메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 108, Issue 2, 1998, Pages 312-339

The autonomy defense of free speech

(1)  Brison, Susan J a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0002422030     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/233807     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (126)

References (180)
  • 1
    • 26444480298 scopus 로고
    • Autonomy in Law
    • ed. John Christman New York: Oxford University Press
    • See David A. J. Richards, "Autonomy in Law," in The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy, ed. John Christman (New York: Oxford University Press, 1989), pp. 246-58. Richards also considers autonomy to ground the right to free speech, as well as defendants' rights under the criminal law. According to Richards, "Autonomy is a core value in American public and private law, since it is one of the constitutive ingredients of the generative idea of background rights of the person to which interpretive controversy in American law characteristically appeals" (p. 246).
    • (1989) The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy , pp. 246-258
    • Richards, D.A.J.1
  • 3
    • 11144341194 scopus 로고
    • The Constitution and Autonomy
    • Rogers M. Smith refers to these rights, as well as the right to free speech and the right to privacy relied upon in recent Fourth and Fifth Amendment cases, as grounded in "the fundamental value [of] autonomy," in "The Constitution and Autonomy," Texas Law Review 60 (1982): 175-205, p. 175. In this article, Smith analyzes what he takes to be "a broad and basic transformation in liberal political theory, and correspondingly in American constitutional thought, that has given a new centrality to autonomy concerns" (p. 176).
    • (1982) Texas Law Review , vol.60 , pp. 175-205
    • Smith, R.M.1
  • 4
    • 0040567352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Autonomy in Law," "Free Speech and Obscenity Law: Toward a Moral Theory of the First Amendment,"
    • I use the term "free speech" to cover freedom of the press as well. Autonomy defenses of free speech can be found in David A. J. Richards, "Autonomy in Law," "Free Speech and Obscenity Law: Toward a Moral Theory of the First Amendment," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 123 (1974): 45-91,
    • (1974) University of Pennsylvania Law Review , vol.123 , pp. 45-91
    • Richards, D.A.J.1
  • 5
    • 26444534043 scopus 로고
    • Pornography Commissions and the First Amendment: On Constitutional Values and Constitutional Facts
    • "Pornography Commissions and the First Amendment: On Constitutional Values and Constitutional Facts," Maine Law Review 39 (1987): 275-320,
    • (1987) Maine Law Review , vol.39 , pp. 275-320
  • 6
    • 84928837685 scopus 로고
    • Toleration and Free Speech
    • "Toleration and Free Speech," Philosophy and Public Affairs 17 (1988): 323-36;
    • (1988) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.17 , pp. 323-336
  • 7
    • 0003981612 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985),
    • (1985) A Matter of Principle
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 8
    • 0013397983 scopus 로고
    • Liberty and Pornography
    • August 15
    • "Liberty and Pornography," New York Review of Books (August 15, 1991), pp. 12-15,
    • (1991) New York Review of Books , pp. 12-15
  • 9
    • 0010212472 scopus 로고
    • Women and Pornography
    • October 21
    • "Women and Pornography," New York Review of Books (October 21, 1993), pp. 36-42,
    • (1993) New York Review of Books , pp. 36-42
  • 10
    • 0347098353 scopus 로고
    • The Coming Battles over Free Speech
    • June 11
    • "The Coming Battles over Free Speech," New York Review of Books (June 11, 1992), pp. 55-64;
    • (1992) New York Review of Books , pp. 55-64
  • 11
    • 34248543738 scopus 로고
    • A Theory of Freedom of Expression
    • Thomas Scanlon, "A Theory of Freedom of Expression," Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (1972): 204-26,
    • (1972) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.1 , pp. 204-226
    • Scanlon, T.1
  • 12
    • 0347728836 scopus 로고
    • Freedom of Expression and Categories of Expression
    • "Freedom of Expression and Categories of Expression," University of Pittsburgh Law Review 40 (1979): 519-50;
    • (1979) University of Pittsburgh Law Review , vol.40 , pp. 519-550
  • 13
    • 84935459594 scopus 로고
    • The New First Amendment Jurisprudence: A Threat to Liberty
    • ed. Geoffrey R. Stone, Richard A. Epstein, and Cass R. Sunstein Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Charles Fried, "The New First Amendment Jurisprudence: A Threat to Liberty," in The Bill of Rights in the Modern State, ed. Geoffrey R. Stone, Richard A. Epstein, and Cass R. Sunstein (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992);
    • (1992) The Bill of Rights in the Modern State
    • Fried, C.1
  • 14
    • 0346703553 scopus 로고
    • Persuasion, Autonomy, and Freedom of Expression
    • David Strauss, "Persuasion, Autonomy, and Freedom of Expression," Columbia Law Review 91 (1991): 334-71;
    • (1991) Columbia Law Review , vol.91 , pp. 334-371
    • Strauss, D.1
  • 16
    • 0010158702 scopus 로고
    • Scope of the First Amendment Freedom of Speech
    • C. Edwin Baker, "Scope of the First Amendment Freedom of Speech," UCLA Law Review 25 (1978): 961-90,
    • (1978) UCLA Law Review , vol.25 , pp. 961-990
    • Baker, C.E.1
  • 18
    • 0042678711 scopus 로고
    • Rights in Collision: A Non-punitive Compensatory Remedy for Abusive Speech
    • Diana T. Meyers, "Rights in Collision: A Non-punitive Compensatory Remedy for Abusive Speech," Law and Philosophy 14 (1995): 203-43;
    • (1995) Law and Philosophy , vol.14 , pp. 203-243
    • Meyers, D.T.1
  • 19
    • 84937288609 scopus 로고
    • Personal Rights and Public Space
    • Thomas Nagel, "Personal Rights and Public Space," Philosophy and Public Affairs 24 (1995): 83-107.
    • (1995) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.24 , pp. 83-107
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 20
    • 84928848869 scopus 로고
    • Free Speech Justifications
    • Kent Greenawalt, who criticizes some attempts to ground free speech in the singular value of autonomy, nonetheless appeals to autonomy as one of "the subtle plurality of values that does govern the practice of freedom of speech." Kent Greenawalt, "Free Speech Justifications," Columbia Law Review 89 (1989): 119-55, p. 119.
    • (1989) Columbia Law Review , vol.89 , pp. 119-155
    • Greenawalt, K.1
  • 21
    • 85055295295 scopus 로고
    • Managing Deliberation: The Quandary of Democratic Dialogue
    • Robert C. Post, "Managing Deliberation: The Quandary of Democratic Dialogue," Ethics 103 (1993): 654-78, p. 666.
    • (1993) Ethics , vol.103 , pp. 654-678
    • Post, R.C.1
  • 22
    • 0003649668 scopus 로고
    • Baltimore: National Institute against Prejudice and Violence, appendix
    • For a selected list of reported incidents of hate speech on college campuses from 1986 to 1988, see Howard J. Ehrlich, Campus Ethnoviolence and the Policy Options (Baltimore: National Institute against Prejudice and Violence, 1990), appendix.
    • (1990) Campus Ethnoviolence and the Policy Options
    • Ehrlich, H.J.1
  • 25
    • 0003472540 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • For numerous examples of pornography that could be construed as hate speech under this definition, see the analyses of pornography in Catherine MacKinnon, Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1987),
    • (1987) Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law
    • MacKinnon, C.1
  • 26
    • 0004239464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Only Words (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993),
    • (1993) Only Words
  • 27
    • 0003833353 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Toward a Feminist Theory of the State (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993);
    • (1993) Toward a Feminist Theory of the State
  • 28
    • 84859399646 scopus 로고
    • U.S. Department of Justice, July
    • Attorney General's Commission on Pornography, Final Report, U.S. Department of Justice, July 1986;
    • (1986) Final Report
  • 31
    • 0002778018 scopus 로고
    • If He Hollers Let Him Go: Regulating Racist Speech on Campus
    • Mari J. Matsuda et al., Boulder, Colo.: Westview
    • Quoted in Charles R. Lawrence III, "If He Hollers Let Him Go: Regulating Racist Speech on Campus," in Mari J. Matsuda et al., Words That Wound: Critical Race Theory, Assaultive Speech, and the First Amendment (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1993), p. 67. The Stanford code was struck down by the court because of the Leonard Law which requires even private educational institutions in California to abide by the U.S. Constitution.
    • (1993) Words That Wound: Critical Race Theory, Assaultive Speech, and the First Amendment , pp. 67
    • Lawrence III, C.R.1
  • 32
    • 85034186875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Doe v. University of Michigan, 721 F. Supp. 852, 856 (E.D.Mich. 1989). This is a partial definition taken from the University of Michigan policy on discrimination and discriminatory harassment, a policy which was ruled unconstitutional in Doe v. University of Michigan. This definition was based on existing sexual harassment law prohibiting "hostile environment" harassment. See Meritor Savings Bank v. Vinson, 477 U.S. 57 (1986).
  • 33
    • 85034182579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beauharnais v. People of the State of Illinois, 343 U.S. 250 (1957) at 251
    • Beauharnais v. People of the State of Illinois, 343 U.S. 250 (1957) at 251.
  • 34
    • 85034170188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964)
    • New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964).
  • 35
    • 0345745280 scopus 로고
    • Group Libel versus Free Speech: When Big Brother Should Butt in
    • See, e.g., Kenneth Lasson, "Group Libel versus Free Speech: When Big Brother Should Butt In," Duquesne Law Review 23 (1984): 77-130.
    • (1984) Duquesne Law Review , vol.23 , pp. 77-130
    • Lasson, K.1
  • 36
    • 85034196375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Doe v. University of Michigan; UWM Post v. Board of Regents of the University of Wisconsin, 774 F. Supp. 1163 (E.D. Wis. 1991)
    • Doe v. University of Michigan; UWM Post v. Board of Regents of the University of Wisconsin, 774 F. Supp. 1163 (E.D. Wis. 1991).
  • 37
    • 85034175333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the U.S. Court of Appeals, 771 F.2d 323 (7th Cir. 1985)
    • For the U.S. Court of Appeals, 771 F.2d 323 (7th Cir. 1985).
  • 38
    • 85034172289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ibid., p. 329. One doesn't, however, hear the courts declaring that if segregation harms minorities' opportunities for equal rights this simply demonstrates the power of freedom of association.
  • 39
    • 85034157301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Doe v. University of Michigan, 721 F. Supp. at 853
    • Doe v. University of Michigan, 721 F. Supp. at 853.
  • 40
    • 85034163427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 863
    • Ibid., p. 863.
  • 41
    • 85034191154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, in press
    • R.A.V. v. St. Paul, 120 L.Ed.2d, 305 (1992). Justice Scalia's opinion raises too many issues for me even to begin to discuss them here, but I examine them in my Speech, Harm, and Conflict of Rights (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, in press).
    • Speech, Harm, and Conflict of Rights
  • 42
    • 85034168850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As Nagel observes, "The censorship of a fanatical bigot is an offense to us all." He makes it clear that he is "not just talking about the more ridiculous excesses of political correctness, but about the prohibition of hard-core, intentional expressions of hostility." See Nagel, p. 98.
  • 43
    • 0348197361 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • As Lee Bollinger notes, "There is a curious disjunction in our attitudes about the degree to which we should tolerate the speech of others. When we compare our reluctance to impose legal restraints against speech with our readiness to employ a host of informal, or nonlegal, forms of coercion against speech behavior, the paradox is striking." Lee Bollinger, The Tolerant Society (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), p. 12.
    • (1986) The Tolerant Society , pp. 12
    • Bollinger, L.1
  • 44
    • 85034194659 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Speech, Harm, and the Mind-Body Problem in First Amendment Jurisprudence
    • forthcoming
    • I defend this claim in "Speech, Harm, and the Mind-Body Problem in First Amendment Jurisprudence," forthcoming in Legal Theory.
    • Legal Theory
  • 45
    • 85050417302 scopus 로고
    • The Phenomenology of Speech and Harm
    • Matsuda et al.
    • For discussions of the nature of the harm of hate speech, see also Frederick Schauer, "The Phenomenology of Speech and Harm," Ethics 103 (1993): 635-53; Matsuda et al.;
    • (1993) Ethics , vol.103 , pp. 635-653
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 47
    • 0002261086 scopus 로고
    • Racist Speech, Democracy, and the First Amendment
    • Robert C. Post, "Racist Speech, Democracy, and the First Amendment," William and Mary Law Review 32 (1991): 267-327, pp. 271-77.
    • (1991) William and Mary Law Review , vol.32 , pp. 267-327
    • Post, R.C.1
  • 48
    • 0007577430 scopus 로고
    • The Bill of Rights
    • Justice Hugo L. Black, Smith v. California, 361 U.S. 147, 157 (1959). See also his article, "The Bill of Rights," New York University Law Review 35 (1960):865-81.
    • (1960) New York University Law Review , vol.35 , pp. 865-881
  • 49
    • 85034179151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919)
    • Schenck v. United States, 249 U.S. 47 (1919).
  • 50
    • 85034201069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fighting words are "those which by their very utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of the peace." Chaplinsky v. State of New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568 (1942)
    • Fighting words are "those which by their very utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate breach of the peace." Chaplinsky v. State of New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568 (1942).
  • 51
    • 85034178803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Libel is printed defamatory speech that impeaches the reputation of an individual, exposing him or her to hatred, contempt, ridicule, or financial injury. At times, group libel has also been unprotected. Group libel is speech that "exposes the citizens of any race, color, creed or religion to contempt, derision, or obloquy or which is productive of breach of the peace or riots." Beauharnais v. People of State of Illinois, 343 U.S. at 251. Beauharnais, though never formally overturned, is no longer considered to be authoritative. Group libel is now considered to be constitutionally protected speech. After New York Times Co. v. Sullivan was decided in 1964, it became extremely difficult for public figures to win libel suits, since the Court determined that "the constitutional guarantees require . . . a federal rule that prohibits a public official from recovering damages for a defamatory false-hood relating to his official conduct unless he proves that the statement was made with 'actual malice' - that is, with knowledge that it was false or with reckless disregard of whether it was false or not." New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 279-80. Libel of private individuals continues to be less protected, however.
  • 52
    • 85034191497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 'Obscenity' is defined as works that "appeal to the prurient interest in sex . . . in a patently offensive way, and which, taken as a whole, do not have serious literary, artistic, political or scientific value." Miller v. California, 413 U.S. 15 (1973).
  • 53
    • 85034178458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Posadas de Puerto Rico Assocs. v. Tourism Co., 478 U.S. 328 (1986)
    • See, e.g., Posadas de Puerto Rico Assocs. v. Tourism Co., 478 U.S. 328 (1986).
  • 54
    • 85034194896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although the ordinance adopted by Stanford University touched only hate speech that counts as fighting words, it was recently struck down by the courts, since Stanford employs a definition of "fighting words" that is no longer considered good law, and since, although Stanford is a private institution, it is forbidden by California's "Leonard Law" to violate constitutionally protected rights.
  • 55
    • 85034201164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See R.A.V. v. St. Paul and Corry v. Leland Stanford Junior Univ., California Superior Court at Santa Clara, case no. 740309, February 27, 1995
    • See R.A.V. v. St. Paul and Corry v. Leland Stanford Junior Univ., California Superior Court at Santa Clara, case no. 740309, February 27, 1995.
  • 56
    • 85034197588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For example, Canada and most Western European countries have laws prohibiting speech that incites or promotes racial hatred. See Bollinger, pp. 253-56.
  • 57
    • 0000028891 scopus 로고
    • Public Response to Racist Speech: Considering the Victim's Story
    • Quoted in Mari Matsuda, "Public Response to Racist Speech: Considering the Victim's Story," University of Michigan Law Review 87 (1989): 2320-81, p. 2349.
    • (1989) University of Michigan Law Review , vol.87 , pp. 2320-2381
    • Matsuda, M.1
  • 59
    • 84902730457 scopus 로고
    • Uncoupling Free Speech
    • For discussions of the costs of hate speech to its victims and proposals for compensating them, see Frederick Schauer, "Uncoupling Free Speech," Columbia Law Review 92 (1992): 1321-57;
    • (1992) Columbia Law Review , vol.92 , pp. 1321-1357
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 61
    • 84926270778 scopus 로고
    • The Impossibility of a Free Speech Principle
    • Fish clearly means to assert both senses of his ambiguous title. Others who argue that no justification can be given for a free speech principle are Lawrence Alexander and Paul Horton, "The Impossibility of a Free Speech Principle," Northwestern University Law Review 78 (1984): 1319-57.
    • (1984) Northwestern University Law Review , vol.78 , pp. 1319-1357
    • Alexander, L.1    Horton, P.2
  • 65
    • 0002413504 scopus 로고
    • reprint, New York: New York University Press
    • John Milton, Areopagitica (1644; reprint, New York: New York University Press, 1968);
    • (1644) Areopagitica
    • Milton, J.1
  • 66
    • 0004001507 scopus 로고
    • reprint, Indianapolis: Hackett, Oliver Wendell Holmes, dissenting, in Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 630 (1919)
    • John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (1859; reprint, Indianapolis: Hackett, 1978); Oliver Wendell Holmes, dissenting, in Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 630 (1919).
    • (1859) On Liberty
    • Mill, J.S.1
  • 67
    • 85034155967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mill
    • Mill.
  • 69
    • 0040267387 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harper
    • Political Freedom (New York: Harper, 1960);
    • (1960) Political Freedom
  • 71
    • 0040311462 scopus 로고
    • Free Speech and Social Structure
    • Owen Fiss, "Free Speech and Social Structure," Iowa Law Review 71 (1986): 1405-25.
    • (1986) Iowa Law Review , vol.71 , pp. 1405-1425
    • Fiss, O.1
  • 72
    • 84985337969 scopus 로고
    • The Checking Value in First Amendment Theory
    • Vincent Blasi, "The Checking Value in First Amendment Theory," American Bar Foundation Research Journal, no. 3 (1977), pp. 521-649;
    • (1977) American Bar Foundation Research Journal , Issue.3 , pp. 521-649
    • Blasi, V.1
  • 75
  • 76
    • 0041543446 scopus 로고
    • Regulating Racist Speech on Campus: A Modest Proposal?
    • Nadine Strossen, "Regulating Racist Speech on Campus: A Modest Proposal?" Duke Law Journal (1990), pp. 484-572;
    • (1990) Duke Law Journal , pp. 484-572
    • Strossen, N.1
  • 78
    • 85034201336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The slippery slope argument is the one I hear most often from students and popular commentators. Judges are also fond of it. Judge Pell used a slippery slope argument in an appellate court opinion striking down the Village of Skokie's ordinance prohibiting dissemination of material which "promotes and incites hatred against persons by reason of their race, national origin, or religion, and is intended to do so." Collin v. Smith, 578 F.2d 1197, 1199 (1978). Pell argued that "the ordinance could conceivably be applied to criminalize dissemination of The Merchant of Venice," Collin v. Smith, 578 F.2d at 1207. In discussion (April 6, 1990), Lewis characterized his own defense of free speech in "Mill and Milquetoast" as a version of the slippery slope argument, but I think it is more accurately characterized as a version of the argument from tolerance.
  • 81
    • 0040567343 scopus 로고
    • Toward a General Theory of the First Amendment
    • Thomas I. Emerson, "Toward a General Theory of the First Amendment," Yale Law Journal 72 (1963): 877-956.
    • (1963) Yale Law Journal , vol.72 , pp. 877-956
    • Emerson, T.I.1
  • 83
    • 0007588330 scopus 로고
    • Slippery Slopes
    • "Slippery Slopes," Harvard Law Review 99 (1985): 361-83;
    • (1985) Harvard Law Review , vol.99 , pp. 361-383
  • 84
    • 84933489809 scopus 로고
    • John Stuart Mill and the Harm of Pornography
    • Alexander and Horton; the recent debate about Mill's theory of free speech in Ethics by David Dyzenhaus, "John Stuart Mill and the Harm of Pornography," Ethics 102 (1992): 534-51;
    • (1992) Ethics , vol.102 , pp. 534-551
    • Dyzenhaus, D.1
  • 85
    • 84982004193 scopus 로고
    • Mill and Pornography
    • Robert Skipper, "Mill and Pornography," Ethics 103 (1993): 726-30;
    • (1993) Ethics , vol.103 , pp. 726-730
    • Skipper, R.1
  • 86
    • 84937274587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Stuart Mill and Pornography: Beyond the Harm Principle
    • Richard Vernon, "John Stuart Mill and Pornography: Beyond the Harm Principle," Ethics 106 (1996): 621-32;
    • (1996) Ethics , vol.106 , pp. 621-632
    • Vernon, R.1
  • 87
    • 0040607489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Greenawalt, "Free Speech Justifications." As Greenawalt warns, however, we should be wary of strategies that attempt to eliminate certain reasons for free speech by showing that they are "applicable to things other than speech" since a "reason that applies to other subjects may apply with special intensity to speech; various reasons may coalesce in a unique way with respect to speech" (p. 126).
    • Free Speech Justifications
    • Greenawalt1
  • 88
    • 85034185428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This argument has been given by R. Dworkin, Scanlon, Richards, Fried, Strauss, Baker, Redish, Meyers, and Nagel. See references in n. 4
    • This argument has been given by R. Dworkin, Scanlon, Richards, Fried, Strauss, Baker, Redish, Meyers, and Nagel. See references in n. 4.
  • 89
    • 0040607489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Greenawalt notes that not all versions of the argument from autonomy are non-consequentialist in nature, although his classification of these versions differs from my own. For example, he considers Richards to be a proponent of a consequentialist version, whereas I place him in the nonconsequentialist camp, since he claims to derive the right to free speech from a moral right to autonomy which functions as a side constraint on governmental interference. Greenawalt, "Free Speech Justifications," pp. 143-45.
    • Free Speech Justifications , pp. 143-145
    • Greenawalt1
  • 90
    • 85034171394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, p. 222
    • Cohen, p. 222.
  • 91
    • 85034167072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
    • Ibid.
  • 92
    • 84935597626 scopus 로고
    • The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good
    • For the classic discussion of the distinction between "the good" and "right," see John Rawls, "The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good," Philosophy and Public Affairs 17 (1988): 251-76.
    • (1988) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.17 , pp. 251-276
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 93
    • 5944263605 scopus 로고
    • Personal Autonomy and the Paradox of Feminine Socialization
    • See Christman, ed., for an insightful overview of the field and a collection of articles representing a wide range of positions except, unfortunately, feminist theories of autonomy. Feminist accounts include Diana T. Meyers, "Personal Autonomy and the Paradox of Feminine Socialization," Journal of Philosophy 84 (1987): 619-828,
    • (1987) Journal of Philosophy , vol.84 , pp. 619-828
    • Meyers, D.T.1
  • 95
    • 0038671056 scopus 로고
    • Second Persons
    • Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press
    • Lorraine Code, "Second Persons," in What Can She Know? (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1991), pp. 71-109;
    • (1991) What Can She Know? , pp. 71-109
    • Code, L.1
  • 96
    • 0002516455 scopus 로고
    • Reconceiving Autonomy: Sources, Thoughts, and Possibilities
    • Jennifer Nedelsky, "Reconceiving Autonomy: Sources, Thoughts, and Possibilities," Yale Journal of Law and Feminism 1 (1989): 7-36;
    • (1989) Yale Journal of Law and Feminism , vol.1 , pp. 7-36
    • Nedelsky, J.1
  • 97
    • 85050524557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Autonomy and Social Relationships: Rethinking the Feminist Critique
    • ed. Diana T. Meyers Boulder, Colo.: Westview
    • Marilyn Freidman, "Autonomy and Social Relationships: Rethinking the Feminist Critique," in Feminists Rethink the Self, ed. Diana T. Meyers (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1997), pp. 40-61.
    • (1997) Feminists Rethink the Self , pp. 40-61
    • Freidman, M.1
  • 98
    • 26444578953 scopus 로고
    • Harm to Self
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Joel Feinberg doubts that "autonomy" has a single meaning, and holds that it has, instead, these four related meanings. Joel Feinberg, Harm to Self, vol. 3 of The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), pp. 27-51.
    • (1986) The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law , vol.3 , pp. 27-51
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 99
    • 0002068898 scopus 로고
    • Two Concepts of Liberty
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Isaiah Berlin, "Two Concepts of Liberty," in Four Essays on Liberty (New York: Oxford University Press, 1969).
    • (1969) Four Essays on Liberty
    • Berlin, I.1
  • 100
    • 0001376305 scopus 로고
    • Negative and Positive Freedom
    • In describing the following accounts of autonomy, I do not mean to be taken as accepting uncritically Berlin's distinction between negative and positive liberty. See Gerald C. MacCallum, "Negative and Positive Freedom," Philosophical Review 76 (1967): 312-32, for arguments undermining Berlin's distinction.
    • (1967) Philosophical Review , vol.76 , pp. 312-332
    • MacCallum, G.C.1
  • 104
    • 0004239464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin also uses this approach in his review of MacKinnon's Only Words.
    • Only Words
    • MacKinnon1
  • 110
    • 85055308452 scopus 로고
    • Speech Acts and Unspeakable Acts
    • Rae Langton has given a perceptive analysis of MacKinnon's claim that pornography silences women, thereby depriving them of their free speech rights, in "Speech Acts and Unspeakable Acts," Philosophy and Public Affairs 22 (1993): 293-330.
    • (1993) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.22 , pp. 293-330
  • 111
    • 84930557953 scopus 로고
    • Whose Right? Ronald Dworkin, Women, and Pornographers
    • See also Rae Langton's "Whose Right? Ronald Dworkin, Women, and Pornographers," Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (1990): 311-59, in which she argues that given the conflict posed by pornography between liberty and equality, Dworkin's own account of liberal equality can be used to justify restrictions on pornography.
    • (1990) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.19 , pp. 311-359
    • Langton, R.1
  • 112
    • 0039948325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, "A Theory of Freedom of Expression," p. 213. (Although Scanlon calls this "the Millian Principle," it owes more to Kant than to Mill.)
    • A Theory of Freedom of Expression , pp. 213
    • Scanlon1
  • 113
    • 84935413686 scopus 로고
    • The Id, the Ego, and Equal Protection: Reckoning with Unconscious Racism
    • Matsuda et al.; Lederer and Delgado, eds.
    • See Matsuda et al.; Lederer and Delgado, eds.; and Charles R. Lawrence III, "The Id, the Ego, and Equal Protection: Reckoning with Unconscious Racism" Stanford Law Review 39 (1987): 317-88.
    • (1987) Stanford Law Review , vol.39 , pp. 317-388
    • Lawrence III, C.R.1
  • 114
    • 84935413686 scopus 로고
    • The Id, the Ego, and Equal Protection: Reckoning with Unconscious Racism
    • Charles R. Lawrence III, The Id, the Ego, and Equal Protection: Reckoning with Unconscious Racism Stanford Law Review 39 (1987): 317-88. Ibid.
    • (1987) Stanford Law Review , vol.39 , pp. 317-388
    • Lawrence III, C.R.1
  • 116
    • 0346044952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Social Norms and Social Roles
    • Beauharnais v. People of the State of Illinois, 343 U.S. at 263. See also Cass R. Sunstein, "Social Norms and Social Roles" Columbia Law Review 96 (1996): 903-68, for a discussion of the ways social norms, meanings, and roles, constructed largely through speech, affect our views about and actions toward others.
    • (1996) Columbia Law Review , vol.96 , pp. 903-968
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 117
    • 0004140212 scopus 로고
    • New York: Pantheon
    • Victim blaming is a common feature of our society, perhaps because of a deep-seated, if irrational, belief that we live in a basically just world in which people get what they deserve. See William Ryan, Blaming the Victim (New York: Pantheon, 1971);
    • (1971) Blaming the Victim
    • Ryan, W.1
  • 120
    • 0347728836 scopus 로고
    • Freedom of Expression and Categories of Expression
    • In a later article, he employed a revised autonomy account to argue against restrictions on hate speech (as in the proposed Skokie march) and pornography. See Thomas Scanlon, "Freedom of Expression and Categories of Expression," University of Pittsburgh Law Review 40 (1979): 519-50. This revised account will be discussed next.
    • (1979) University of Pittsburgh Law Review , vol.40 , pp. 519-550
    • Scanlon, T.1
  • 121
    • 85034164664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stone, Epstein, and Sunstein, eds.
    • Nagel, p. 96. Nagel points out that his autonomy defense of free speech "is close to the argument Scanlon offers for his principle of free expression, except that his argument goes through the conditions of legitimacy in the exercise of state power, and its conclusion is a limit on legal restrictions of expression rather than a general moral right" (p. 97). Nagel argues that the right to free speech is a general moral right, that is, a universal human right. Nagel still owes the skeptic, however, an argument for why the right to free speech should be considered to be a universal human right. Fried has also argued against restrictions on hate speech and pornography by appealing to autonomy. In a recent article he states, "Freedom of expression is properly based on autonomy: the Kantian right of each individual to be treated as an end in himself, an equal sovereign citizen of the kingdom of ends with a right to the greatest liberty compatible with the like liberties of all others." Charles Fried, "The New First Amendment Jurisprudence: A Threat to Liberty," in Stone, Epstein, and Sunstein, eds., p. 223.
    • The New First Amendment Jurisprudence: A Threat to Liberty , pp. 223
    • Fried, C.1
  • 122
    • 0039948325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is not entirely clear from the article just what Fried means by "autonomy," but a plausible interpretation is that he has in mind something like the account Scanlon gives in "A Theory of Freedom of Expression."
    • A Theory of Freedom of Expression
    • Scanlon1
  • 123
    • 34248528020 scopus 로고
    • Scanlon on Freedom of Expression
    • Robert Amdur, "Scanlon on Freedom of Expression," Philosophy and Public Affairs 9 (1980): 290.
    • (1980) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.9 , pp. 290
    • Amdur, R.1
  • 128
    • 0010060869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Greenawalt, Speech, Crime, and the Uses of Language, p. 115. See also pp. 32-33 and 265. Amdur makes a similar point in arguing that "autonomous citizens, deciding whether to grant the state authority to regulate thought and discussion, would not only think of themselves as potential speakers and listeners, examining different views and deciding what to believe and when to obey the law. They would also think of themselves as potential victims of harms brought about by acts of expression." Amdur argues persuasively that rational, autonomous individuals would not "demand anything as strict as the Millian principle." See Amdur, p. 299.
    • Speech, Crime, and the Uses of Language , pp. 115
    • Greenawalt1
  • 131
    • 1542451987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, "Freedom of Expression and Categories of Expression," p. 533. Richard H. Fallon calls this concept of autonomy "descriptive autonomy." The accounts (1-3) above would presumably be classified as accounts of "ascriptive autonomy." According to Fallon, "Ascriptive autonomy - the autonomy that we ascribe to ourselves and others as the foundation of a right to make self-regarding decisions - is a moral entailment of personhood," whereas "descriptive autonomy refers to the actual condition of persons and views autonomy as partial and contingent" (p. 876).
    • Freedom of Expression and Categories of Expression , pp. 533
    • Scanlon1
  • 132
    • 84937306799 scopus 로고
    • Two Senses of Autonomy
    • Richard H. Fallon, "Two Senses of Autonomy," Stanford Law Review 46 (1994): 875-905. As I argue in this article, there are more varieties of autonomy invoked in the free speech literature than just these two. Furthermore, I question whether any defense of "ascriptive autonomy" could be given that did not refer to the more fundamental value of "descriptive autonomy."
    • (1994) Stanford Law Review , vol.46 , pp. 875-905
    • Fallon, R.H.1
  • 134
    • 85034177227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berlin
    • Berlin.
  • 135
    • 0346275693 scopus 로고
    • Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Harry Frankfurt, "Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person," in The Importance of What We Care About (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988), p. 12. Although Scanlon himself does not invoke Frankfurt's account of autonomy, it is the position in the philosophical literature on autonomy that appears to be closest to the view Scanlon invokes in this later article on free speech. It may be of some interest to note that Frankfurt himself has commented (in conversations during the spring of 1995) that he does not think his account of autonomy can be used to defend free speech.
    • (1988) The Importance of What We Care about , pp. 12
    • Frankfurt, H.1
  • 136
    • 85034158750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For example, Scanlon's account of autonomy.
  • 138
    • 85034188978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Three Concepts of Free Action," "Identification and Externality," and "Identification and Wholeheartedness,"
    • See also Harry Frankfurt, "Three Concepts of Free Action," "Identification and Externality," and "Identification and Wholeheartedness," all in The Importance of What We Care About.
    • The Importance of What We Care about
    • Frankfurt, H.1
  • 139
    • 0004238267 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Gerald Dworkin, The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988). See pp. 15-17 for his reasons for rejecting the endorsement account.
    • (1988) The Theory and Practice of Autonomy
    • Dworkin, G.1
  • 142
    • 85034196605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strauss
    • Strauss.
  • 143
    • 85034197434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is a somewhat misleading objection to Strauss, since he does present an argument of sorts, although I do not think it is successful. He argues along Kantian lines that restricting speech classified as "persuasion" (i.e., speech appealing to reason) violates autonomy in the same way that lying does, but I am not persuaded by his claim that only governmental, and not private, restrictions on speech violate autonomy in this way.
  • 144
    • 0039948325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, "A Theory of Freedom of Expression," p. 216. Although Scanlon makes this point in this earlier article, it also applies to the view defended in his later article.
    • A Theory of Freedom of Expression , pp. 216
    • Scanlon1
  • 145
    • 85034199641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In one passage of "Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person," Frankfurt acknowledges that "when an agent is aware that there are certain things he is not free to do, this doubtless affects his desires and limits the range of choices he can make" (p. 20). Elsewhere, however, he describes his view of freedom of the will (what I and others call his account of "autonomy") in an ahistorical manner which does not take into account the conditions on the formation of first order desires and second-order desires and volitions. For example, on p. 22, he asks us to suppose that someone "enjoys both freedom of action and freedom of the will. Then he is not only free to do what he wants to do; he is also free to want what he wants to want. It seems to me that he has, in that case, all the freedom it is possible to desire or to conceive." On this account of autonomy, even a woman confined to a harem all her life, with no awareness of - and no desire for - any alternative kind of existence, must be considered to have "all the freedom it is possible to desire or to conceive."
  • 146
    • 85034201192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • G. Dworkin
    • G. Dworkin.
  • 148
    • 85077300914 scopus 로고
    • Access, Enablement, and the First Amendment
    • ed. Diana T. Meyers and Kenneth Kipnis Boulder, Colo.: Westview
    • Virginia Held, "Access, Enablement, and the First Amendment," Philosophical Dimensions of the Constitution, ed. Diana T. Meyers and Kenneth Kipnis (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1988), pp. 158-79;
    • (1988) Philosophical Dimensions of the Constitution , pp. 158-179
    • Held, V.1
  • 149
    • 84928460466 scopus 로고
    • Foundations and Limits of Freedom of the Press
    • Judith Lichtenberg, "Foundations and Limits of Freedom of the Press," Philosophy and Public Affairs 16 (1987): 329-55.
    • (1987) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.16 , pp. 329-355
    • Lichtenberg, J.1
  • 150
    • 85034191717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an argument that more choice is not always better than less, see G. Dworkin, pp. 62-81
    • For an argument that more choice is not always better than less, see G. Dworkin, pp. 62-81.
  • 151
    • 0344498981 scopus 로고
    • Conceptions of Democracy in American Constitutional Argument: The Case of Pornography Regulation
    • For a discussion of the ways in which private pressures can constrain speech as effectively as governmental regulation, see Frank Michelman, "Conceptions of Democracy in American Constitutional Argument: The Case of Pornography Regulation," Tennessee Law Review 56 (1989): 291-319.
    • (1989) Tennessee Law Review , vol.56 , pp. 291-319
    • Michelman, F.1
  • 154
    • 84924265956 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • C. Edwin Baker discusses the seriously distorting effects of advertising on access to speech in Advertising and a Democratic Press (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1994).
    • (1994) Advertising and a Democratic Press
    • Baker, C.E.1
  • 155
    • 85034170776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. at 630-61, (Holmes, J., dissenting) (emphases added). Holmes's claim that the principle of free speech embodies "freedom for the thought we hate" (United States v. Schwimmer, 279 U.S. 644, 655 [1929] [Holmes, J., dissenting]) also suggests an absence of agency behind the instilling and shaping of thoughts, in addition to asserting that it is thoughts rather than (or along with) their expressions that are protected by the principle of free speech.
  • 159
    • 85034202346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For discussions of how hate speech can disorder reason, see the articles in Matsuda et al.
  • 163
    • 3142513733 scopus 로고
    • Speech Acts and Pornography
    • ed. Susan Dwyer Belmont, Mass.: Wadsworth
    • Jennifer Hornsby, "Speech Acts and Pornography," in The Problem of Pornography, ed. Susan Dwyer (Belmont, Mass.: Wadsworth, 1995), pp. 220-32.
    • (1995) The Problem of Pornography , pp. 220-232
    • Hornsby, J.1
  • 164
    • 85034168785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Baker
    • Baker.
  • 165
    • 85034189764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Redish
    • Redish.
  • 166
    • 85034167323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the numerous examples in Matsuda et al.
    • See the numerous examples in Matsuda et al.
  • 167
    • 77955986377 scopus 로고
    • Autonomy and Personal History
    • For defenses of this kind of account of autonomy, see John Christman, "Autonomy and Personal History," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (1991): 1-24;
    • (1991) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.21 , pp. 1-24
    • Christman, J.1
  • 168
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986);
    • (1986) The Morality of Freedom
    • Raz, J.1
  • 170
    • 85034191927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Personal Autonomy and the Paradox of Feminine Socialization
    • Meyers, "Personal Autonomy and the Paradox of Feminine Socialization," and Self, Society, and Personal Choice; Code; Nedelsky; and Friedman. This concept of autonomy has not, however, been explicitly discussed in the free speech literature, although Meyers suggests, in "Rights in Collision," that the right to free speech is grounded in the combined values of autonomy (presumably of this variety, since this is the account she defends elsewhere) and democracy.
    • Self, Society, and Personal Choice
    • Meyers1
  • 171
    • 0004266765 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Jon Elster, Sour Grapes (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1983);
    • (1983) Sour Grapes
    • Elster, J.1
  • 172
    • 0004274013 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • Amartya Sen, Inequality Reexamined (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1992). See p. 55, where he discusses the effects of entrenched inequalities and deprivations on preferences.
    • (1992) Inequality Reexamined , pp. 55
    • Sen, A.1
  • 173
    • 84933492590 scopus 로고
    • Conceptions of Choice and Conceptions of Autonomy
    • See also Meir Dan-Cohen, "Conceptions of Choice and Conceptions of Autonomy," Ethics 102 (1992): 221-43.
    • (1992) Ethics , vol.102 , pp. 221-243
    • Dan-Cohen, M.1
  • 174
    • 0010866168 scopus 로고
    • New York: World
    • This example comes from Simone de Beauvoir's memoirs, in which she recalled arguments she had with Jean-Paul Sartre in 1940 about his account of freedom as an active transcendence of one's situation. She had maintained that not every situation offered the same scope for freedom: "what sort of transcendence could a woman shut up in a harem achieve?" Simone de Beauvoir, The Prime of Life (New York: World, 1962), p. 346.
    • (1962) The Prime of Life , pp. 346
    • De Beauvoir, S.1
  • 175
    • 0039316362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Sunstein puts it, "The notion of autonomy should refer . . . to decisions reached with a full and vivid awareness of available opportunities, with reference to all relevant information, and without illegitimate or excessive constraints on the process of preference formation." Sunstein, "Preference and Politics," p. 11.
    • Preference and Politics , pp. 11
    • Sunstein1
  • 176
    • 85034180139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As Raz argues, "If having an autonomous life is an ultimate value, then having a sufficient range of acceptable options is of intrinsic value, for it is constitutive of an autonomous life that it is lived in circumstances where acceptable alternatives are present." Raz, p. 205. See also pp. 373-80.
  • 177
    • 67649471004 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Relational Autonomy and Freedom of Expression
    • ed. Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar (New York: Oxford University Press, in press)
    • For a defense of this account of autonomy and an application of it to free speech issues, see Susan J. Brison, "Relational Autonomy and Freedom of Expression," in Relational Autonomy:Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self, ed. Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar (New York: Oxford University Press, in press).
    • Relational Autonomy:Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self
    • Brison, S.J.1
  • 178
    • 84928460367 scopus 로고
    • Why the State?
    • Owen Fiss, in arguing for a more activist role for the government in the regulation of speech, urges us to "begin with the fact of state intervention in economic matters, and then use that historical experience to understand why the state might have a role to play in furthering free speech values." See Owen Fiss, "Why the State?" Harvard Law Review 100 (1987): 781-94, p. 783.
    • (1987) Harvard Law Review , vol.100 , pp. 781-794
    • Fiss, O.1
  • 179
    • 0346709706 scopus 로고
    • The Parity of the Economic Marketplace
    • Aaron Director, "The Parity of the Economic Marketplace," Journal of Law and Economics 7 (1964): 1-10, p. 5.
    • (1964) Journal of Law and Economics , vol.7 , pp. 1-10
    • Director, A.1
  • 180
    • 0040526113 scopus 로고
    • The Economics of the First Amendment: The Market for Goods and the Market for Ideas
    • See also R. H. Coase, "The Economics of the First Amendment: The Market for Goods and the Market for Ideas," American Economic Review 64 (1974): 384-91.
    • (1974) American Economic Review , vol.64 , pp. 384-391
    • Coase, R.H.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.