메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 106, Issue 1, 1997, Pages 35-68

How we learn mathematical language

(1)  McGee, Vann a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0012539398     PISSN: 00318108     EISSN: 15581470     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/2998341     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (113)

References (59)
  • 1
    • 0011290659 scopus 로고
    • Meaning
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • Cf. H. P. Grice, "Meaning," in Studies in the Way of Words (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989), 213-223
    • (1989) Studies in the Way of Words , pp. 213-223
    • Grice, H.P.1
  • 2
    • 0012586667 scopus 로고
    • What numbers could not be
    • "What Numbers Could Not Be," Philosophical Review 74 (1965): 47-73.
    • (1965) Philosophical Review , vol.74 , pp. 47-73
  • 3
    • 77950060862 scopus 로고
    • Reprinted
    • 2d ed., ed. Benacerraf and Hilary Putnam (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Reprinted in Philosophy of Mathematics, 2d ed., ed. Benacerraf and Hilary Putnam (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), 272-294
    • (1983) Philosophy of Mathematics , pp. 272-294
  • 4
    • 0000849473 scopus 로고
    • Untersuchungen über die grundlagen der mengenlehre I
    • Ernst Zermelo, "Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre I," Malhematische Annalen 65 (1908): 261-281
    • (1908) Malhematische Annalen , vol.65 , pp. 261-281
    • Zermelo, E.1
  • 5
    • 0039170583 scopus 로고
    • Investigations in the foundations of set theory I
    • English translation by, ed. Jean van Heijenoort, Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • English translation by Stefan BauerMengelberg, "Investigations in the Foundations of Set Theory I," in From Frege to Gödel, ed. Jean van Heijenoort (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1967), 199-223.
    • (1967) From Frege to Gödel , pp. 199-223
    • Bauer Mengelberg, S.1
  • 7
    • 77950055881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the introduction of transfinite numbers
    • English translation by
    • English translation by van Heijenoort, "On the Introduction of Transfinite Numbers," in From Frege to Gödel, 346-54.
    • From Frege to Gödel , pp. 346-354
    • Heijenoort, V.1
  • 9
    • 0003438275 scopus 로고
    • Reprinted in, Oxford: Oxford University Press, Clarendon Press
    • Reprinted in Davidson's Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, Clarendon Press, 1984), 227-41.
    • (1984) Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation , pp. 227-241
    • Davidson1
  • 10
    • 0004235120 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, chap. 2 and appendix
    • Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth, and History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), chap. 2 and appendix.
    • (1981) Reason Truth and History
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 11
    • 77950059981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For impure abstracta, like the set of justices of the U.S. Supreme Court, the inscrutability is mitigated, since, arguably, the set is located where the court sits
    • For impure abstracta, like the set of justices of the U.S. Supreme Court, the inscrutability is mitigated, since, arguably, the set is located where the court sits.
  • 12
    • 0004202287 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, Clarendon Press
    • See Penelope Maddy, Realism in Mathematics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, Clarendon Press, 1990).
    • (1990) Realism in Mathematics
    • Maddy, P.1
  • 13
    • 49249117198 scopus 로고
    • A semantic conception of truth?
    • Its status is discussed further in my
    • Its status is discussed further in my "A Semantic Conception of Truth?" Philosophical Topics 21 (1993): 83-111.
    • (1993) Philosophical Topics , vol.21 , pp. 83-111
  • 14
    • 77950055010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The meaning of arithmetical terms, as we currently use them, ensures the truth of all conditionals with "The natural numbers exist" as antecedent and an axiom as consequent, but meaning is highly mutable. Should we discover that there is no structure that satisfies all the axioms, we might respond by saying diat we have learned that there are no natural numbers. But we might instead respond by changing the waywe use number words, adopting a new conception according to which the natural numbers exist but some of the axioms we hitherto accepted are false. Which course we would choose is difficult to predict
    • The meaning of arithmetical terms, as we currently use them, ensures the truth of all conditionals with "The natural numbers exist" as antecedent and an axiom as consequent, but meaning is highly mutable. Should we discover that there is no structure that satisfies all the axioms, we might respond by saying diat we have learned that there are no natural numbers. But we might instead respond by changing the way we use number words, adopting a new conception according to which the natural numbers exist but some of the axioms we hitherto accepted are false. Which course we would choose is difficult to predict.
  • 15
    • 77950048277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To connect numbers with popsicle sticks, we might use a rudimentary set theory,or we might employ higher-order logic. The latter counts as "non-arithmetical" only because the range of the individual variables includes things other than numbers
    • To connect numbers with popsicle sticks, we might use a rudimentary set theory, or we might employ higher-order logic. The latter counts as "non-arithmetical" only because the range of the individual variables includes things other than numbers.
  • 16
    • 3843068521 scopus 로고
    • Ontological commitment, thick and thin
    • ed. George Boolos Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Harold Hodes, "Ontological Commitment, Thick and Thin," in Meaning and Method, ed. George Boolos (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 235-60.
    • (1990) Meaning and Method , pp. 235-260
    • Hodes, H.1
  • 17
    • 77950025932 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To show that the theory is true, one must show that there is at least one structure that satisfies the axioms.Inasmuch as any two structures that satisfy the axioms are isomorphic, an arithmetic sentence will count as true if and only if it is true inat least one structure that satisfies the axioms, or, equivalently, if and only if it is true in every structure that satisfies the axioms
    • To show that the theory is true, one must show that there is at least one structure that satisfies the axioms. Inasmuch as any two structures that satisfy the axiomsare isomorphic, an arithmetic sentence will count as true if and only if it is true inat least one structure that satisfies the axioms, or, equivalently, if and only if it is true in every structure that satisfies the axioms.
  • 18
    • 0002228435 scopus 로고
    • Theories
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Frank P. Ramsey, "Theories," in his Philosophical Papers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 112-36.
    • (1990) Philosophical Papers , pp. 112-136
    • Ramsey, F.P.1
  • 19
    • 0004238871 scopus 로고
    • Robinson's R is a simple system of extremely rudimentary arithmetical axioms, little more than extended addition and multiplication tables. See Alfred Tarski, Andrzej Mostowski, and Raphael M. Robinson, Amsterdam: North-Holland
    • Robinson's R is a simple system of extremely rudimentary arithmetical axioms, little more than extended addition and multiplication tables. See Alfred Tarski, Andrzej Mostowski, and Raphael M. Robinson, Undecidable Theories (Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1953), 53.
    • (1953) Undecidable Theories , pp. 53
    • Tarski, A.1    Mostowski, A.2    Robinson, R.M.3
  • 20
    • 0013424925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The general thesis that second-order logic is fundamental to our mathematical understanding is developed in Stewart Shapiro's highly insightful, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, Clarendon Press
    • The general thesis that second-order logic is fundamental to our mathematical understanding is developed in Stewart Shapiro's highly insightful Foundations without Foundationalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, Clarendon Press, 1991).
    • (1991) Foundations without Foundationalism
  • 21
    • 77950035902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The second-order variables come in different sorts, taking the grammatical positions of one-place predicates, two-place predicates, three-place predicates, and so on. A careful notation would distinguish the sorts, but here I shall be sloppy, countingon context to indicate which sort is intended
    • The second-order variables come in different sorts, taking the grammatical positions of one-place predicates, two-place predicates, three-place predicates, and so on. A careful notation would distinguish the sorts, but here I shall be sloppy, counting on context to indicate which sort is intended.
  • 22
    • 77950031084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Within purely arithmetical investigations, the restriction of one's quantifiers to natural numbers is typically tacit. For applications, however, one needs to make the restriction explicit
    • Within purely arithmetical investigations, the restriction of one's quantifiers to natural numbers is typically tacit. For applications, however, one needs to make the restriction explicit.
  • 24
    • 0040818210 scopus 로고
    • The nature and meaning of numbers
    • English translation by, New York: Dover
    • English translation by Wooster Woodruff Beman, "The Nature and Meaning of Numbers," in Dedekind's Essays on the Theory of Numbers (New York: Dover, 1963), 29-115.
    • (1963) Dedekind's Essays on the Theory of Numbers , pp. 29-115
    • Beman, W.W.1
  • 25
    • 77950038161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, every two models of the theory are isomorphic
    • That is, every two models of the theory are isomorphic.
  • 26
    • 77950046745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intuitionists would dispute this, of course. Affirming the traditional view that logic is universal (which goes back to Metaphysics I) is part of our presumptive commitment to realism
    • Intuitionists would dispute this, of course. Affirming the traditional view that logic is universal (which goes back to Metaphysics I) is part of our presumptive commitment to realism.
  • 27
    • 0004242804 scopus 로고
    • 2d ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • Philosophy of Logic, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986), 66.
    • (1986) Philosophy of Logic , vol.66
  • 28
    • 77950039520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These so-called laws of second-order logic are, on the mooted view, really first-order comprehension axioms, in a disguised notation
    • These so-called laws of second-order logic are, on the mooted view, really first-order comprehension axioms, in a disguised notation.
  • 30
    • 77950039965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ZFCU is often formulated with two axiom schemata, Replacement and Separation, but the latter is redundant
    • ZFCU is often formulated with two axiom schemata, Replacement and Separation, but the latter is redundant.
  • 31
    • 77950028722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notice that since we have Urelemente, we cannot follow the practice, customary among set theories, of taking our quantifiers tacitly to be restricted to sets; we require the predicate'Set(x)'
    • Notice that since we have Urelemente, we cannot follow the practice, customary among set theories, of taking our quantifiers tacitly to be restricted to sets; we require the predicate 'Set(x)'.
  • 33
    • 33746850381 scopus 로고
    • On the concept of logical consequence
    • English translation by, 2d ed. Indianapolis: Hackett
    • J. H. Woodger, "On the Concept of Logical Consequence," in Tarski's Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, 2d ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983), 409-20.
    • (1983) Tarski's Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics , pp. 409-420
    • Woodger, J.H.1
  • 34
    • 77950056318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Making no provision for varying the universe of discourse as we go from one model to another, Tarski's paper defines a model for a formula φ (Set, ε) to be a variable assignment for the formula φ (X,Y) that we obtain from φ (Set, ε) by replacing its nonlogical terms with variables of appropriate types. Making no provision for varying the universe of discourse as we go from one model to another, Tarski's paper defines a model for a formula φ (Set, ε) to be a variable assignment for the formula φ (X,Y) that we obtain from φ (Set, ε) by replacing its nonlogical terms with variables of appropriate types. However, as the discussion in John Etchemendy's The Concept of Logical Consequence (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1990) makes abundandy clear, we need to make allowance for varying the universe of discourse, else the notion of "logical consequence" we define will diverge wildly from standard mathematical usage
    • Making no provision for varying the universe of discourse as we go from one model to another, Tarski's paper defines a model for a formula φ (Set, ε) to be a variable assignment for the formula φ (X,Y) that we obtain from φ (Set, ε) by replacing its nonlogical terms with variables of appropriate types. Making no provision for varying the universe of discourse as we go from one model to another, Tarski's paper defines a model for a formula φ (Set, ε) to be a variable assignment for the formula φ (X,Y) that we obtain from φ (Set, ε) by replacing its nonlogical terms with variables of appropriate types. However, as the discussion in John Etchemendy's The Concept of Logical Consequence (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1990) makes abundandy clear, we need to make allowance for varying the universe of discourse, else the notion of "logical consequence" we define will diverge wildly from standard mathematical usage.
  • 35
    • 77950066117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As found, for example, in C. C. Chang and H. J. Keisler, Model Theory, 3d ed. (Amsterdam: North Holland, 1990)
    • As found, for example, in C. C. Chang and H. J. Keisler, Model Theory, 3d ed. (Amsterdam: North Holland, 1990).
  • 36
    • 77950039751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The kinds of nonlogical terms available to us when we use second-order logic are the same as when we use first-order logic: individual constants, signs for functions from individuals to individuals, and predicates designating properties and relations among individuals. Such resources will not suffice to enable us to define truth in a model, for we naturally define truth in a model in terms of satisfaction, and to represent the satisfaction relation for second-order formulas, we require a predicate that has a second-order variable in one of its argument places
    • The kinds of nonlogical terms available to us when we use second-order logic are the same as when we use first-order logic: individual constants, signs for functions from individuals to individuals, and predicates designating properties and relations among individuals. Such resources will not suffice to enable us to define truth in a model, for we naturally define truth in a model in terms of satisfaction, and to represent the satisfaction relation for second-order formulas, we require a predicate that has a second-order variable in one of its argument places.
  • 38
    • 77950049715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2>))
    • 2>)).
  • 39
    • 77950034030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • α: α an ordinal >, only it will be a sequence of proper classes, rather than a sequence of sets. This way of talking is only credible if it isn't taken literally
    • α:: α an ordinal >, only it will be a sequence of proper classes, rather than a sequence of sets. This way of talking is only credible if it isn't taken literally.
  • 40
    • 77950056527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On one way of thinking about classes, there aren't any proper classes; the only classes there are are the sets. This is the point of view that's being developed here. Talk about proper classes is figurative, a vivid way of expressing ideas that can be expressed more precisely either by employing higher-order logic or by metalinguistic ascent. Far be it from me to object to a figure of speech
    • On one way of thinking about classes, there aren't any proper classes; the only classes there are are the sets. This is the point of view that's being developed here. Talk about proper classes is figurative, a vivid way of expressing ideas that can be expressed more precisely either by employing higher-order logic or by metalinguistic ascent. Far be it from me to object to a figure of speech.
  • 41
    • 77950041093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 0 will be a proper class that includes all proper classes. But according to the standard conception of class theory, which requires classes to be well founded, such a thing isn't possible
    • 0 will be a proper class that includes all proper classes. But according to the standard conception of class theory, which requires classes to be well founded, such a thing isn't possible.
  • 42
    • 77950043156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • αs as proper classes, we need to take the Urelemente to be the non-classes, rather than the non-sets. As we shall see below, such an account, which takes the theory of classes, rather than the theory of sets, as its mathematical foundation, still requires a new axiom, in addition to the standard second-order theory of classes, in order to ensure mat the non-classes form a class
    • αs as proper classes, we need to take the Urelemente to be the non-classes, rather than the non-sets. As we shall see below, such an account, which takes the theory of classes, rather than the theory of sets, as its mathematical foundation, still requires a new axiom, in addition to the standard second-order theory of classes, in order to ensure mat the non-classes form a class.
  • 43
    • 77950041526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There will be many intended models, not just one, since the best we can hope for is that our intentions should pick out the preferred models uniquely up to isomorphism
    • There will be many intended models, not just one, since the best we can hope for is that our intentions should pick out the preferred models uniquely up to isomorphism.
  • 44
    • 77950025052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A collection C of pure sets is said to be an initial segment of the pure sets if and only if every member of a member of C is a member of C. It is called a proper initial segment if there are some pure sets that aren't in C
    • A collection C of pure sets is said to be an initial segment of the pure sets if and only if every member of a member of C is a member of C. It is called a proper initial segment if there are some pure sets that aren't in C.
  • 45
    • 77950063593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, there isn't any model < U,S,E > of second-order ZFCU such that there is a one-one function I, taking pure sets to members of S, that meets the following conditions: every member of the range of I satisfies "x is a pure set" in the model, but not everything that satisfies "x is a pure set" in the model is a member of the range of I; if y is in the range of I and Exy, then x is in the range of I; for any pure sets x and y, we have x ε y if and only if EI(x) I(y)
    • That is, there isn't any model < U,S,E > of second-order ZFCU such that there is a one-one function I, taking pure sets to members of S, that meets the following conditions: every member of the range of I satisfies "x is a pure set" in the model, but not everything that satisfies "x is a pure set" in the model is a member of the range of I; if y is in the range of I and Exy, then x is in the range of I; for any pure sets x and y, we have x ε y if and only if EI(x) I(y).
  • 46
    • 0011894114 scopus 로고
    • 2d ed., trans. E. J. Townsend, Chicago: Open Court
    • The Foundations of Geometry, 2d ed., trans. E. J. Townsend (Chicago: Open Court, 1910), 25.
    • (1910) The Foundations of Geometry , pp. 25
  • 47
    • 77950036795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sometimes a specification of a mathematical system is regarded as categorical only if it characterizes the system, uniquely up to isomorphism, by its internal structure. Our axioms are not categorical is this strict sense, since we characterize the pure sets by reference to things that aren't pure sets, namely, the Urelemente. Usage here is not uniform. Hilbert's axioms for geometry are often referred to as "categorical," even though they refer to things outside the given system of points, lines, and planes
    • Sometimes a specification of a mathematical system is regarded as categorical only if it characterizes the system, uniquely up to isomorphism, by its internal structure. Our axioms are not categorical is this strict sense, since we characterize the pure sets by reference to things that aren't pure sets, namely, the Urelemente. Usage here is not uniform. Hilbert's axioms for geometry are often referred to as "categorical," even though they refer to things outside the given system of points, lines, and planes.
  • 48
    • 77950061462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Gödel sentence for the enlarged language, "This sentence is not provable wiuhin the version of PA that permits substituents from the language gotten from the language of arithmetic by adjoining a truth predicate," is not provable within the version of PA that permits substituents from the language gotten from the language of arithmetic by adjoining a truth predicate. But it is provable in the version of PA gotten by allowing substituents from the language gotten from the language of arithmetic by first adjoining a trudi predicate for the language of arithmetic, then adding another truth predicate for the enlarged language. And so on, up the Tarski hierarchy
    • The Gödel sentence for the enlarged language, "This sentence is not provable wiuhin the version of PA that permits substituents from the language gotten from the language of arithmetic by adjoining a truth predicate," is not provable within the version of PA that permits substituents from the language gotten from the language of arithmetic by adjoining a truth predicate. But it is provable in the version of PA gotten by allowing substituents from the language gotten from the language of arithmetic by first adjoining a trudi predicate for the language of arithmetic, then adding another truth predicate for the enlarged language. And so on, up the Tarski hierarchy.
  • 49
    • 0041484427 scopus 로고
    • A mathematical incompleteness in Peano arithmetic
    • ed. Jon Barwise, Amsterdam: North Holland
    • Jeff Paris and Leo Harrington, "A Mathematical Incompleteness in Peano Arithmetic," in Handbook of Mathematical Lope, ed. Jon Barwise (Amsterdam: North Holland, 1977), 1133-42.
    • (1977) Handbook of Mathematical Lope , pp. 1133-1142
    • Paris, J.1    Harrington, L.2
  • 50
    • 77950040864 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The advantages of using schemata as a substitute for universally quantified second-order sentences are discussed by
    • The advantages of using schemata as a substitute for universally quantified second-order sentences are discussed by Shapiro, Foundations without Foundationalism, 246-50.
    • Foundations without Foundationalism , pp. 246-250
    • Shapiro1
  • 51
    • 0002236012 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • Lavine, Understanding the Infinite (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1994), 228-34.
    • (1994) Understanding the Infinite , pp. 228-234
    • Lavine1
  • 52
    • 77950041824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If we describe the force of the rule by saying that every Induction Axiom holds in every logically permissible extension of our language, we commit ourselves, at least prima facie, to the dubious category of logically permissible languages. But we by no means require diis metalinguistic description in order to employ the rule
    • If we describe the force of the rule by saying that every Induction Axiom holds in every logically permissible extension of our language, we commit ourselves, at least prima facie, to the dubious category of logically permissible languages. But we by no means require diis metalinguistic description in order to employ the rule.
  • 53
    • 77950047615 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Talk of the cardinality of the universe is figurative, to be cashed out in terms of second-order quantification
    • Talk of the cardinality of the universe is figurative, to be cashed out in terms of second-order quantification.
  • 54
    • 77950059696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, we take second-order ZFCU + the Urelement Set Axiom as premises and prove the conclusion, as opposed to giving a model-theoretic argument that the conclusion holds in every model of second-order ZFCU + the Urelement Set Axiom
    • That is, we take second-order ZFCU + the Urelement Set Axiom as premises and prove the conclusion, as opposed to giving a model-theoretic argument that the conclusion holds in every model of second-order ZFCU + the Urelement Set Axiom.
  • 55
    • 77950058392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • κ, which is κ.
  • 56
    • 77950033339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cantor's Theorem has both first- and second-order formulations, both theorems of second-order ZFCU. Here we are using the latter
    • Cantor's Theorem has both first- and second-order formulations, both theorems of second-order ZFCU. Here we are using the latter.
  • 57
    • 77950042046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The derivation of the schema mimics the second-order proof. To play the role of H, the one-one function mapping the universe into the pure sets, find a formula γ(g,x,y) such uiat it is provable that, for any g, if g is a bijection from the set of Urelemente onto an ordinal, then the ordered pairs such that γ(g,x,y) describe a one-one map from the entire universe into the pure sets. Then prove, using the Urelement Set Axiom and the Axiom of Choice, that such a bijection g exists
    • The derivation of the schema mimics the second-order proof. To play the role of H, the one-one function mapping the universe into the pure sets, find a formula γ(g,x,y) such uiat it is provable that, for any g, if g is a bijection from the set of Urelemente onto an ordinal, then the ordered pairs such that γ(g,x,y) describe a one-one map from the entire universe into the pure sets. Then prove, using the Urelement Set Axiom and the Axiom of Choice, that such a bijection g exists.
  • 58
    • 77950027387 scopus 로고
    • Fraenkel's Addition to the Axioms of Zermelo, ed. Yehoshua Bar-Hillel, E. I. J. Poznanski, and Abraham Robinson, Jerusalem: Magnes Press
    • "Fraenkel's Addition to the Axioms of Zermelo," in Essays on the Foundations of Mathematics, ed. Yehoshua Bar-Hillel, E. I. J. Poznanski, and Abraham Robinson (Jerusalem: Magnes Press, 1961), 91-114.
    • (1961) Essays on the Foundations of Mathematics , pp. 91-114
  • 59
    • 84972494041 scopus 로고
    • Axiom schemata of strong infinity in axiomatic set theory
    • "Axiom Schemata of Strong Infinity in Axiomatic Set Theory," Pacific Journal of Mathematics 10 (1960): 223-38.
    • (1960) Pacific Journal of Mathematics , vol.10 , pp. 223-238


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.