메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 31, Issue 4, 2001, Pages 32-40

On knowing the 'why': Particularism and moral theory

(1)  Little, Margaret Olivia a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords

ANALYTICAL APPROACH; ARTICLE; BIOETHICS AND PROFESSIONAL ETHICS; ETHICAL THEORY; ETHICS; HUMAN; MORALITY; PHILOSOPHICAL APPROACH; UNITED STATES;

EID: 0013116588     PISSN: 00930334     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/3527954     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (42)

References (29)
  • 1
    • 0004206765 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell Publishers
    • John McDowell is cited by many as inspiration for the view, which is developed and endorsed more explicitly by, among others, J. Dancy, Moral Reasons (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1993);
    • (1993) Moral Reasons
    • Dancy, J.1
  • 2
    • 0004312818 scopus 로고
    • chapter 13 Oxford: Blackwell Publishers
    • D. McNaughton, chapter 13 of Moral Vision (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1988);
    • (1988) Moral Vision
    • McNaughton, D.1
  • 3
    • 14544280447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Generalities Revisited
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press, ed. B. Hooker and M.O. Little
    • M. Little, "Moral Generalities Revisited," in Moral Particularism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000), ed. B. Hooker and M.O. Little. For recent debate on the view as such, see
    • (2000) Moral Particularism
    • Little, M.1
  • 4
    • 0013154798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • B. Hooker and M.O. Little, eds.
    • B. Hooker and M.O. Little, eds., Moral Particularism.
    • Moral Particularism.
  • 6
    • 0009880364 scopus 로고
    • S. Clarke and E. Simpson, eds., Albany: State University of New York
    • For a collection of related essays, see S. Clarke and E. Simpson, eds., Anti-Theory in Ethics and Moral Conservatism (Albany: State University of New York, 1989).
    • (1989) Anti-Theory in Ethics and Moral Conservatism
  • 8
    • 0003667932 scopus 로고
    • Morality and Conflict
    • Oxford: Blackwell Publishers
    • S. Hampshire, "Morality and Conflict," in his Morality and Conflict (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1983).
    • (1983) Morality and Conflict
    • Hampshire, S.1
  • 9
    • 33747657396 scopus 로고
    • Theory and Reflective Practices
    • Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
    • A. Baier, "Theory and Reflective Practices," in her Postures of the Mind: Essays in Mind and Morals (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1985).
    • (1985) Postures of the Mind: Essays in Mind and Morals
    • Baier, A.1
  • 10
    • 0004195469 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • To the objections just presented we can add two others that concern epistemological issues less relevant to the discussion pursued above. When Bernard Williams objects to theory, for instance, his central point is to criticize the idea that it might admit justification that is transcendent of a culture's norms. See his Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985). And sometimes "antitheory" is used to describe objections to the claim, no longer current, that justification always proceeds in a "top-down" fashion - that is, that intuitions about generalizations always carry more weight than intuitions about individual cases.
    • (1985) Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy
  • 11
    • 85009007897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Kant, for instance, is often singled out as a particularly egregious sinner in these regards, but as many have pointed out, he never denied the need for judgment or dismissed entirely the importance of emotion in the human moral life. And Aristotle, often touted as the exemplar for amitheorists, is often let off the hook too lightly. As Hampshire notes (see ref. 4), Aristotle was dismissive of the idea that moral values and directives located in "conventions," such as the way society organizes familial or sexual relations, could nonetheless be fully authoritative for those within those ways of life. And while not a reductivist, he was a true-born systematist of the sort objected to in the following paragraphs (although he agreed that the concepts needed to describe morality are open-ended): each virtue is assigned its domain, and all are capable of being corralled under one notion - flourishing - to boot.
  • 12
    • 85009003202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Most everyone, of course, will agree that moral concepts can all be organized under very abstract concepts, though disagreement will persist in the extent to which those abstract concepts thus do any real work for us
    • Most everyone, of course, will agree that moral concepts can all be organized under very abstract concepts, though disagreement will persist in the extent to which those abstract concepts thus do any real work for us.
  • 13
    • 84929746428 scopus 로고
    • The Advantages of Moral Diversity
    • A. Rorty, "The Advantages of Moral Diversity," Social Philosophy and Policy 9, no. 2 (1992): 38-62.
    • (1992) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.9 , Issue.2 , pp. 38-62
    • Rorty, A.1
  • 15
    • 84917344439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Murdoch, Practical Reasoning, and Particularism
    • forthcoming
    • E. Milgram, "Murdoch, Practical Reasoning, and Particularism," forthcoming in Notizie di Politeia.
    • Notizie di Politeia
    • Milgram, E.1
  • 16
    • 85009009650 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The pain example is from Milgram, the Diplomacy example from Mark Lance, and the pleasure example from Dancy, who further attributes it to Roy Hattersley
    • The pain example is from Milgram, the Diplomacy example from Mark Lance, and the pleasure example from Dancy, who further attributes it to Roy Hattersley.
  • 17
    • 33747495044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unprincipled Ethics
    • ed. Little and Hooker
    • A good representative of the first can be found in D. McNaughton and P. Rawlings, "Unprincipled Ethics," in Moral Particularism, ed. Little and Hooker, pp. 256-75. An example of the second is in
    • Moral Particularism , pp. 256-275
    • McNaughton, D.1    Rawlings, P.2
  • 18
    • 84977360988 scopus 로고
    • In Defense of Thick Concepts
    • Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
    • J. Dancy, "In Defense of Thick Concepts," Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 20 (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota, 1995).
    • (1995) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.20
    • Dancy, J.1
  • 19
    • 85008980501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that the two sorts of objection are different. One could be a holist about the reason-giving force of considerations and yet believe moral concepts capable of nontrivial exhaustive definitions. Note, too, that one may well believe there remain pockets of well-ordered theory even if the whole is not so systematic. (Many, for instance, will believe the cluster of concepts dealing with interference, agency, and consent form such an internally codifiable system, however messily it might interface with other moral considerations.) I myself think it motley all the way down; but again, this is only an issue of how widely the particularist wants to cast her net.
  • 20
    • 0009045305 scopus 로고
    • Eating Meat and Eating People
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Massachusetts Institute ofTechnology Press
    • This is the central point of Cora Diamond's, "Anything But Argument?" The reference to animals and poetry in this paragraph is a reference to her "Eating Meat and Eating People," both from her The Realistic Spirit: Wittgenstein, Philosophy, and the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: Massachusetts Institute ofTechnology Press, 1991).
    • (1991) The Realistic Spirit: Wittgenstein, Philosophy, and the Mind
  • 21
    • 85008990666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My thanks to Mark Lance for the example
    • My thanks to Mark Lance for the example.
  • 22
    • 33747671019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wittgensteinian Lessons on Particularism
    • ed. C. Elliott Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press
    • See M.O. Little, "Wittgensteinian Lessons on Particularism," in Wittgensteinian Bioethics, ed. C. Elliott (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2001), and
    • (2001) Wittgensteinian Bioethics
    • Little, M.O.1
  • 23
    • 33747731722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Particularity and Principle: The Structure of Moral Knowledge
    • ed. Hooker and Little
    • J. Garfield, "Particularity and Principle: The Structure of Moral Knowledge," in Moral Particularism, ed. Hooker and Little, pp. 178-204.
    • Moral Particularism , pp. 178-204
    • Garfield, J.1
  • 26
    • 33747677099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ethics as an Inexact Science: Aristotle's Ambitions for Moral Theory
    • ed. Hooker and Little
    • For an argument defending the claim that Aristotle himself could not have endorsed a statistical interpretation of "for the most part" generalizations, but which then tries therefore to render them in principle exceptionless, see T.H. Irwin, "Ethics as an Inexact Science: Aristotle's Ambitions for Moral Theory," in Moral Particularism, ed. Hooker and Little, pp. 100-129.
    • Moral Particularism , pp. 100-129
    • Irwin, T.H.1
  • 27
    • 85008994518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In this section, I am presenting work done jointly with my colleague Mark Lance, which we are developing more fully in a book tentatively tided "Porous Generalizations and Privileged Conditions." This section also signals an important change in the view I presented in "Moral Generalities Reconsidered," where I defended a more radical particularism that denied moral imports to features such as lying - the import we precisely work here to recover.
  • 28
    • 85008994519 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Not an epistemic default, in the sense of something we can justifiably presume is true until we see evidence to the contrary: a court servant at Versailles might wisely abandon his usual presumption of sitting on the chairs he encounters; the person who realizes she is going into the hologram chamber rightly presumes to distrust what her eyes seem to tell her.
  • 29
    • 85009009637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • These are different and more robust than the explanatory generalizations I defended in the last section of "Moral Generalities Reconsidered." There my concern was to provide an analysis of the "good-making" relationship (not the notion of moral nature here discussed); the explanations recovered there hence apply equally well to something like shoelace color, wherever it does in fact count as a good-making feature.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.