-
1
-
-
0039163524
-
Plato's line revisited: The pedagogy of complete reflection
-
"Plato's Line Revisited: The Pedagogy of Complete Reflection," The Review of Metaphysics 44 (1991): 525-47. have attempted to fit that into the full context of the Republic in "Image, Structure and Content: A Remark on a Passage in Plato's Republic," The Review of Metaphysics 40 (1987): 495-514.
-
(1991)
The Review of Metaphysics
, vol.44
, pp. 525-547
-
-
-
2
-
-
0039163525
-
Image, structure and content: A remark on a passage in Plato's Republic
-
"Plato's Line Revisited: The Pedagogy of Complete Reflection," The Review of Metaphysics 44 (1991): 525-47. have attempted to fit that into the full context of the Republic in "Image, Structure and Content: A Remark on a Passage in Plato's Republic," The Review of Metaphysics 40 (1987): 495-514.
-
(1987)
The Review of Metaphysics
, vol.40
, pp. 495-514
-
-
-
3
-
-
0003548526
-
-
trans. R. D. Hicks Cambridge: Harvard University Press
-
One could also see how reflexivity works more concretely by attending to the opening of the Republic, which, according to antiquity, Plato reworked many times to get it just right: Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, trans. R. D. Hicks (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1972), 310-311. The very first line, "I went down to the Peireius yesterday," announces the metaphoric theme of going down and going up which structures the whole work precisely because it structures the way we talk about our lives in terms of values. Yet what immediately follows presents a concrete instantiation of the proximate work of the Republic, which is to persuade the citizens that philosophy is no threat to the city but could even be a boon to it. Socrates and Glaucon are about to go "up to the city" when they are arrested by a group which claims the power to hold them from their goal by reason of their greater numbers. Socrates tells them that that in addition to such power, there is also the power to persuade the group to let him and Glaucon do what they originally intended, namely go up to the city. The dialogue leads, through an attempt to persuade the group that philosophy is no threat for the city, to Socrates' leading them in discourse to "a city laid up in heaven," which will never exist on earth but of which each individual can make himself or herself a member by becoming the philosopher-king of his or her own life. It is this self-reflexivity clue that leads us to look at the opening of the Theaetetus in the light of the dialogue taken as a whole. It is the central claim of this paper that in the Theaetetus the self-reflexivity is not merely metaphorical; it is substantive.
-
(1972)
Lives of Eminent Philosophers
, pp. 310-311
-
-
Laertius, D.1
-
7
-
-
11544328039
-
-
See also Sophist 263e.
-
Sophist
-
-
-
9
-
-
0010353918
-
-
with the M. J. Levett translation Indianapolis: Hackett
-
Myles Burneat, The Theaetetus of Plato with the M. J. Levett translation (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1990), 2-3. In Gadamerian terms, we will try to achieve a Horizontverschmelzung. See Truth and Method, trans. Garrett Barden and John Cumming (New York: Crossroads, 1982), 267-74 and 337-34.
-
(1990)
The Theaetetus of Plato
, pp. 2-3
-
-
Burneat, M.1
-
10
-
-
0004225610
-
-
New York: Crossroads
-
Myles Burneat, The Theaetetus of Plato with the M. J. Levett translation (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1990), 2-3. In Gadamerian terms, we will try to achieve a Horizontverschmelzung. See Truth and Method, trans. Garrett Barden and John Cumming (New York: Crossroads, 1982), 267-74 and 337-34.
-
(1982)
Truth and Method
, pp. 267-274
-
-
Barden, G.1
Cumming, J.2
-
11
-
-
0842278175
-
-
Theaetetus 142a. The translations are from H. N. Fowler, Theaetetus and Sophist, Loeb Classics (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977).
-
Theaetetus
-
-
-
12
-
-
0842278175
-
-
Theaetetus 142a. The translations are from H. N. Fowler, Theaetetus and Sophist, Loeb Classics (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977).
-
Theaetetus
-
-
Fowler, H.N.1
-
13
-
-
0040942070
-
-
Loeb Classics Cambridge: Harvard University Press
-
Theaetetus 142a. The translations are from H. N. Fowler, Theaetetus and Sophist, Loeb Classics (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977).
-
(1977)
Sophist
-
-
-
14
-
-
0842278175
-
-
Theaetetus 154d, 143a, 172c, 175e, 187d.
-
Theaetetus
-
-
-
18
-
-
7444245644
-
-
Statesman 269d-274e. The surface level background to the States-man is projected at the beginning of Sophis t as an inquiry into the samenes s and/or difference between the sophist, statesman, and philosopher (Sophist 217a). The deeper level is the inquiry into sameness and difference them-selves playing in relation to motion and rest as encompassed by the notion of being in the Sophist (254a-257b). The latter announces its aim as securing a place for logos among beings (260a), thus continuing the discussion of Theaetetus into logos. The Statesman announces that its aim is not simply to teach how to think about the statesman but how to think about all things (285d). It weaves the hard and soft fibers of apodeixis ("showing from the top down") and paradeigma (a model "showing alongside") respectively. It begins with a paradigm (shepherding, 261c), as does the Sophist (angling, 221b), and comes later to weaving (305e), but the models are set within a top-down framework of the human arts which are set, in turn, within the widest distinction between nature and techne. It proceeds, as does the Sophist, by bifurcatory diairesis, showing relations of sameness and difference. It modifies the paradigm by manipulating and integrating traditional myths which has the effect of setting the divine shepherd at a distance and viewing the statesman as a man among men (268d). It further modifies the diairetic procedure by an articulation of the functions of the city which follows the Phaedrus's advice to "carve along the joints" (265e). It also distinguishes between the universalizing function of law and the particularizing function of prudence in seeking the mean (284e).
-
Statesman
-
-
-
19
-
-
7444245644
-
-
Statesman 269d-274e. The surface level background to the States-man is projected at the beginning of Sophis t as an inquiry into the samenes s and/or difference between the sophist, statesman, and philosopher (Sophist 217a). The deeper level is the inquiry into sameness and difference them-selves playing in relation to motion and rest as encompassed by the notion of being in the Sophist (254a-257b). The latter announces its aim as securing a place for logos among beings (260a), thus continuing the discussion of Theaetetus into logos. The Statesman announces that its aim is not simply to teach how to think about the statesman but how to think about all things (285d). It weaves the hard and soft fibers of apodeixis ("showing from the top down") and paradeigma (a model "showing alongside") respectively. It begins with a paradigm (shepherding, 261c), as does the Sophist (angling, 221b), and comes later to weaving (305e), but the models are set within a top-down framework of the human arts which are set, in turn, within the widest distinction between nature and techne. It proceeds, as does the Sophist, by bifurcatory diairesis, showing relations of sameness and difference. It modifies the paradigm by manipulating and integrating traditional myths which has the effect of setting the divine shepherd at a distance and viewing the statesman as a man among men (268d). It further modifies the diairetic procedure by an articulation of the functions of the city which follows the Phaedrus's advice to "carve along the joints" (265e). It also distinguishes between the universalizing function of law and the particularizing function of prudence in seeking the mean (284e).
-
Statesman
-
-
-
20
-
-
0039163520
-
-
Statesman 269d-274e. The surface level background to the States-man is projected at the beginning of Sophis t as an inquiry into the samenes s and/or difference between the sophist, statesman, and philosopher (Sophist 217a). The deeper level is the inquiry into sameness and difference them-selves playing in relation to motion and rest as encompassed by the notion of being in the Sophist (254a-257b). The latter announces its aim as securing a place for logos among beings (260a), thus continuing the discussion of Theaetetus into logos. The Statesman announces that its aim is not simply to teach how to think about the statesman but how to think about all things (285d). It weaves the hard and soft fibers of apodeixis ("showing from the top down") and paradeigma (a model "showing alongside") respectively. It begins with a paradigm (shepherding, 261c), as does the Sophist (angling, 221b), and comes later to weaving (305e), but the models are set within a top-down framework of the human arts which are set, in turn, within the widest distinction between nature and techne. It proceeds, as does the Sophist, by bifurcatory diairesis, showing relations of sameness and difference. It modifies the paradigm by manipulating and integrating traditional myths which has the effect of setting the divine shepherd at a distance and viewing the statesman as a man among men (268d). It further modifies the diairetic procedure by an articulation of the functions of the city which follows the Phaedrus's advice to "carve along the joints" (265e). It also distinguishes between the universalizing function of law and the particularizing function of prudence in seeking the mean (284e).
-
Sophist
-
-
-
21
-
-
4243862040
-
-
Statesman 269d-274e. The surface level background to the States-man is projected at the beginning of Sophis t as an inquiry into the samenes s and/or difference between the sophist, statesman, and philosopher (Sophist 217a). The deeper level is the inquiry into sameness and difference them-selves playing in relation to motion and rest as encompassed by the notion of being in the Sophist (254a-257b). The latter announces its aim as securing a place for logos among beings (260a), thus continuing the discussion of Theaetetus into logos. The Statesman announces that its aim is not simply to teach how to think about the statesman but how to think about all things (285d). It weaves the hard and soft fibers of apodeixis ("showing from the top down") and paradeigma (a model "showing alongside") respectively. It begins with a paradigm (shepherding, 261c), as does the Sophist (angling, 221b), and comes later to weaving (305e), but the models are set within a top-down framework of the human arts which are set, in turn, within the widest distinction between nature and techne. It proceeds, as does the Sophist, by bifurcatory diairesis, showing relations of sameness and difference. It modifies the paradigm by manipulating and integrating traditional myths which has the effect of setting the divine shepherd at a distance and viewing the statesman as a man among men (268d). It further modifies the diairetic procedure by an articulation of the functions of the city which follows the Phaedrus's advice to "carve along the joints" (265e). It also distinguishes between the universalizing function of law and the particularizing function of prudence in seeking the mean (284e).
-
Sophist
-
-
-
22
-
-
4243853916
-
-
Statesman 269d-274e. The surface level background to the States-man is projected at the beginning of Sophis t as an inquiry into the samenes s and/or difference between the sophist, statesman, and philosopher (Sophist 217a). The deeper level is the inquiry into sameness and difference them-selves playing in relation to motion and rest as encompassed by the notion of being in the Sophist (254a-257b). The latter announces its aim as securing a place for logos among beings (260a), thus continuing the discussion of Theaetetus into logos. The Statesman announces that its aim is not simply to teach how to think about the statesman but how to think about all things (285d). It weaves the hard and soft fibers of apodeixis ("showing from the top down") and paradeigma (a model "showing alongside") respectively. It begins with a paradigm (shepherding, 261c), as does the Sophist (angling, 221b), and comes later to weaving (305e), but the models are set within a top-down framework of the human arts which are set, in turn, within the widest distinction between nature and techne. It proceeds, as does the Sophist, by bifurcatory diairesis, showing relations of sameness and difference. It modifies the paradigm by manipulating and integrating traditional myths which has the effect of setting the divine shepherd at a distance and viewing the statesman as a man among men (268d). It further modifies the diairetic procedure by an articulation of the functions of the city which follows the Phaedrus's advice to "carve along the joints" (265e). It also distinguishes between the universalizing function of law and the particularizing function of prudence in seeking the mean (284e).
-
Sophist
-
-
-
23
-
-
0842278175
-
-
Statesman 269d-274e. The surface level background to the States-man is projected at the beginning of Sophis t as an inquiry into the samenes s and/or difference between the sophist, statesman, and philosopher (Sophist 217a). The deeper level is the inquiry into sameness and difference them-selves playing in relation to motion and rest as encompassed by the notion of being in the Sophist (254a-257b). The latter announces its aim as securing a place for logos among beings (260a), thus continuing the discussion of Theaetetus into logos. The Statesman announces that its aim is not simply to teach how to think about the statesman but how to think about all things (285d). It weaves the hard and soft fibers of apodeixis ("showing from the top down") and paradeigma (a model "showing alongside") respectively. It begins with a paradigm (shepherding, 261c), as does the Sophist (angling, 221b), and comes later to weaving (305e), but the models are set within a top-down framework of the human arts which are set, in turn, within the widest distinction between nature and techne. It proceeds, as does the Sophist, by bifurcatory diairesis, showing relations of sameness and difference. It modifies the paradigm by manipulating and integrating traditional myths which has the effect of setting the divine shepherd at a distance and viewing the statesman as a man among men (268d). It further modifies the diairetic procedure by an articulation of the functions of the city which follows the Phaedrus's advice to "carve along the joints" (265e). It also distinguishes between the universalizing function of law and the particularizing function of prudence in seeking the mean (284e).
-
Theaetetus
-
-
-
24
-
-
7444245644
-
-
Statesman 269d-274e. The surface level background to the States-man is projected at the beginning of Sophis t as an inquiry into the samenes s and/or difference between the sophist, statesman, and philosopher (Sophist 217a). The deeper level is the inquiry into sameness and difference them-selves playing in relation to motion and rest as encompassed by the notion of being in the Sophist (254a-257b). The latter announces its aim as securing a place for logos among beings (260a), thus continuing the discussion of Theaetetus into logos. The Statesman announces that its aim is not simply to teach how to think about the statesman but how to think about all things (285d). It weaves the hard and soft fibers of apodeixis ("showing from the top down") and paradeigma (a model "showing alongside") respectively. It begins with a paradigm (shepherding, 261c), as does the Sophist (angling, 221b), and comes later to weaving (305e), but the models are set within a top-down framework of the human arts which are set, in turn, within the widest distinction between nature and techne. It proceeds, as does the Sophist, by bifurcatory diairesis, showing relations of sameness and difference. It modifies the paradigm by manipulating and integrating traditional myths which has the effect of setting the divine shepherd at a distance and viewing the statesman as a man among men (268d). It further modifies the diairetic procedure by an articulation of the functions of the city which follows the Phaedrus's advice to "carve along the joints" (265e). It also distinguishes between the universalizing function of law and the particularizing function of prudence in seeking the mean (284e).
-
Statesman
-
-
-
25
-
-
4243324220
-
-
Statesman 269d-274e. The surface level background to the States-man is projected at the beginning of Sophis t as an inquiry into the samenes s and/or difference between the sophist, statesman, and philosopher (Sophist 217a). The deeper level is the inquiry into sameness and difference them-selves playing in relation to motion and rest as encompassed by the notion of being in the Sophist (254a-257b). The latter announces its aim as securing a place for logos among beings (260a), thus continuing the discussion of Theaetetus into logos. The Statesman announces that its aim is not simply to teach how to think about the statesman but how to think about all things (285d). It weaves the hard and soft fibers of apodeixis ("showing from the top down") and paradeigma (a model "showing alongside") respectively. It begins with a paradigm (shepherding, 261c), as does the Sophist (angling, 221b), and comes later to weaving (305e), but the models are set within a top-down framework of the human arts which are set, in turn, within the widest distinction between nature and techne. It proceeds, as does the Sophist, by bifurcatory diairesis, showing relations of sameness and difference. It modifies the paradigm by manipulating and integrating traditional myths which has the effect of setting the divine shepherd at a distance and viewing the statesman as a man among men (268d). It further modifies the diairetic procedure by an articulation of the functions of the city which follows the Phaedrus's advice to "carve along the joints" (265e). It also distinguishes between the universalizing function of law and the particularizing function of prudence in seeking the mean (284e).
-
Sophist
-
-
-
26
-
-
25044462609
-
-
Statesman 269d-274e. The surface level background to the States-man is projected at the beginning of Sophis t as an inquiry into the samenes s and/or difference between the sophist, statesman, and philosopher (Sophist 217a). The deeper level is the inquiry into sameness and difference them-selves playing in relation to motion and rest as encompassed by the notion of being in the Sophist (254a-257b). The latter announces its aim as securing a place for logos among beings (260a), thus continuing the discussion of Theaetetus into logos. The Statesman announces that its aim is not simply to teach how to think about the statesman but how to think about all things (285d). It weaves the hard and soft fibers of apodeixis ("showing from the top down") and paradeigma (a model "showing alongside") respectively. It begins with a paradigm (shepherding, 261c), as does the Sophist (angling, 221b), and comes later to weaving (305e), but the models are set within a top-down framework of the human arts which are set, in turn, within the widest distinction between nature and techne. It proceeds, as does the Sophist, by bifurcatory diairesis, showing relations of sameness and difference. It modifies the paradigm by manipulating and integrating traditional myths which has the effect of setting the divine shepherd at a distance and viewing the statesman as a man among men (268d). It further modifies the diairetic procedure by an articulation of the functions of the city which follows the Phaedrus's advice to "carve along the joints" (265e). It also distinguishes between the universalizing function of law and the particularizing function of prudence in seeking the mean (284e).
-
Sophist
-
-
-
27
-
-
84886987932
-
-
Statesman 269d-274e. The surface level background to the States-man is projected at the beginning of Sophis t as an inquiry into the samenes s and/or difference between the sophist, statesman, and philosopher (Sophist 217a). The deeper level is the inquiry into sameness and difference them-selves playing in relation to motion and rest as encompassed by the notion of being in the Sophist (254a-257b). The latter announces its aim as securing a place for logos among beings (260a), thus continuing the discussion of Theaetetus into logos. The Statesman announces that its aim is not simply to teach how to think about the statesman but how to think about all things (285d). It weaves the hard and soft fibers of apodeixis ("showing from the top down") and paradeigma (a model "showing alongside") respectively. It begins with a paradigm (shepherding, 261c), as does the Sophist (angling, 221b), and comes later to weaving (305e), but the models are set within a top-down framework of the human arts which are set, in turn, within the widest distinction between nature and techne. It proceeds, as does the Sophist, by bifurcatory diairesis, showing relations of sameness and difference. It modifies the paradigm by manipulating and integrating traditional myths which has the effect of setting the divine shepherd at a distance and viewing the statesman as a man among men (268d). It further modifies the diairetic procedure by an articulation of the functions of the city which follows the Phaedrus's advice to "carve along the joints" (265e). It also distinguishes between the universalizing function of law and the particularizing function of prudence in seeking the mean (284e).
-
Phaedrus
-
-
-
28
-
-
78751642821
-
-
1.10.1100a10-1100b10
-
Nicomachean Ethics 1.10.1100a10-1100b10.
-
Nicomachean Ethics
-
-
-
29
-
-
25044432605
-
-
Phaedo 64a.
-
Phaedo
-
-
-
31
-
-
25044457976
-
-
This is the sole reference in antiquity to Socrates' engagement in writing, outside of the belated attempt in the Phaedo at writing a hymn to Apollo and turning Aesop's fables into verse, following the command in a dream to compose poetry (Phaedo 60d-61b).
-
Phaedo
-
-
-
46
-
-
0842278175
-
-
Theaetetus 160a. To my knowledge, this is the first instance of the notion of intentionality in the history of thought.
-
Theaetetus
-
-
-
50
-
-
0842278175
-
-
Theaetetus 185e. I am utterly amazed at the claim some scholars make that the Theaetetus does not consider the εδη. They appear again and again throughout the dialogue, although, it must be admitted, they are not consid-ered in the three theses focally but only in passing.
-
Theaetetus
-
-
-
51
-
-
0004241822
-
-
New York: Harper
-
The expression is Whitehead's: Process and Reality (New York: Harper, 1960), 44-7.
-
(1960)
Process and Reality
, pp. 44-47
-
-
Whitehead1
-
52
-
-
84886987932
-
-
Phaedrus 274c-277a. See Derrida's comments in his "Plato's Pharmakon," in Dissemination, trans. Barbara Johnson (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981), 61-171. We should also look to the Herculean memory feats of Cephalus, Antiphon, and Polydorus in the Parmenides where the immensely complex account of the dialectical turnings between the one and the many (others) have been committed to memory without, at least in the case of Antiphon, sustaining their interest in the issues involved. Antiphon, after all, turned from such memory feats to raising horses!
-
Phaedrus
-
-
-
53
-
-
0003244798
-
Plato's Pharmakon
-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
Phaedrus 274c-277a. See Derrida's comments in his "Plato's Pharmakon," in Dissemination, trans. Barbara Johnson (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981), 61-171. We should also look to the Herculean memory feats of Cephalus, Antiphon, and Polydorus in the Parmenides where the immensely complex account of the dialectical turnings between the one and the many (others) have been committed to memory without, at least in the case of Antiphon, sustaining their interest in the issues involved. Antiphon, after all, turned from such memory feats to raising horses!
-
(1981)
Dissemination
, pp. 61-171
-
-
Johnson, B.1
-
54
-
-
34548845918
-
The model of the text: Meaningful action considered as a text
-
On the comparison of writing to speech, see Paul Ricoeur, "The Model of the Text: Meaningful Action Considered as a Text," Social Research 38 (1971): 530-7.
-
(1971)
Social Research
, vol.38
, pp. 530-537
-
-
Ricoeur, P.1
-
56
-
-
0006323183
-
The origin of the work of art
-
trans. Albert Hofstadter New York: Harper and Row
-
Heidegger notes, in "The Origin of the Work of Art," that we have to "listen away" from our actual experience to hear sounds. What we hear are voices in the next room, the airplane overhead, the car going by outside, etc.: Poetry, Language, and Thought, trans. Albert Hofstadter (New York: Harper and Row, 1971), 26.
-
(1971)
Poetry, Language, and Thought
, pp. 26
-
-
Heidegger1
-
58
-
-
4243853914
-
-
Sophist 254d. In the Theatetus for 'being' see 186; for sameness and difference, 185a; for motion and rest, 180e-182e.
-
Sophist
-
-
-
59
-
-
0039163483
-
-
for sameness and difference, 185a; for motion and rest, 180e-182e
-
Sophist 254d. In the Theatetus for 'being' see 186; for sameness and difference, 185a; for motion and rest, 180e-182e.
-
Theatetus
, pp. 186
-
-
-
63
-
-
0039771254
-
-
20.1456b-1457a
-
See Aristotle's treatment in his Poetics 20.1456b-1457a.
-
Poetics
-
-
Aristotle1
-
70
-
-
0040348022
-
Knowledge and logos in the Theaetetus
-
See Gail Fine, "Knowledge and Logos in the Theaetetus," Philosophical Review 88 (1979): 391-2. For a more ample treatment, see Rosemary Desjardins, The Rational Enterprise: Logos in Plato's Theaetetus (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1990).
-
(1979)
Philosophical Review
, vol.88
, pp. 391-392
-
-
Fine, G.1
-
71
-
-
0010307097
-
-
Albany: State University of New York Press
-
See Gail Fine, "Knowledge and Logos in the Theaetetus," Philosophical Review 88 (1979): 391-2. For a more ample treatment, see Rosemary Desjardins, The Rational Enterprise: Logos in Plato's Theaetetus (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1990).
-
(1990)
The Rational Enterprise: Logos in Plato's Theaetetus
-
-
Desjardins, R.1
-
74
-
-
0842278175
-
-
Theaetetus 146c, 171e, and 178b.
-
Theaetetus
-
-
-
83
-
-
0004158981
-
-
1.2.982b13
-
Metaphysics 1.2.982b13.
-
Metaphysics
-
-
-
84
-
-
0043060717
-
-
New York: Twayne
-
I owe this reading to Heidegger, What Is Philosophy?, trans. William Klubak and Jean T. Wilde (New York: Twayne, 1958), 78-85. Heidegger says elsewhere that in great philosophy and poetry so much "world-space" is created that even the ordinary appears extraordinary: Introduction to Metaphysics, trans. Ralph Manheim (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1959), 26.
-
(1958)
What Is Philosophy?
, pp. 78-85
-
-
Klubak, W.1
Wilde, J.T.2
-
85
-
-
0004236266
-
-
New Haven: Yale University Press
-
I owe this reading to Heidegger, What Is Philosophy?, trans. William Klubak and Jean T. Wilde (New York: Twayne, 1958), 78-85. Heidegger says elsewhere that in great philosophy and poetry so much "world-space" is created that even the ordinary appears extraordinary: Introduction to Metaphysics, trans. Ralph Manheim (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1959), 26.
-
(1959)
Introduction to Metaphysics
, pp. 26
-
-
Manheim, R.1
-
86
-
-
0842278175
-
-
London: Penguin
-
See, for example, Robin Waterfield, commentary appended to his translation of Plato's Theaetetus (London: Penguin, 1987), 177. In his commentary appended to M. J. Levett's translation of Theaetetus, 34-5, Burnyeat gives a short history of response to this "digression."
-
(1987)
Theaetetus
, pp. 177
-
-
Waterfield, R.1
-
87
-
-
0842278175
-
-
Burnyeat gives a short history of response to this "digression."
-
See, for example, Robin Waterfield, commentary appended to his translation of Plato's Theaetetus (London: Penguin, 1987), 177. In his commentary appended to M. J. Levett's translation of Theaetetus, 34-5, Burnyeat gives a short history of response to this "digression."
-
Theaetetus
, pp. 34-35
-
-
Levett, M.J.1
-
91
-
-
0040941992
-
Parmenides
-
Parmenides, in Kirk and Raven, Presocratic Philosophers, 269 n. 344. The editors render it: "the same thing can be thought as can be."
-
Presocratic Philosophers
, vol.269
, Issue.344
-
-
Kirk1
Raven2
-
93
-
-
84871294606
-
-
See Republic 4.436b.
-
Republic
-
-
-
101
-
-
84871294606
-
-
Republic 5.476.
-
Republic
, pp. 5476
-
-
-
103
-
-
7444245644
-
-
Statesman 287e-289a, 303d-305d.
-
Statesman
-
-
|