-
-
above, n. 9
-
Unlike Descartes and many others, Locke, in subscribing to the Great Chain of Being, did much the same as Darwin (see Essay [above, n. 9], IV.xvi.12). Nevertheless, he denied that animals below man have the power of abstract thought, and he affirmed that this "puts a perfect distinction betwixt Man and Brutes" (II.xi.10).
-
Essay
-
-
Darwin1
-
15
-
-
25844456328
-
-
Cf. Darwin, Notebook C, p. 243, and Notebook M, p. 123
-
Cf. Darwin, Notebook C, p. 243, and Notebook M, p. 123.
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
25844467701
-
-
Darwin, Notebook D, pp. 36-37
-
Darwin, Notebook D, pp. 36-37.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
0000488406
-
Biological Species as Natural Kinds
-
David B. Kitts and David J. Kitts, "Biological Species as Natural Kinds," Phil. Sci., 46 (1979), 618.
-
(1979)
Phil. Sci.
, vol.46
, pp. 618
-
-
Kitts, D.B.1
Kitts, D.J.2
-
20
-
-
84883904823
-
-
See Darwin, Origin, pp. 47, 59, 248, 276, 297, 469.
-
Origin
, pp. 47
-
-
Darwin1
-
21
-
-
61149230995
-
The Effect of Essentialism on Taxonomy: Two Thousand Years of Stasis
-
See, for example, David Hull, "The Effect of Essentialism on Taxonomy: Two Thousand Years of Stasis," Brit. J. Phil. Sci., 15 (1965), 320;
-
(1965)
Brit. J. Phil. Sci.
, vol.15
, pp. 320
-
-
Hull, D.1
-
22
-
-
0003601219
-
-
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
-
Ernst Mayr, Populations, Species, and Evolution (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1970), p. 13;
-
(1970)
Populations, Species, and Evolution
, pp. 13
-
-
Mayr, E.1
-
23
-
-
0007687257
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Jonathan Howard, Darwin (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982), pp. 17, 37;
-
(1982)
Darwin
, pp. 17
-
-
Howard, J.1
-
24
-
-
0005926299
-
-
Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
Niles Eldredge, Time Frames (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989), pp. 109-110;
-
(1989)
Time Frames
, pp. 109-110
-
-
Eldredge, N.1
-
27
-
-
0011680369
-
Speaking of Species: Darwin's Strategy
-
ed. David Kohn Princeton: Princeton University Press
-
Quoted in John Beatty, "Speaking of Species: Darwin's Strategy," in The Darwinian Heritage, ed. David Kohn (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985), p. 270.
-
(1985)
The Darwinian Heritage
, pp. 270
-
-
Beatty, J.1
-
28
-
-
0004095302
-
-
Boulder: Westview Press
-
Elliott Sober, Philosophy of Biology (Boulder: Westview Press, 1993), p. 143.
-
(1993)
Philosophy of Biology
, pp. 143
-
-
Sober, E.1
-
34
-
-
84883904823
-
-
See Darwin, Origin, pp. 49-50, 247, 268, 424, 485.
-
Origin
, pp. 49-50
-
-
Darwin1
-
37
-
-
0003867942
-
-
above, n. 7
-
See, for example, Mayr, Growth of Biological Thought (above, n. 7), pp. 288-289, 640-641, 741.
-
Growth of Biological Thought
, pp. 288-289
-
-
Mayr1
-
40
-
-
77952732868
-
-
above, n. 1
-
, and autobiography (above, n. 1), pp. 73-74.
-
Autobiography
, pp. 73-74
-
-
-
41
-
-
84883904823
-
-
See Darwin, Origin, pp. 44, 47, 49, 51-52, 248, 268, 484-485.
-
Origin
, pp. 44
-
-
Darwin1
-
42
-
-
0003756180
-
-
New York: Columbia University Press
-
See, for example, George Gaylord Simpson, Principles of Animal Taxonomy (New York: Columbia University Press, 1961), p. 129
-
(1961)
Principles of Animal Taxonomy
, pp. 129
-
-
Simpson, G.G.1
-
43
-
-
0004039596
-
-
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
-
, and Ernst Mayr, Toward a New Philosophy of Biology (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1988), pp. 187, 314.
-
(1988)
Toward a New Philosophy of Biology
, pp. 187
-
-
Mayr, E.1
-
44
-
-
25844517017
-
-
note
-
Horizontal species, of course, are ontologically prior to vertical species. If vertical species are real, then so must horizontal species be real. But if vertical species are not real, that does not mean that horizontal species are not real (any more than in the case of evolving languages). Horizontal species may be real without being vertically real. But clearly if horizontal species are not real, then neither are vertical species. To affirm the unreality of biological species taxa, then, although one must affirm the unreality of both vertical and horizontal species taxa, the issue comes down to whether horizontal species taxa are real.
-
-
-
-
45
-
-
0003867942
-
-
above, n. 7
-
Mayr, Growth of Biological Thought (above, n. 7), p. 273. It should be noted that by "multidimensional" Mayr is referring to populations compared at different times and different places. Whether members from two different populations completely separated in either space or time, or in both, can furtively interbreed can never be determined by observation but can only be inferred. Such inferences result in a multidimensional species concept. Since horizontal species refer to conspecific populations that may be separated geographically but not temporally, Mayr's nondimensional/multidimensional distinction, contrary to what he thinks elsewhere
-
Growth of Biological Thought
, pp. 273
-
-
Mayr1
-
46
-
-
0004039596
-
-
above, n. 35
-
(cf. Mayr, Toward a New Philosophy [above, n. 35], p. 314), does not perfectly correspond to the horizontal/vertical distinction.
-
Toward a New Philosophy
, pp. 314
-
-
Mayr1
-
48
-
-
25844527091
-
-
See Darwin, Notebook N, p. 65, and Origin, pp. 422-423.
-
Origin
, pp. 422-423
-
-
-
50
-
-
0024773729
-
Competition
-
ed. J. M. Cherrett Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications
-
I myself am skeptical, but am of course incompetent to pass judgment. I think of, for example, members of Pongo pygmaeus (orangutans), which in the wild live an almost exclusively solitary existence: it seems evident that their competition comes mainly from man and not from each other. But this may indeed be an exception. Darwin may be right as a rule - his "almost invariably." Against my view, it is almost a truism in ecology that species occupy niches, and that if two species occupy the same niche, one will eventually cause the extinction of the other, this is known as the competitive exclusion principle (or Gause's axiom). It would seem to follow that "niche differentiation should reduce competition between species relative to that within species" (R. Law and A. R. Watkinson, "Competition," in Ecological Concepts, ed. J. M. Cherrett [Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications, 1989], p. 273). However, as Law and Watkinson point out (pp. 275-276), there are almost no data to support this or any conclusion on the relative strengths of the two types of competition.
-
(1989)
Ecological Concepts
, pp. 273
-
-
Law, R.1
Watkinson, A.R.2
-
51
-
-
0003867942
-
-
above, n. 7
-
Of course, one might naturally credit Lamarck instead. Not only did he stress gradualness, but on his view all extinction is pseudo-extinction. He believed that any given species does not cease to exist by evolving into another species but continues to exist in that new form (cf. Mayr, Growth of Biological Thought [above, n. 7], p. 349).
-
Growth of Biological Thought
, pp. 349
-
-
Mayr1
-
52
-
-
0003756180
-
-
above, n. 35
-
One consequence of this view is that it makes out of the tree of life one large phylogenetic continuum (Simpson, Principles of Animal Taxonomy [above, n. 35], p. 51) and consequently one big species.
-
Principles of Animal Taxonomy
, pp. 51
-
-
Simpson1
-
53
-
-
0003867942
-
-
And from this one big species it is easy to conclude that there are no species (plural) in any conventional sense, that any method of chopping up the continuum is entirely arbitrary. And that was precisely Lamarck's view: like numerous species nominalists before him, but now for entirely new reasons, he found himself forced to conclude that only individual organisms are real, although he was later to recant (Mayr, Growth of Biological Thought, p. 264).
-
Growth of Biological Thought
, pp. 264
-
-
Mayr1
-
54
-
-
84883904823
-
-
However, unlike Darwin (cf. Origin, p. 484), Lamarck apparently did not hold a belief in common descent, the view that all life can be traced back to one or a few ancestors in the very remote past.
-
Origin
, pp. 484
-
-
Darwin1
-
55
-
-
0003867942
-
-
And yet he did, in a sense, inaugurate the historical version of the Great Chain of Being, modifying the Great Chain into branches, with all lineages beginning at the most rudimentary level and evolving upward through levels of ever-increasing complexity, upward all the way to humans, who are still evolving. Combined with what was then the widespread belief in constant and rudimentary spontaneous generation - a view not shared by Darwin, who, like biologists today, thought that the favorable conditions for the origin of life were long distant in the past (Mayr, Growth of Biological Thought, pp. 582-583) - Lamarck's tree of life is perhaps better thought of as a homogeneous forest.
-
Growth of Biological Thought
, pp. 582-583
-
-
Mayr1
-
56
-
-
84883904823
-
-
See Darwin, Origin, pp. 88, 168, 208, 313, 345, 388, 406, 468.
-
Origin
, pp. 88
-
-
Darwin1
-
57
-
-
25844474033
-
-
See Origin, ibid., pp. 194, 206, 210, 454, 460, 471.
-
Origin
, pp. 194
-
-
-
58
-
-
0004039907
-
-
Sunderland, Mass.: Sinauer
-
Douglas J. Futuyma, Evolutionary Biology (Sunderland, Mass.: Sinauer, 1986), p. 228.
-
(1986)
Evolutionary Biology
, pp. 228
-
-
Futuyma, D.J.1
-
60
-
-
84883904823
-
-
See Darwin, Origin, p. 124 for his discussion.
-
Origin
, pp. 124
-
-
Darwin1
|