메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 31, Issue 2, 1997, Pages 195-212

Emotions and morality

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0008653268     PISSN: 00225363     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1023/A:1004236823330     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (18)

References (55)
  • 2
    • 0010780633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Typical emotions
    • W. O'Donohue and R. Kitchener (eds.), London: Sage
    • A. Ben-Ze'ev, "Typical emotions," in W. O'Donohue and R. Kitchener (eds.), Philosophy ofpyschology (London: Sage, 1996), pp. 228-243.
    • (1996) Philosophy Ofpyschology , pp. 228-243
    • Ben-Ze'ev, A.1
  • 6
    • 0043067378 scopus 로고
    • Emotion and feeling
    • P. Edwards (ed.), New York: Macmillan
    • See also W.P. Alston, "Emotion and feeling," in P. Edwards (ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy (New York: Macmillan, 1967), Vol. II, pp. 479-486; E. Bedford, Emotions. Proceedings of the Artistotelian Society, 57 (1957), pp. 281-304; W. Lyons, Emotion (Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1980), pp. 6-8; and G. Pitcher, "Emotion," Mind, 74 (1965), pp. 326-345. Kant, who refers to emotions as simple feelings for which we are not responsible, indeed considers them to be irrelevant or even obstacles to responsible moral behavior. For criticism of Kant's view, see P. Lauritzen, "Errors of an ill-reasoning reason: The disparagement of emotions in the moral life," The Journal of Value Inquiry, 25 (1991), 5-21. Various places in Kant's writings may suggest that his view on the role of emotions in morality is more complex than a simple rejection of such a role; see N. Sherman, "The place of emotions in Kantian morality," in O. Flanagan and A.O. Rorty (eds.), Identity, character, and morality (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1990).
    • (1967) Encyclopedia of Philosophy , vol.2 , pp. 479-486
    • Alston, W.P.1
  • 7
    • 0010770818 scopus 로고
    • See also W.P. Alston, "Emotion and feeling," in P. Edwards (ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy (New York: Macmillan, 1967), Vol. II, pp. 479-486; E. Bedford, Emotions. Proceedings of the Artistotelian Society, 57 (1957), pp. 281-304; W. Lyons, Emotion (Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1980), pp. 6-8; and G. Pitcher, "Emotion," Mind, 74 (1965), pp. 326-345. Kant, who refers to emotions as simple feelings for which we are not responsible, indeed considers them to be irrelevant or even obstacles to responsible moral behavior. For criticism of Kant's view, see P. Lauritzen, "Errors of an ill-reasoning reason: The disparagement of emotions in the moral life," The Journal of Value Inquiry, 25 (1991), 5-21. Various places in Kant's writings may suggest that his view on the role of emotions in morality is more complex than a simple rejection of such a role; see N. Sherman, "The place of emotions in Kantian morality," in O. Flanagan and A.O. Rorty (eds.), Identity, character, and morality (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1990).
    • (1957) Emotions. Proceedings of the Artistotelian Society , vol.57 , pp. 281-304
    • Bedford, E.1
  • 8
    • 0003920273 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press
    • See also W.P. Alston, "Emotion and feeling," in P. Edwards (ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy (New York: Macmillan, 1967), Vol. II, pp. 479-486; E. Bedford, Emotions. Proceedings of the Artistotelian Society, 57 (1957), pp. 281-304; W. Lyons, Emotion (Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1980), pp. 6-8; and G. Pitcher, "Emotion," Mind, 74 (1965), pp. 326-345. Kant, who refers to emotions as simple feelings for which we are not responsible, indeed considers them to be irrelevant or even obstacles to responsible moral behavior. For criticism of Kant's view, see P. Lauritzen, "Errors of an ill-reasoning reason: The disparagement of emotions in the moral life," The Journal of Value Inquiry, 25 (1991), 5-21. Various places in Kant's writings may suggest that his view on the role of emotions in morality is more complex than a simple rejection of such a role; see N. Sherman, "The place of emotions in Kantian morality," in O. Flanagan and A.O. Rorty (eds.), Identity, character, and morality (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1990).
    • (1980) Emotion , pp. 6-8
    • Lyons, W.1
  • 9
    • 0009130719 scopus 로고
    • Emotion
    • See also W.P. Alston, "Emotion and feeling," in P. Edwards (ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy (New York: Macmillan, 1967), Vol. II, pp. 479-486; E. Bedford, Emotions. Proceedings of the Artistotelian Society, 57 (1957), pp. 281-304; W. Lyons, Emotion (Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1980), pp. 6-8; and G. Pitcher, "Emotion," Mind, 74 (1965), pp. 326-345. Kant, who refers to emotions as simple feelings for which we are not responsible, indeed considers them to be irrelevant or even obstacles to responsible moral behavior. For criticism of Kant's view, see P. Lauritzen, "Errors of an ill-reasoning reason: The disparagement of emotions in the moral life," The Journal of Value Inquiry, 25 (1991), 5-21. Various places in Kant's writings may suggest that his view on the role of emotions in morality is more complex than a simple rejection of such a role; see N. Sherman, "The place of emotions in Kantian morality," in O. Flanagan and A.O. Rorty (eds.), Identity, character, and morality (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1990).
    • (1965) Mind , vol.74 , pp. 326-345
    • Pitcher, G.1
  • 10
    • 0347038245 scopus 로고
    • Errors of an ill-reasoning reason: The disparagement of emotions in the moral life
    • See also W.P. Alston, "Emotion and feeling," in P. Edwards (ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy (New York: Macmillan, 1967), Vol. II, pp. 479-486; E. Bedford, Emotions. Proceedings of the Artistotelian Society, 57 (1957), pp. 281-304; W. Lyons, Emotion (Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1980), pp. 6-8; and G. Pitcher, "Emotion," Mind, 74 (1965), pp. 326-345. Kant, who refers to emotions as simple feelings for which we are not responsible, indeed considers them to be irrelevant or even obstacles to responsible moral behavior. For criticism of Kant's view, see P. Lauritzen, "Errors of an ill-reasoning reason: The disparagement of emotions in the moral life," The Journal of Value Inquiry, 25 (1991), 5-21. Various places in Kant's writings may suggest that his view on the role of emotions in morality is more complex than a simple rejection of such a role; see N. Sherman, "The place of emotions in Kantian morality," in O. Flanagan and A.O. Rorty (eds.), Identity, character, and morality (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1990).
    • (1991) The Journal of Value Inquiry , vol.25 , pp. 5-21
    • Lauritzen, P.1
  • 11
    • 0347038247 scopus 로고
    • The place of emotions in Kantian morality
    • O. Flanagan and A.O. Rorty (eds.), Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
    • See also W.P. Alston, "Emotion and feeling," in P. Edwards (ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy (New York: Macmillan, 1967), Vol. II, pp. 479-486; E. Bedford, Emotions. Proceedings of the Artistotelian Society, 57 (1957), pp. 281-304; W. Lyons, Emotion (Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1980), pp. 6-8; and G. Pitcher, "Emotion," Mind, 74 (1965), pp. 326-345. Kant, who refers to emotions as simple feelings for which we are not responsible, indeed considers them to be irrelevant or even obstacles to responsible moral behavior. For criticism of Kant's view, see P. Lauritzen, "Errors of an ill-reasoning reason: The disparagement of emotions in the moral life," The Journal of Value Inquiry, 25 (1991), 5-21. Various places in Kant's writings may suggest that his view on the role of emotions in morality is more complex than a simple rejection of such a role; see N. Sherman, "The place of emotions in Kantian morality," in O. Flanagan and A.O. Rorty (eds.), Identity, character, and morality (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 1990).
    • (1990) Identity, Character, and Morality
    • Sherman, N.1
  • 12
    • 0001811513 scopus 로고
    • The economy of gratitude
    • D.D. Franks and E.D. McCarthy (eds.), New York: JAI Press, ch. 4
    • See also A.R. Hochschild, "The economy of gratitude," in D.D. Franks and E.D. McCarthy (eds.), The sociology of emotions (New York: JAI Press, 1989), ch. 4; and Lyons, op. cit.
    • (1989) The Sociology of Emotions
    • Hochschild, A.R.1
  • 13
    • 0346408109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also A.R. Hochschild, "The economy of gratitude," in D.D. Franks and E.D. McCarthy (eds.), The sociology of emotions (New York: JAI Press, 1989), ch. 4; and Lyons, op. cit.
    • The Sociology of Emotions
    • Lyons1
  • 14
    • 0346408108 scopus 로고
    • Emotion
    • W. Reich (ed.), New York: Macmillan
    • N. Sherman, "Emotion," in W. Reich (ed.), Encyclopedia of Bioethics (New York: Macmillan, 1995), pp. 664-671.
    • (1995) Encyclopedia of Bioethics , pp. 664-671
    • Sherman, N.1
  • 15
    • 0347669012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Artistotle, op. cit., 1106b, 16-23; J. Horder, Provocation and responsibility (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), p. 44; and N. Sherman, "The role of emotions in Artistotelian virtue," Proceedings of the Boston area colloquium in ancient philosophy, IX (1993), pp. 1-33. The indirect nature of emotional regulation has been indicated by other philosophers as well. For example, Descartes argues that our passions "cannot be directly aroused or suppressed by the action of our will, but only indirectly through the representation of things which are usually joined with the passions we wish to have and opposed to the passions we wish to reject." Similarly, Spinoza claims: "An affect cannot be restrained or taken away except by an affect opposite to, and stronger than, the affect to be restrained."
    • Encyclopedia of Bioethics , vol.1106 B , pp. 16-23
    • Artistotle1
  • 16
    • 0004188564 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Artistotle, op. cit., 1106b, 16-23; J. Horder, Provocation and responsibility (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), p. 44; and N. Sherman, "The role of emotions in Artistotelian virtue," Proceedings of the Boston area colloquium in ancient philosophy, IX (1993), pp. 1-33. The indirect nature of emotional regulation has been indicated by other philosophers as well. For example, Descartes argues that our passions "cannot be directly aroused or suppressed by the action of our will, but only indirectly through the representation of things which are usually joined with the passions we wish to have and opposed to the passions we wish to reject." Similarly, Spinoza claims: "An affect cannot be restrained or taken away except by an affect opposite to, and stronger than, the affect to be restrained."
    • (1992) Provocation and Responsibility , pp. 44
    • Horder, J.1
  • 17
    • 0345776855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The role of emotions in Artistotelian virtue
    • Artistotle, op. cit., 1106b, 16-23; J. Horder, Provocation and responsibility (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), p. 44; and N. Sherman, "The role of emotions in Artistotelian virtue," Proceedings of the Boston area colloquium in ancient philosophy, IX (1993), pp. 1-33. The indirect nature of emotional regulation has been indicated by other philosophers as well. For example, Descartes argues that our passions "cannot be directly aroused or suppressed by the action of our will, but only indirectly through the representation of things which are usually joined with the passions we wish to have and opposed to the passions we wish to reject." Similarly, Spinoza claims: "An affect cannot be restrained or taken away except by an affect opposite to, and stronger than, the affect to be restrained."
    • (1993) Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy , vol.9 , pp. 1-33
    • Sherman, N.1
  • 18
    • 0038912416 scopus 로고
    • Emotion, practical knowledge and common culture
    • A. Rorty (ed.), Berkeley: University of California Press
    • R. Scruton, "Emotion, practical knowledge and common culture," in A. Rorty (ed.), Explaining emotions (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), p. 525.
    • (1980) Explaining Emotions , pp. 525
    • Scruton, R.1
  • 19
    • 0004276563 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press
    • R. Gordon, The structure of emotions (Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1987), pp. 125-127.
    • (1987) The Structure of Emotions , pp. 125-127
    • Gordon, R.1
  • 20
    • 0002417199 scopus 로고
    • Sadder but wiser? Rationality and the emotions
    • See also J. Elster, "Sadder but wiser? Rationality and the emotions," Social Science Information, 24 (1985), pp. 375-406; P. Greenspan, Emotions and reasons (New York: Routledge, 1988), pp. 10 and 155; and E. Sankowski, "Responsibility of persons for their emotions," Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 1 (1977), pp. 829-840.
    • (1985) Social Science Information , vol.24 , pp. 375-406
    • Elster, J.1
  • 21
    • 0002417199 scopus 로고
    • New York: Routledge
    • See also J. Elster, "Sadder but wiser? Rationality and the emotions," Social Science Information, 24 (1985), pp. 375-406; P. Greenspan, Emotions and reasons (New York: Routledge, 1988), pp. 10 and 155; and E. Sankowski, "Responsibility of persons for their emotions," Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 1 (1977), pp. 829-840.
    • (1988) Emotions and Reasons , pp. 10
    • Greenspan, P.1
  • 22
    • 0040414208 scopus 로고
    • Responsibility of persons for their emotions
    • See also J. Elster, "Sadder but wiser? Rationality and the emotions," Social Science Information, 24 (1985), pp. 375-406; P. Greenspan, Emotions and reasons (New York: Routledge, 1988), pp. 10 and 155; and E. Sankowski, "Responsibility of persons for their emotions," Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 1 (1977), pp. 829-840.
    • (1977) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.1 , pp. 829-840
    • Sankowski, E.1
  • 24
    • 84925666905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Along these lines, Ferguson argues: "As jealousy is often the most watchful guardian of chastity, so malice of often the quickest to spy the fallings of our neighbour. . . the worst principles of our nature may be at the bottom of our pretended zeal for morality," op. cit., p. 36. See also A. Ben-Ze'ev, "Envy and inequality," Journal of Philosophy, 89 (1992), pp. 551-581.
    • An Essay on the History of Civil Society , pp. 36
  • 25
    • 0010850909 scopus 로고
    • Envy and inequality
    • Along these lines, Ferguson argues: "As jealousy is often the most watchful guardian of chastity, so malice of often the quickest to spy the fallings of our neighbour. . . the worst principles of our nature may be at the bottom of our pretended zeal for morality," op. cit., p. 36. See also A. Ben-Ze'ev, "Envy and inequality," Journal of Philosophy, 89 (1992), pp. 551-581.
    • (1992) Journal of Philosophy , vol.89 , pp. 551-581
    • Ben-Ze'ev, A.1
  • 26
    • 0038643020 scopus 로고
    • You always hurt the one you love
    • A. Ben-Ze'ev, "You always hurt the one you love," The Journal of Value Inquiry, 27 (1993), pp. 487-495;
    • (1993) The Journal of Value Inquiry , vol.27 , pp. 487-495
    • Ben-Ze'ev, A.1
  • 29
    • 0346408101 scopus 로고
    • Desire and emotion in the virtue tradition
    • G.A. Hartz, "Desire and emotion in the virtue tradition," Philosophia, 20 (1990), pp. 145-165; and R.C. Solomon, The passions (New York: Doubleday, 1976).
    • (1990) Philosophia , vol.20 , pp. 145-165
    • Hartz, G.A.1
  • 30
    • 0346408101 scopus 로고
    • New York: Doubleday
    • G.A. Hartz, "Desire and emotion in the virtue tradition," Philosophia, 20 (1990), pp. 145-165; and R.C. Solomon, The passions (New York: Doubleday, 1976).
    • (1976) The Passions
    • Solomon, R.C.1
  • 32
    • 0019765646 scopus 로고
    • The tyranny of principles
    • December
    • S. Toulmin, "The tyranny of principles," The Hastings center report, December 1981; see also A. Ben-Ze'ev, "Emotional and moral evaluation," Metaphilosophy, 23 (1992), pp. 214-229.
    • (1981) The Hastings Center Report
    • Toulmin, S.1
  • 33
    • 84981374633 scopus 로고
    • Emotional and moral evaluation
    • S. Toulmin, "The tyranny of principles," The Hastings center report, December 1981; see also A. Ben-Ze'ev, "Emotional and moral evaluation," Metaphilosophy, 23 (1992), pp. 214-229.
    • (1992) Metaphilosophy , vol.23 , pp. 214-229
    • Ben-Ze'ev, A.1
  • 34
    • 0346408102 scopus 로고
    • Friendship, morality, and special obligation
    • J.O. Grunebaum, "Friendship, morality, and special obligation," American Philosophical Quarterly, 30 (1993), pp. 51-61; H. Sigwick, Methods of ethics (New York: Dover, 1966), p. 434; and R.C. Solomon, A passion for justice: Emotions and the origins of the social contract (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1990), p. 47.
    • (1993) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.30 , pp. 51-61
    • Grunebaum, J.O.1
  • 35
    • 0004255852 scopus 로고
    • New York: Dover
    • J.O. Grunebaum, "Friendship, morality, and special obligation," American Philosophical Quarterly, 30 (1993), pp. 51-61; H. Sigwick, Methods of ethics (New York: Dover, 1966), p. 434; and R.C. Solomon, A passion for justice: Emotions and the origins of the social contract (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1990), p. 47.
    • (1966) Methods of Ethics , pp. 434
    • Sigwick, H.1
  • 36
    • 0004105941 scopus 로고
    • Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley
    • J.O. Grunebaum, "Friendship, morality, and special obligation," American Philosophical Quarterly, 30 (1993), pp. 51-61; H. Sigwick, Methods of ethics (New York: Dover, 1966), p. 434; and R.C. Solomon, A passion for justice: Emotions and the origins of the social contract (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1990), p. 47.
    • (1990) A Passion for Justice: Emotions and the Origins of the Social Contract , pp. 47
    • Solomon, R.C.1
  • 37
    • 0003587061 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press, ch. 3
    • L. A. Blum, Moral perception and particularity (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1994), ch. 3; I.P. Railton, "Alienation, consequentialism and the demands of morality," Philosophy and Public Affairs, 13 (1984), pp. 134-171; See also J. Cottingham, "Ethics and impartiality," Philosophical Studies, 43 (1983), pp. 83-99; J. Cottingham, "Partiality, favouritism and morality," Philosophical Quarterly, 36 (1986), pp. 357-373.
    • (1994) Moral Perception and Particularity
    • Blum, L.A.1
  • 38
    • 84875336363 scopus 로고
    • Alienation, consequentialism and the demands of morality
    • L. A. Blum, Moral perception and particularity (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1994), ch. 3; I.P. Railton, "Alienation, consequentialism and the demands of morality," Philosophy and Public Affairs, 13 (1984), pp. 134-171; See also J. Cottingham, "Ethics and impartiality," Philosophical Studies, 43 (1983), pp. 83-99; J. Cottingham, "Partiality, favouritism and morality," Philosophical Quarterly, 36 (1986), pp. 357-373.
    • (1984) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.13 , pp. 134-171
    • Railton, I.P.1
  • 39
    • 0040221590 scopus 로고
    • Ethics and impartiality
    • L. A. Blum, Moral perception and particularity (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1994), ch. 3; I.P. Railton, "Alienation, consequentialism and the demands of morality," Philosophy and Public Affairs, 13 (1984), pp. 134-171; See also J. Cottingham, "Ethics and impartiality," Philosophical Studies, 43 (1983), pp. 83-99; J. Cottingham, "Partiality, favouritism and morality," Philosophical Quarterly, 36 (1986), pp. 357-373.
    • (1983) Philosophical Studies , vol.43 , pp. 83-99
    • Cottingham, J.1
  • 40
    • 84963094861 scopus 로고
    • Partiality, favouritism and morality
    • L. A. Blum, Moral perception and particularity (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1994), ch. 3; I.P. Railton, "Alienation, consequentialism and the demands of morality," Philosophy and Public Affairs, 13 (1984), pp. 134-171; See also J. Cottingham, "Ethics and impartiality," Philosophical Studies, 43 (1983), pp. 83-99; J. Cottingham, "Partiality, favouritism and morality," Philosophical Quarterly, 36 (1986), pp. 357-373.
    • (1986) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.36 , pp. 357-373
    • Cottingham, J.1
  • 41
    • 0347038240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is interesting to note that sensitivity to the particular person is also part of Kant's morality which requires that we respect individuals in their own right as ends having intrinsic value.
  • 44
    • 0004183823 scopus 로고
    • Lawrence, Kans.: University Press of Kansas
    • M.W. Martin, Self-deception and morality (Lawrence, Kans.: University Press of Kansas, 1986), p. 65.
    • (1986) Self-deception and Morality , pp. 65
    • Martin, M.W.1
  • 45
    • 0347669003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The place of emotions in Kantian morality
    • Sherman, "The place of emotions in Kantian morality," op. cit., pp. 152-153.
    • Self-deception and Morality , pp. 152-153
    • Sherman1
  • 47
    • 0346408097 scopus 로고
    • Kant on sentimentalism and stoic apathy
    • H. Robinson (ed.), Milwaukee, Wis.: Marquette University Press
    • See also N. Sherman, "Kant on sentimentalism and stoic apathy," in H. Robinson (ed.), Proceedings of the 8th international Kant world congress, Vol. 1 (Milwaukee, Wis.: Marquette University Press, 1995), pp. 705-711.
    • (1995) Proceedings of the 8th International Kant World Congress , vol.1 , pp. 705-711
    • Sherman, N.1
  • 48
    • 84963052537 scopus 로고
    • Loyalty and virtues
    • R.E. Ewin, "Loyalty and virtues," Philosophical Quarterly, 42 (1992), pp. 403-419; S. Nathanson, "In defense of 'moderate patriotism'," Ethics, 99 (1989), pp. 535-552; I.P. Railton, "Alienation, consequentialism and the demands of morality "Philosophy & Public Affairs, 13 (1984), 134-171.
    • (1992) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.42 , pp. 403-419
    • Ewin, R.E.1
  • 49
    • 84963052537 scopus 로고
    • In defense of 'moderate patriotism'
    • R.E. Ewin, "Loyalty and virtues," Philosophical Quarterly, 42 (1992), pp. 403-419; S. Nathanson, "In defense of 'moderate patriotism'," Ethics, 99 (1989), pp. 535-552; I.P. Railton, "Alienation, consequentialism and the demands of morality "Philosophy & Public Affairs, 13 (1984), 134-171.
    • (1989) Ethics , vol.99 , pp. 535-552
    • Nathanson, S.1
  • 50
    • 84963052537 scopus 로고
    • Alienation, consequentialism and the demands of morality
    • R.E. Ewin, "Loyalty and virtues," Philosophical Quarterly, 42 (1992), pp. 403-419; S. Nathanson, "In defense of 'moderate patriotism'," Ethics, 99 (1989), pp. 535-552; I.P. Railton, "Alienation, consequentialism and the demands of morality "Philosophy & Public Affairs, 13 (1984), 134-171.
    • (1984) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.13 , pp. 134-171
    • Railton, I.P.1
  • 52
    • 0347668964 scopus 로고
    • Anger as a vice: A Maimonidean critique of Artistotle's ethics
    • This, for instance, is Maimonides' belief, and hence in his view, the virtuous person should imitate this behavior of God. See D.H. Frank, "Anger as a vice: A Maimonidean critique of Artistotle's ethics," History of Philosophy Quarterly, 7 (1990), pp. 269-281.
    • (1990) History of Philosophy Quarterly , vol.7 , pp. 269-281
    • Frank, D.H.1
  • 54
    • 0345776855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The role of emotions in Aristotelian virtue
    • Frank, op. cit, pp. 269-281; Sherman, "The role of emotions in Aristotelian virtue," op. cit., pp. 1-33.
    • History of Philosophy Quarterly , pp. 1-33
    • Sherman1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.