-
1
-
-
0040228936
-
-
159 F.2d 169 (2d Cir. 1947)
-
159 F.2d 169 (2d Cir. 1947).
-
-
-
-
2
-
-
0039637012
-
-
Id. at 173
-
Id. at 173.
-
-
-
-
3
-
-
0000241518
-
Toward an economic theory of liability
-
This is a large literature and we can only touch upon it here. In his pathbreaking article, "Toward an Economic Theory of Liability," 2 Journal of Legal Studies 323 (1973), John Brown introduced the first formal economic model of torts. Brown and most of his followers assumed risk-neutral and homogeneous agents. Steven Shavell, in "Strict Liability versus Negligence," 9 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1980), and A. Mitchell Polinsky, in "Strict Liability vs. Negligence in a Market Setting," 70 American Economic Review 363 (1980), extended Brown's analysis to consider the ramifications of parties having differential knowledge of risk (i.e., likelihood of accident) and firm entry and exit, respectively. David Haddock and Christopher Curran, in "An Economic Theory of Comparative Negligence," 14 Journal of Legal Studies 49 (1985), used Brown's framework to analyze two broad categories of comparative negligence: pure comparative negligence and a 50% threshold rule. Samuel A. Rea, Jr., in "The Economics of Comparative Negligence," 7 International Review of Law and Economics 149 (1987), extended Haddock and Curran's analysis to consider when parties took action sequentially, rather than simultaneously. Winand Emons, in "Efficient Liability Rules for an Economy with Non-Identical Individuals," 42 Journal of Public Economics 89 (1990), analyzed the implications of heterogeneous individuals within the Brown model. Finally, Lynda Thoman, in "Strict Liability and Negligence Rules when the Product is Information," 44 Economics Letters 205 (1994), analyzed the implications of the model in a principal-agent framework.
-
(1973)
Journal of Legal Studies
, vol.2
, pp. 323
-
-
-
4
-
-
0002775690
-
Strict liability versus negligence
-
This is a large literature and we can only touch upon it here. In his pathbreaking article, "Toward an Economic Theory of Liability," 2 Journal of Legal Studies 323 (1973), John Brown introduced the first formal economic model of torts. Brown and most of his followers assumed risk-neutral and homogeneous agents. Steven Shavell, in "Strict Liability versus Negligence," 9 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1980), and A. Mitchell Polinsky, in "Strict Liability vs. Negligence in a Market Setting," 70 American Economic Review 363 (1980), extended Brown's analysis to consider the ramifications of parties having differential knowledge of risk (i.e., likelihood of accident) and firm entry and exit, respectively. David Haddock and Christopher Curran, in "An Economic Theory of Comparative Negligence," 14 Journal of Legal Studies 49 (1985), used Brown's framework to analyze two broad categories of comparative negligence: pure comparative negligence and a 50% threshold rule. Samuel A. Rea, Jr., in "The Economics of Comparative Negligence," 7 International Review of Law and Economics 149 (1987), extended Haddock and Curran's analysis to consider when parties took action sequentially, rather than simultaneously. Winand Emons, in "Efficient Liability Rules for an Economy with Non-Identical Individuals," 42 Journal of Public Economics 89 (1990), analyzed the implications of heterogeneous individuals within the Brown model. Finally, Lynda Thoman, in "Strict Liability and Negligence Rules when the Product is Information," 44 Economics Letters 205 (1994), analyzed the implications of the model in a principal-agent framework.
-
(1980)
Journal of Legal Studies
, vol.9
, pp. 1
-
-
Shavell, S.1
-
5
-
-
0000345134
-
Strict liability vs. Negligence in a market setting
-
This is a large literature and we can only touch upon it here. In his pathbreaking article, "Toward an Economic Theory of Liability," 2 Journal of Legal Studies 323 (1973), John Brown introduced the first formal economic model of torts. Brown and most of his followers assumed risk-neutral and homogeneous agents. Steven Shavell, in "Strict Liability versus Negligence," 9 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1980), and A. Mitchell Polinsky, in "Strict Liability vs. Negligence in a Market Setting," 70 American Economic Review 363 (1980), extended Brown's analysis to consider the ramifications of parties having differential knowledge of risk (i.e., likelihood of accident) and firm entry and exit, respectively. David Haddock and Christopher Curran, in "An Economic Theory of Comparative Negligence," 14 Journal of Legal Studies 49 (1985), used Brown's framework to analyze two broad categories of comparative negligence: pure comparative negligence and a 50% threshold rule. Samuel A. Rea, Jr., in "The Economics of Comparative Negligence," 7 International Review of Law and Economics 149 (1987), extended Haddock and Curran's analysis to consider when parties took action sequentially, rather than simultaneously. Winand Emons, in "Efficient Liability Rules for an Economy with Non-Identical Individuals," 42 Journal of Public Economics 89 (1990), analyzed the implications of heterogeneous individuals within the Brown model. Finally, Lynda Thoman, in "Strict Liability and Negligence Rules when the Product is Information," 44 Economics Letters 205 (1994), analyzed the implications of the model in a principal-agent framework.
-
(1980)
American Economic Review
, vol.70
, pp. 363
-
-
Polinsky, A.M.1
-
6
-
-
0040823607
-
An economic theory of comparative negligence
-
This is a large literature and we can only touch upon it here. In his pathbreaking article, "Toward an Economic Theory of Liability," 2 Journal of Legal Studies 323 (1973), John Brown introduced the first formal economic model of torts. Brown and most of his followers assumed risk-neutral and homogeneous agents. Steven Shavell, in "Strict Liability versus Negligence," 9 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1980), and A. Mitchell Polinsky, in "Strict Liability vs. Negligence in a Market Setting," 70 American Economic Review 363 (1980), extended Brown's analysis to consider the ramifications of parties having differential knowledge of risk (i.e., likelihood of accident) and firm entry and exit, respectively. David Haddock and Christopher Curran, in "An Economic Theory of Comparative Negligence," 14 Journal of Legal Studies 49 (1985), used Brown's framework to analyze two broad categories of comparative negligence: pure comparative negligence and a 50% threshold rule. Samuel A. Rea, Jr., in "The Economics of Comparative Negligence," 7 International Review of Law and Economics 149 (1987), extended Haddock and Curran's analysis to consider when parties took action sequentially, rather than simultaneously. Winand Emons, in "Efficient Liability Rules for an Economy with Non-Identical Individuals," 42 Journal of Public Economics 89 (1990), analyzed the implications of heterogeneous individuals within the Brown model. Finally, Lynda Thoman, in "Strict Liability and Negligence Rules when the Product is Information," 44 Economics Letters 205 (1994), analyzed the implications of the model in a principal-agent framework.
-
(1985)
Journal of Legal Studies
, vol.14
, pp. 49
-
-
Haddock, D.1
Curran, C.2
-
7
-
-
0007291462
-
The economics of comparative negligence
-
This is a large literature and we can only touch upon it here. In his pathbreaking article, "Toward an Economic Theory of Liability," 2 Journal of Legal Studies 323 (1973), John Brown introduced the first formal economic model of torts. Brown and most of his followers assumed risk-neutral and homogeneous agents. Steven Shavell, in "Strict Liability versus Negligence," 9 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1980), and A. Mitchell Polinsky, in "Strict Liability vs. Negligence in a Market Setting," 70 American Economic Review 363 (1980), extended Brown's analysis to consider the ramifications of parties having differential knowledge of risk (i.e., likelihood of accident) and firm entry and exit, respectively. David Haddock and Christopher Curran, in "An Economic Theory of Comparative Negligence," 14 Journal of Legal Studies 49 (1985), used Brown's framework to analyze two broad categories of comparative negligence: pure comparative negligence and a 50% threshold rule. Samuel A. Rea, Jr., in "The Economics of Comparative Negligence," 7 International Review of Law and Economics 149 (1987), extended Haddock and Curran's analysis to consider when parties took action sequentially, rather than simultaneously. Winand Emons, in "Efficient Liability Rules for an Economy with Non-Identical Individuals," 42 Journal of Public Economics 89 (1990), analyzed the implications of heterogeneous individuals within the Brown model. Finally, Lynda Thoman, in "Strict Liability and Negligence Rules when the Product is Information," 44 Economics Letters 205 (1994), analyzed the implications of the model in a principal-agent framework.
-
(1987)
International Review of Law and Economics
, vol.7
, pp. 149
-
-
Rea S.A., Jr.1
-
8
-
-
38249019958
-
Efficient liability rules for an economy with non-identical individuals
-
This is a large literature and we can only touch upon it here. In his pathbreaking article, "Toward an Economic Theory of Liability," 2 Journal of Legal Studies 323 (1973), John Brown introduced the first formal economic model of torts. Brown and most of his followers assumed risk-neutral and homogeneous agents. Steven Shavell, in "Strict Liability versus Negligence," 9 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1980), and A. Mitchell Polinsky, in "Strict Liability vs. Negligence in a Market Setting," 70 American Economic Review 363 (1980), extended Brown's analysis to consider the ramifications of parties having differential knowledge of risk (i.e., likelihood of accident) and firm entry and exit, respectively. David Haddock and Christopher Curran, in "An Economic Theory of Comparative Negligence," 14 Journal of Legal Studies 49 (1985), used Brown's framework to analyze two broad categories of comparative negligence: pure comparative negligence and a 50% threshold rule. Samuel A. Rea, Jr., in "The Economics of Comparative Negligence," 7 International Review of Law and Economics 149 (1987), extended Haddock and Curran's analysis to consider when parties took action sequentially, rather than simultaneously. Winand Emons, in "Efficient Liability Rules for an Economy with Non-Identical Individuals," 42 Journal of Public Economics 89 (1990), analyzed the implications of heterogeneous individuals within the Brown model. Finally, Lynda Thoman, in "Strict Liability and Negligence Rules when the Product is Information," 44 Economics Letters 205 (1994), analyzed the implications of the model in a principal-agent framework.
-
(1990)
Journal of Public Economics
, vol.42
, pp. 89
-
-
Emons, W.1
-
9
-
-
38149143501
-
Strict liability and negligence rules when the product is information
-
This is a large literature and we can only touch upon it here. In his pathbreaking article, "Toward an Economic Theory of Liability," 2 Journal of Legal Studies 323 (1973), John Brown introduced the first formal economic model of torts. Brown and most of his followers assumed risk-neutral and homogeneous agents. Steven Shavell, in "Strict Liability versus Negligence," 9 Journal of Legal Studies 1 (1980), and A. Mitchell Polinsky, in "Strict Liability vs. Negligence in a Market Setting," 70 American Economic Review 363 (1980), extended Brown's analysis to consider the ramifications of parties having differential knowledge of risk (i.e., likelihood of accident) and firm entry and exit, respectively. David Haddock and Christopher Curran, in "An Economic Theory of Comparative Negligence," 14 Journal of Legal Studies 49 (1985), used Brown's framework to analyze two broad categories of comparative negligence: pure comparative negligence and a 50% threshold rule. Samuel A. Rea, Jr., in "The Economics of Comparative Negligence," 7 International Review of Law and Economics 149 (1987), extended Haddock and Curran's analysis to consider when parties took action sequentially, rather than simultaneously. Winand Emons, in "Efficient Liability Rules for an Economy with Non-Identical Individuals," 42 Journal of Public Economics 89 (1990), analyzed the implications of heterogeneous individuals within the Brown model. Finally, Lynda Thoman, in "Strict Liability and Negligence Rules when the Product is Information," 44 Economics Letters 205 (1994), analyzed the implications of the model in a principal-agent framework.
-
(1994)
Economics Letters
, vol.44
, pp. 205
-
-
Thoman, L.1
-
10
-
-
0040228934
-
-
note
-
In particular, is it a game-theoretic or Nash equilibrium? That is, does each party maximize his welfare, given the liability rule in force and the behavior of the other party?
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
0039044985
-
-
In the Mathematical Appendix we allow for multiple defendants
-
In the Mathematical Appendix we allow for multiple defendants.
-
-
-
-
13
-
-
0039044971
-
Legal evolution and precedent
-
who argues that the dichotomous nature of liability may be key to understanding how common-law rules develop
-
See also Mark F. Grady, "Legal Evolution and Precedent," 3 Annual Review of Law & Ethics 147 (1995), who argues that the dichotomous nature of liability may be key to understanding how common-law rules develop.
-
(1995)
Annual Review of Law & Ethics
, vol.3
, pp. 147
-
-
Grady, M.F.1
-
14
-
-
0001195671
-
Toward a test for strict liability in torts
-
Guido Calabresi and Jon T. Hirschoff, "Toward a Test for Strict Liability in Torts," 81 Yale Law Journal 1055, 1059 (1972).
-
(1972)
Yale Law Journal
, vol.81
, pp. 1055
-
-
Calabresi, G.1
Hirschoff, J.T.2
-
15
-
-
0039637010
-
-
The reverse Hand rule of Table 1 corresponds to Brown's rule of strict liability with contributory negligence. See supra note 3, p. 328
-
The reverse Hand rule of Table 1 corresponds to Brown's rule of strict liability with contributory negligence. See supra note 3, p. 328.
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
0002071502
-
The problem of social cost
-
Note that we exclude side payments between the plaintiff and the defendant, which would guarantee efficiency regardless of the liability rule. The classic statement of this result appears in R. H. Coase, "The Problem of Social Cost," 3 Journal of Law and Economics 1 (1960).
-
(1960)
Journal of Law and Economics
, vol.3
, pp. 1
-
-
Coase, R.H.1
-
17
-
-
0040823608
-
-
All the outcomes shown in Table 2 are Nash equilibria. See supra note 4 and Proposition 1 in the Mathematical Appendix
-
All the outcomes shown in Table 2 are Nash equilibria. See supra note 4 and Proposition 1 in the Mathematical Appendix.
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
0039044980
-
-
note
-
D = $30, should find negligence on the part of the defendant when he spends $0.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
0040228929
-
-
Once again this contrasts with the results of the continuous cost-of-precaution models. But cf. supra note 12
-
Once again this contrasts with the results of the continuous cost-of-precaution models. But cf. supra note 12.
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
0040228935
-
-
Supra note 8, p. 1058
-
Supra note 8, p. 1058.
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
0039637011
-
-
20 Ill. 478 (1858)
-
20 Ill. 478 (1858).
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
0003438895
-
-
W. Page Keeton, Dan B. Dobbs, Robert E. Keeton, and David G. Owen, Prosser and Keeton on the Law of Torts, 5th ed., p. 470 (1984).
-
(1984)
Prosser and Keeton on the Law of Torts, 5th Ed.
, pp. 470
-
-
Keeton, W.P.1
Dobbs, D.B.2
Keeton, R.E.3
Owen, D.G.4
-
23
-
-
0039044983
-
-
Id.
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
0040228931
-
-
Id.
-
Id.
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
0040823609
-
-
note
-
p, and therefore under the reverse Hand rule plaintiff bears the burden.
-
-
-
-
26
-
-
0039044984
-
-
Brown, supra note 3, pp. 328-329, emphasized this symmetry
-
Brown, supra note 3, pp. 328-329, emphasized this symmetry.
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
0000208815
-
Four tests for liability in torts
-
In practice, what is commonly called strict liability is usually some offshoot of negligence, and it rarely means liability on the part of the injurer in every possible case. In fact, the rules we discuss in Section III are called strict liability rules by Guido Calabresi and Alvin Klevorick in "Four Tests for Liability in Torts," 14 Journal of Legal Studies 585 (1985), although we do not refer to them as such. Stephen G. Gilles, in "Negligence, Strict Liability, and the Cheapest Cost-Avoider," 78 Virginia Law Review 1291, 1293 (1992), notes that what we call strict liability is "tantamount to absolute liability," and that it is "inefficient, except in unusual cases." Table 2 illustrates exactly when strict liability is efficient, when it is inefficient, and why.
-
(1985)
Journal of Legal Studies
, vol.14
, pp. 585
-
-
Calabresi, G.1
Klevorick, A.2
-
28
-
-
21144478992
-
Negligence, strict liability, and the cheapest cost-avoider
-
notes that what we call strict liability is "tantamount to absolute liability," and that it is "inefficient, except in unusual cases." Table 2 illustrates exactly when strict liability is efficient, when it is inefficient, and why
-
In practice, what is commonly called strict liability is usually some offshoot of negligence, and it rarely means liability on the part of the injurer in every possible case. In fact, the rules we discuss in Section III are called strict liability rules by Guido Calabresi and Alvin Klevorick in "Four Tests for Liability in Torts," 14 Journal of Legal Studies 585 (1985), although we do not refer to them as such. Stephen G. Gilles, in "Negligence, Strict Liability, and the Cheapest Cost-Avoider," 78 Virginia Law Review 1291, 1293 (1992), notes that what we call strict liability is "tantamount to absolute liability," and that it is "inefficient, except in unusual cases." Table 2 illustrates exactly when strict liability is efficient, when it is inefficient, and why.
-
(1992)
Virginia Law Review
, vol.78
, pp. 1291
-
-
Gilles, S.G.1
-
29
-
-
0040228930
-
-
See Calabresi and Klevorick, supra note 21
-
See Calabresi and Klevorick, supra note 21.
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
0039044978
-
-
Id. at 591
-
Id. at 591.
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
50849151677
-
The judgment proof problem
-
for an analysis of this problem
-
See Steven Shavell, "The Judgment Proof Problem," 6 International Review of Law and Economics 45 (1986), for an analysis of this problem.
-
(1986)
International Review of Law and Economics
, vol.6
, pp. 45
-
-
Shavell, S.1
-
32
-
-
0039044986
-
-
Brown, supra note 3, p. 329
-
Brown, supra note 3, p. 329.
-
-
-
-
33
-
-
0040823605
-
-
For an analysis of other comparative negligence rules, see the Mathematical Appendix
-
For an analysis of other comparative negligence rules, see the Mathematical Appendix.
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
0003109360
-
Untaken precautions
-
observed that rather than perform complicated cost-benefit calculations on a continuum of potential actions, judges identify a limited number of specific precautionary actions that the parties could have taken and then apply the Hand formula to determine liability. He emphasized, id. p. 139, that "[t]he key question the courts ask is what particular precautions the [plaintiff or] defendant could have taken but did not."
-
Mark F. Grady, in "Untaken Precautions," 18 Journal of Legal Studies 139 (1989), observed that rather than perform complicated cost-benefit calculations on a continuum of potential actions, judges identify a limited number of specific precautionary actions that the parties could have taken and then apply the Hand formula to determine liability. He emphasized, id. p. 139, that "[t]he key question the courts ask is what particular precautions the [plaintiff or] defendant could have taken but did not."
-
(1989)
Journal of Legal Studies
, vol.18
, pp. 139
-
-
Grady, M.F.1
-
35
-
-
0039044987
-
-
But cf. supra note 12
-
But cf. supra note 12.
-
-
-
-
36
-
-
0039044976
-
-
The Mathematical Appendix deals with some of these complications
-
The Mathematical Appendix deals with some of these complications.
-
-
-
-
37
-
-
0039044977
-
-
Note that ℓ corresponds to πL in the text. We drop the redundant notation here
-
Note that ℓ corresponds to πL in the text. We drop the redundant notation here.
-
-
-
-
38
-
-
0040228933
-
-
note
-
j = 0 for all j ≠ i. In general, - i means all j ≠ i. 32 This is the rule of relative negligence referred to in Section III.
-
-
-
-
39
-
-
0039637009
-
-
Contrast this result with the models of Rea, and Haddock and Curran, supra note 3, where precaution is a continuous variable for both the plaintiff and the defendant, and any arbitrary assignment of comparative liability leads to the efficient amount of care
-
Contrast this result with the models of Rea, and Haddock and Curran, supra note 3, where precaution is a continuous variable for both the plaintiff and the defendant, and any arbitrary assignment of comparative liability leads to the efficient amount of care.
-
-
-
|