-
1
-
-
0007371542
-
The Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature
-
July
-
At least, it does not constitute aesthetic appreciation of nature as nature in the positive sense of that idea: see my 'The Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature', British Journal of Aesthetics, vol. 36, no. 3 (July 1996).
-
(1996)
British Journal of Aesthetics
, vol.36
, Issue.3
-
-
-
3
-
-
0004045957
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
On the conceptual or non-conceptual nature of perception and the question whether perceptual experience has a non-conceptual content, see Gareth Evans, The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982);
-
(1982)
The Varieties of Reference
-
-
Evans, G.1
-
4
-
-
0012632016
-
The Nonconceptual Content of Experience
-
Tim Crane ed, Cambridge: Cambridge U.P
-
Tim Crane, 'The Nonconceptual Content of Experience', in Tim Crane (ed.), The Contents of Experience (Cambridge: Cambridge U.P., 1992);
-
(1992)
The Contents of Experience
-
-
Crane, T.1
-
6
-
-
0004109730
-
-
Cambridge, Mass, Harvard U.P
-
and John McDowell, Mind and World (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard U.P., 1994).
-
(1994)
Mind and World
-
-
McDowell, J.1
-
7
-
-
0004187139
-
-
According to Kant, to judge whether an object is beautiful is, in one of his formulations, 'to judge whether freedom in the play of imagination harmonises or clashes with the lawfulness of understanding' (Immanuel Kant, Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, trans. Mary J. Gregor [The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1974], p. 109), the judgement being based on whether the subject experiences pleasure in the contemplation of the object's form, the subject's experience being thought of as exemplary or definitive for human beings.
-
(1974)
Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View
, pp. 109
-
-
Kant, I.1
Gregor, M.J.2
-
8
-
-
0006470148
-
-
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard U.P. especially chs 7-9
-
For a fuller account and an evaluation of Kant's attempted deduction of pure judgements of taste, see Paul Guyer's outstanding work, Kant and the Claims of Taste (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard U.P., 1979), especially chs 7-9;
-
(1979)
Kant and the Claims of Taste
-
-
Guyer's, P.1
-
9
-
-
60950653870
-
-
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, chs 4 and 5
-
Anthony Savile, Aesthetic Reconstructions (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1987), chs 4 and 5;
-
(1987)
Aesthetic Reconstructions
-
-
Savile, A.1
-
10
-
-
0012026665
-
-
London: Allen Lane, The Penguin Press
-
and Malcolm Budd, Values of Art (London: Allen Lane, The Penguin Press, 1995), pp. 26-38.
-
(1995)
Values of Art
, pp. 26-38
-
-
Budd, M.1
-
11
-
-
0010889819
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
This is easy to see from the fact that it is possible that nothing of kind K is, or is experienced by the judging subject as being, beautiful - as, perhaps, with spiders or octopi. (Note that to judge that something is beautiful for a K, or as far as Ks are concerned, is not the same as to judge that it is a beautiful K, i.e beautiful as a K.) Hegel located the distinction between beautiful and ugly animal kinds (not altogether accurately) in their displaying activity and quickness of movement, 'the higher ideality of life', rather than 'drowsy inactivity', or their being of unmixed species, rather than hybrids. (See G. W. F. Hegel, Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art, trans. T. M. Knox [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975], vol. I, pp. 130-131.)
-
(1975)
Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art
, vol.1
, pp. 130-131
-
-
Hegel, G.W.F.1
Knox, T.M.2
|