메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 2, Issue 4, 1998, Pages 299-320

Two kinds of organic unity

Author keywords

Desert; G. E. Moore; Holism; Intrinsic value; Pleasure; Value; Wholes

Indexed keywords


EID: 0005074458     PISSN: 13824554     EISSN: 15728609     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1023/A:1009795120631     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (74)

References (61)
  • 1
    • 0004264902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903), p. 28.
    • (1903) Principia Ethica , pp. 28
    • Moore, G.E.1
  • 3
    • 0007240067 scopus 로고
    • London: Oxford University Press
    • G. E. Moore, Ethics (London: Oxford University Press, 1965), p. 107.
    • (1965) Ethics , pp. 107
    • Moore, G.E.1
  • 4
    • 0004143533 scopus 로고
    • 2nd ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
    • William K. Frankena, Ethics, 2nd ed. (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1973), pp. 89-92
    • (1973) Ethics , pp. 89-92
    • Frankena W., K.1
  • 5
    • 0003740191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), pp. 501- 502
    • (1984) Reasons and Persons , pp. 501-502
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 6
    • 0004247732 scopus 로고
    • ed. Oskar Piest Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, A similar view has been discussed in political philosophy under the heading the "endorsement thesis"
    • John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, ed. Oskar Piest (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1957), pp. 12-16. A similar view has been discussed in political philosophy under the heading the "endorsement thesis"
    • (1957) Utilitarianism , pp. 12-16
    • John Stuart, M.1
  • 7
    • 0002494274 scopus 로고
    • Foundations of liberal equality
    • Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press
    • see Ronald Dworkin, "Foundations of Liberal Equality," The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Vol. 11 (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, 1990), pp. 1-119
    • (1990) The Tanner Lectures on Human Values , vol.11 , pp. 1-119
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 9
    • 77449106969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Some presentations of this view conflate two distinct questions. One is whether a pleasure intentionally directed at a perfectionist state such as knowledge is better than a pleasure with no such object, for example a bodily pleasure such as that of eating ice cream. The other question is whether the combination of a pleasure directed at a perfectionist state and the real existence of that state is better than the pleasure alone. Only the second of these questions involves the principle of organic unities (see the end of Section 2 below). The conflation is evident, for example, in Parfit's suggestion that there is a symmetrical dependence between pleasure and perfectionist states, so that just as knowledge without pleasure lacks value, so pleasure without an object like knowledge lacks value. But the pleasure that is necessary for knowledge to have value is not just any pleasure; it is pleasure in knowledge and not just, say, an accompanying pleasure of eating ice cream. And if we ask whether pleasure in knowledge has value in the absence of knowledge, the answer seems to be "yes". Aristotle's pleasure in what he falsely believed was his knowledge of biology seems every bit as good as pleasure in real knowledge of the same value. The pleasure that lacks value on Parfit's view is pleasure without an object like knowledge, but that pleasure is not the condition for knowledge's having value. And the pleasure that is the condition for that value does not lack value on its own.
  • 10
    • 0008043213 scopus 로고
    • The conception of intrinsic value
    • in his London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • G. E. Moore, "The Conception of Intrinsic Value," in his Philosophical Studies (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1922), p. 260.
    • (1922) Philosophical Studies , pp. 260
    • Moore, G.E.1
  • 11
    • 77449159677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Moore's use of a "method of isolation," whereby we test for intrinsic value by asking whether a world containing only a given state and no other to which it could be related is good 95, 187-188
    • See also Moore's use of a "method of isolation," whereby we test for intrinsic value by asking whether a world containing only a given state and no other to which it could be related is good Principia Ethica, pp. 93, 95, 187-188;
    • Principia Ethica , pp. 9-15
  • 12
    • 77449138350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ethics, pp. 24, 68.
    • Ethics , vol.68 , pp. 24
  • 13
    • 0001610801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two distinctions in goodness
    • The strict definition is also adopted in
    • The strict definition is also adopted in Christine M. Korsgaard, "Two Distinctions in Goodness," Philosophical Review 92 (1983), pp. 169-195
    • (1983) Philosophical Review , vol.92 , pp. 169-195
    • Korsgaard, C.M.1
  • 19
    • 0001610801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Korsgaard's claim may be true for the view that states are good whenever they are the object of desire, or of rational desire. But that view is very different from the views I am expressing using the principle of organic unities
    • Korsgaard, "Two Distinctions in Goodness," p. 170. Korsgaard's claim may be true for the view that states are good whenever they are the object of desire, or of rational desire. But that view is very different from the views I am expressing using the principle of organic unities.
    • Two Distinctions in Goodness , pp. 170
    • Korsgaard1
  • 20
    • 77449134064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is logically possible for a mixed view to deny the generic principle of organic unities. Thus, it is logically possible to hold that whenever the value of a part changes when it enters a whole, there is a compensating value in the whole as a whole that restores the overall value to the sum of the values the parts would have alone. But surely this is just a logical possibility. Surely anyone who makes conditionality claims will want them to have some effect on the overall values of wholes.
  • 21
    • 77449140021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that there is not this reason to favour the conditionality interpretation of Moore's earlier view, on which beauty on its own does have intrinsic value. On this earlier view A's admiration is always of something good in itself, and its appropriateness as an attitude can be equally well explained by a holistic interpretation.
  • 23
    • 77449131748 scopus 로고
    • I discuss this view on what is implicitly a conditionality interpretation in
    • I discuss this view on what is implicitly a conditionality interpretation in Perfectionism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), pp. 110-111.
    • (1993) Perfectionism New York: Oxford University Press , pp. 110-111
  • 24
    • 77449148981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A different account of these issues is proposed by Shelly Kagan. He holds that when the value of a person's life is affected by a relation between himself and a state of the world such as the preservation of Venice, that relational fact and perhaps also the state of the world are internal to or parts of his life, even though they are not internal to him
  • 26
    • 77449143090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • But if we can use the looser definition of intrinsic value, as Kagan himself allows, I see no reason to make this claim. We can equate a person's life with a sequence of states or events within his body and mind and still say that the value of that life is affected by relations to external states even though neither those states nor the facts relating him to them are internal to his life.
  • 28
    • 0039475550 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Self-interest, altruism, and virtue
    • See Thomas Hurka, "Self-Interest, Altruism, and Virtue," Social Philosophy and Policy 14 (1997), pp. 295-298.
    • (1997) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.14 , pp. 295-298
    • Hurka, T.1
  • 31
    • 0004240210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press, 138-140
    • W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1930), pp. 58, 72, 138-140.
    • (1930) The Right and the Good , vol.72 , pp. 5-8
    • Ross, W.D.1
  • 33
    • 0004071138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981), p. 367.
    • Philosophical Explanations , pp. 198-205
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 34
    • 65649115344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adjusting utility for justice: A consequentialist reply to the objection from justice
    • in his Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, -p. 167
    • Fred Feldman, "Adjusting Utility for Justice: A Consequentialist Reply to the Objection from Justice," in his Utilitarianism, Hedonism, and Desert (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), pp. 151-174-p. 167.
    • (1997) Utilitarianism, Hedonism, and Desert , pp. 151-174
    • Feldman, F.1
  • 35
    • 77449085790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Feldman's desert view differs from Kors- gaard's in holding that pleasure in the absence of desert has, not zero, but some positive value, and also in denying that virtue on its own has value. Like any conditionality view, Feldman's presupposes the looser definition of intrinsic value on which a state's value can be affected by its relations to other states. But in his "On the Intrinsic Value of Pleasures" (ibid., pp. 125-147), Feldman criticizes a "Sidgwickian" view of the intrinsic value of pleasure for being inconsistent with the strict definition. His own theory of desert seems to appeal to the very understanding of intrinsic value he denies to views that ground the value of pleasures in a relation to desires.
  • 36
    • 0004221561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These philosophers hold that B is a proper part of A whenever A's existence conceptually implies B's but B's existence does not conceptually imply A's
    • These philosophers hold that B is a proper part of A whenever A's existence conceptually implies B's but B's existence does not conceptually imply A's Chisholm, Brentano and Intrinsic Value, p. 73
    • Brentano and Intrinsic Value , pp. 73
    • Chisholm1
  • 39
    • 77449142857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This makes a person's feeling pleasure a part of his feeling pleasure in pain, they claim, since he cannot feel pleasure in pain without feeling pleasure but can feel pleasure without feeling pleasure in pain. But this analysis requires understanding parts and wholes as universals. It is not true that the person could feel the particular pleasure he feels without feeling pleasure in pain, since that is what his particular pleasure is. What is true is only that he could feel some pleasure or other without feeling pleasure in pain. But this treatment of parts and wholes as universals seems to me strained, as more generally does the claim that its being a pleasure is part of a pleasure in pain rather than an aspect or property of it.
  • 40
    • 77449124109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Korsgaard ascribes the conditionality view of undeserved pleasure to Immanual Kant and endorses it herself; she would presumably endorse the parallel view about malicious pleasure. In the most extensive recent discussion of these views Lemos attributes both views to Ross
  • 42
    • 77449135306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • but this seems to me on several grounds a mistake. First, Ross's explicit claims that undeserved and malicious pleasure are evil
    • but this seems to me on several grounds a mistake. First, Ross's explicit claims that undeserved and malicious pleasure are evil (The Right and the Good, pp. 136-138)
    • The Right and the Good , pp. 136-138
  • 43
    • 77449113720 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • are open to three interpretations: (i) such pleasures are purely evil with no element of good; (ii) such pleasures are evil as undeserved or malicious, though perhaps also good as pleasures; (iii) such pleasures are evil on balance, with their evil as undeserved or malicious outweighing their goodness as pleasures. I see nothing in Ross's text that clearly favours (i) over (ii) and especially (iii), but only (i) expresses a conditionality view. Second, Ross accepts Moore's strict definition of intrinsic goodness (ibid., pp. 114-121)
  • 44
    • 77449112697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • which implies the universality thesis and logically prevents pleasure from changing value when undeserved. Third, a related argument of Ross's explicitly assumes a denial of the conditionality view. Ross holds that virtue and vice have infinite value compared to pleasure and pain, and one of his main arguments for this view concerns malicious pleasure. It claims that unless virtue has infinite comparative value, malicious pleasure could if sufficiently intense be on balance good, which Ross thinks is impossible (ibid., p. 151).
  • 45
    • 77449083345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This argument presupposes that malicious pleasure remains good as pleasure, with that goodness always needing to be outweighed by a greater evil of malice.
  • 47
    • 77449119508 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid., pp. 43-44.
  • 48
    • 0040660916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The virtue in self-interest
    • See also
    • See also Michael Slote, "The Virtue in Self-Interest," Social Philosophy and Policy 14 (1997), pp. 273-274
    • (1997) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.14 , pp. 273-274
    • Slote, M.1
  • 49
    • 52549130913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intrinsic value and moral obligation
    • Robert Audi, "Intrinsic Value and Moral Obligation," The Southern Journal of Philosophy 35 (1997), p. 140.
    • (1997) The Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.35 , pp. 140
    • Audi, R.1
  • 51
    • 77449100839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It may be that different goods are called for by different forms of virtue. For example, if a person is dedicated and principled in his pursuit of knowledge, perhaps what he deserves is knowledge more than pleasure. But the general point remains. For any form of virtue only some goods are appropriate rewards, and for any form of vice only some goods make for an evil of undesert.
  • 52
    • 0039475571 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How great a good is virtue?
    • I also give this argument in Thomas Hurka
    • I also give this argument in Thomas Hurka, "How Great a Good is Virtue?" The Journal of Philosophy 95 (1998), pp. 181-203.
    • (1998) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.95 , pp. 181-203
  • 53
    • 0004308728 scopus 로고
    • Seetrans. Roderick M. Chisholm and Elizabeth Schneewind London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • See Franz Brentano, The Origin of Our Knowledge of Right and Wrong, trans. Roderick M. Chisholm and Elizabeth Schneewind (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1969), pp. 22-23
    • (1969) The Origin of Our Knowledge of Right and Wrong , pp. 22-23
    • Brentano, F.1
  • 54
    • 0004264902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 208-209, 211, 217
    • Moore, Principia Ethica, pp. 204, 208-209, 211, 217
    • Principia Ethica , pp. 204
    • Moore1
  • 59
    • 84974160111 scopus 로고
    • Virtue as loving the good
    • Thomas Hurka "Virtue as Loving the Good," Social Philosophy and Policy 9 (1992), pp. 149-168.
    • (1992) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.9 , pp. 149-168
    • Hurka, T.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.