메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 107, Issue 2, 1997, Pages 226-249

Self-respect: Moral, emotional, political

(1)  Dillon, Robin S a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0002169159     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/233719     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (112)

References (99)
  • 2
    • 0006253689 scopus 로고
    • How to lose your self-respect
    • To be sure, not all who lack self-respect feel miserable as a result; I focus on that sort of experience for reasons that will become clear. For other ways of lacking self-respect, see my "How to Lose Your Self-Respect," American Philosophical Quarterly 29 (1992): 125-39.
    • (1992) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.29 , pp. 125-139
  • 3
    • 84924172853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The account set out in this section extends the account I have developed in earlier essays. See ibid., "Respect and Care: Toward Moral Integration," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1992): 105-32, "Toward a Feminist Conception of Self-Respect," Hypatia 7 (1992): 52-69, and my "Introduction," in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect, ed. Robin S. Dillon (New York: Routledge, 1995), pp. 1-49.
    • American Philosophical Quarterly
  • 4
    • 84954636040 scopus 로고
    • The account set out in this section extends the account I have developed in earlier essays. See ibid., "Respect and Care: Toward Moral Integration," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1992): 105-32, "Toward a Feminist Conception of Self-Respect," Hypatia 7 (1992): 52-69, and my "Introduction," in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect, ed. Robin S. Dillon (New York: Routledge, 1995), pp. 1-49.
    • (1992) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.22 , pp. 105-132
  • 5
    • 84946384599 scopus 로고
    • Toward a feminist conception of self-respect
    • The account set out in this section extends the account I have developed in earlier essays. See ibid., "Respect and Care: Toward Moral Integration," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1992): 105-32, "Toward a Feminist Conception of Self-Respect," Hypatia 7 (1992): 52-69, and my "Introduction," in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect, ed. Robin S. Dillon (New York: Routledge, 1995), pp. 1-49.
    • (1992) Hypatia , vol.7 , pp. 52-69
  • 6
    • 0039195524 scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • ed. Robin S. Dillon New York: Routledge
    • The account set out in this section extends the account I have developed in earlier essays. See ibid., "Respect and Care: Toward Moral Integration," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1992): 105-32, "Toward a Feminist Conception of Self-Respect," Hypatia 7 (1992): 52-69, and my "Introduction," in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect, ed. Robin S. Dillon (New York: Routledge, 1995), pp. 1-49.
    • (1995) Dignity, Character, and Self-respect , pp. 1-49
  • 7
    • 84963062239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Self-respect
    • Elizabeth Telfer, "Self-Respect," Philosophical Quarterly 18 (1968): 114-21, reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1968) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.18 , pp. 114-121
    • Telfer, E.1
  • 8
    • 84963062239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reprinted
    • Elizabeth Telfer, "Self-Respect," Philosophical Quarterly 18 (1968): 114-21, reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • Dignity, Character, and Self-respect
  • 9
    • 85033114897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that not all that is encompassed by the notion of worth is included in the domain of self-respect, but only morally significant worth. This, I would argue, is one of the differences between self-respect and self-esteem. For the purposes of this paper, however, I leave aside the analysis of "morally significant worth." And for simplicity, I refer in the rest of the paper simply to 'worth'.
  • 10
    • 85033118453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I use both prepositions, despite the awkwardness, to convey the idea that self-respect encompasses both a more objective perspective on or stance toward one's self and the more intimate experience of living with oneself. I use both objects to express the idea that respecting oneself is also a matter of how one understands one's place in the world and one's relation to other things, including other people, as well as how one lives with others.
  • 11
    • 0041695440 scopus 로고
    • Servility and self-respect
    • The idea that there are different kinds of self-respect is common in the philosophical literature. See, e.g., Telfer; Thomas E. Hill, Jr., "Servility and Self-Respect," Monist 57 (1973): 87-104, and "Self-Respect Reconsidered," in Respect for Persons, Tulane Studies in Philosophy, vol. 31, ed. O. H. Green (New Orleans: Tulane University Press, 1985), pp. 128-37; Stephen J. Massey, "Is Self-Respect a Moral or a Psychological Concept?" Ethics 93 (1983): 246-61. In what follows I develop the distinction drawn by Stephen Darwall in "Two Kinds of Respect," Ethics 88 (1977): 34-49. All of these essays are reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1973) Monist , vol.57 , pp. 87-104
    • Telfer, T.E.1    Hill, Jr.2
  • 12
    • 85033122867 scopus 로고
    • Self-respect reconsidered
    • ed. O. H. Green New Orleans: Tulane University Press
    • The idea that there are different kinds of self-respect is common in the philosophical literature. See, e.g., Telfer; Thomas E. Hill, Jr., "Servility and Self-Respect," Monist 57 (1973): 87-104, and "Self-Respect Reconsidered," in Respect for Persons, Tulane Studies in Philosophy, vol. 31, ed. O. H. Green (New Orleans: Tulane University Press, 1985), pp. 128-37; Stephen J. Massey, "Is Self-Respect a Moral or a Psychological Concept?" Ethics 93 (1983): 246-61. In what follows I develop the distinction drawn by Stephen Darwall in "Two Kinds of Respect," Ethics 88 (1977): 34-49. All of these essays are reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1985) Respect for Persons, Tulane Studies in Philosophy , vol.31 , pp. 128-137
  • 13
    • 0001690704 scopus 로고
    • Is self-respect a moral or a psychological concept?
    • The idea that there are different kinds of self-respect is common in the philosophical literature. See, e.g., Telfer; Thomas E. Hill, Jr., "Servility and Self-Respect," Monist 57 (1973): 87-104, and "Self-Respect Reconsidered," in Respect for Persons, Tulane Studies in Philosophy, vol. 31, ed. O. H. Green (New Orleans: Tulane University Press, 1985), pp. 128-37; Stephen J. Massey, "Is Self-Respect a Moral or a Psychological Concept?" Ethics 93 (1983): 246-61. In what follows I develop the distinction drawn by Stephen Darwall in "Two Kinds of Respect," Ethics 88 (1977): 34-49. All of these essays are reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1983) Ethics , vol.93 , pp. 246-261
    • Massey, S.J.1
  • 14
    • 83455240567 scopus 로고
    • Two kinds of respect
    • The idea that there are different kinds of self-respect is common in the philosophical literature. See, e.g., Telfer; Thomas E. Hill, Jr., "Servility and Self-Respect," Monist 57 (1973): 87-104, and "Self-Respect Reconsidered," in Respect for Persons, Tulane Studies in Philosophy, vol. 31, ed. O. H. Green (New Orleans: Tulane University Press, 1985), pp. 128-37; Stephen J. Massey, "Is Self-Respect a Moral or a Psychological Concept?" Ethics 93 (1983): 246-61. In what follows I develop the distinction drawn by Stephen Darwall in "Two Kinds of Respect," Ethics 88 (1977): 34-49. All of these essays are reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1977) Ethics , vol.88 , pp. 34-49
    • Darwall, S.1
  • 15
    • 85033119780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Respect and care: Toward moral integration
    • Darwall. Note that respect grounded in status worth is but one of several species of recognition respect, not all of which have correlative forms of self-respect, and that the different sources of status worth yield different configurations of recognition self-respect; see my "Respect and Care: Toward Moral Integration." In what follows, I concentrate on recognition respect for oneself as a person. Note also that, inasmuch as the concepts of respect and self-respect rest on the essentially contested concepts of personhood and the morally significant worth of persons, different conceptions of persons and their worth yield different conceptions of respect and self-respect. In this paper, I focus on the conceptions that have dominated contemporary Western democratic society and hence contemporary Western philosophical discussions of self-respect. In "Toward a Feminist Conception of Self-Respect," I explore the ramifications of transtheoretic variations in the conception of personhood. For an exploration of differences between Western and Indian ways of conceptualizing persons, worth, and self-respect, see Koyeli Gosh-Dastidar, "Respect for Persons and Self-Respect: Western and Indian," Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research 5 (1987): 83-93.
    • Toward a Feminist Conception of Self-respect
    • Darwall1
  • 16
    • 0040974378 scopus 로고
    • Respect for persons and self-respect: Western and Indian
    • Darwall. Note that respect grounded in status worth is but one of several species of recognition respect, not all of which have correlative forms of self-respect, and that the different sources of status worth yield different configurations of recognition self-respect; see my "Respect and Care: Toward Moral Integration." In what follows, I concentrate on recognition respect for oneself as a person. Note also that, inasmuch as the concepts of respect and self-respect rest on the essentially contested concepts of personhood and the morally significant worth of persons, different conceptions of persons and their worth yield different conceptions of respect and self-respect. In this paper, I focus on the conceptions that have dominated contemporary Western democratic society and hence contemporary Western philosophical discussions of self-respect. In "Toward a Feminist Conception of Self-Respect," I explore the ramifications of transtheoretic variations in the conception of personhood. For an exploration of differences between Western and Indian ways of conceptualizing persons, worth, and self-respect, see Koyeli Gosh-Dastidar, "Respect for Persons and Self-Respect: Western and Indian," Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research 5 (1987): 83-93.
    • (1987) Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research , vol.5 , pp. 83-93
    • Gosh-Dastidar, K.1
  • 17
    • 84925928237 scopus 로고
    • The nature of respect
    • I take this term from Stephen D. Hudson, "The Nature of Respect," Social Theory and Practice 6 (1980): 69-90. Darwall's term is 'appraisal self-respect'.
    • (1980) Social Theory and Practice , vol.6 , pp. 69-90
    • Hudson, S.D.1
  • 18
    • 0038592320 scopus 로고
    • trans. Mary Gregor Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press
    • The locus classicus for this view is, of course, Kant: "man regarded as a person . . . is exalted above any price . . . he possesses . . . a dignity (an absolute inner worth) by which he exacts respect for himself from all other rational beings in the world: he can measure himself with every other being in the world and value himself on a footing of equality with them"; Doctrine of Virtue: Part II of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1964), p. 99. See also Hill, "Servility and Self-Respect"; Laurence Thomas, "Self-Respect: Theory and Practice," in Philosophy Born of Struggle: Anthology of Afro-American Philosophy from 1917, ed. Leonard Harris (Dubuque, Iowa: Kendall/Hunt, 1983), pp. 174-89; and Bernard R. Boxill, "Self-Respect and Protest," Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (1976): 58-69. The latter three are reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1964) Doctrine of Virtue: Part II of the Metaphysic of Morals , pp. 99
  • 19
    • 33749308817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The locus classicus for this view is, of course, Kant: "man regarded as a person . . . is exalted above any price . . . he possesses . . . a dignity (an absolute inner worth) by which he exacts respect for himself from all other rational beings in the world: he can measure himself with every other being in the world and value himself on a footing of equality with them"; Doctrine of Virtue: Part II of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1964), p. 99. See also Hill, "Servility and Self-Respect"; Laurence Thomas, "Self-Respect: Theory and Practice," in Philosophy Born of Struggle: Anthology of Afro-American Philosophy from 1917, ed. Leonard Harris (Dubuque, Iowa: Kendall/Hunt, 1983), pp. 174-89; and Bernard R. Boxill, "Self-Respect and Protest," Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (1976): 58-69. The latter three are reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • Servility and Self-respect
    • Hill1
  • 20
    • 0040380125 scopus 로고
    • Self-respect: Theory and practice
    • ed. Leonard Harris Dubuque, Iowa: Kendall/Hunt
    • The locus classicus for this view is, of course, Kant: "man regarded as a person . . . is exalted above any price . . . he possesses . . . a dignity (an absolute inner worth) by which he exacts respect for himself from all other rational beings in the world: he can measure himself with every other being in the world and value himself on a footing of equality with them"; Doctrine of Virtue: Part II of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1964), p. 99. See also Hill, "Servility and Self-Respect"; Laurence Thomas, "Self-Respect: Theory and Practice," in Philosophy Born of Struggle: Anthology of Afro-American Philosophy from 1917, ed. Leonard Harris (Dubuque, Iowa: Kendall/Hunt, 1983), pp. 174-89; and Bernard R. Boxill, "Self-Respect and Protest," Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (1976): 58-69. The latter three are reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1983) Philosophy Born of Struggle: Anthology of Afro-American Philosophy from 1917 , pp. 174-189
    • Thomas, L.1
  • 21
    • 84925902352 scopus 로고
    • Self-respect and protest
    • The locus classicus for this view is, of course, Kant: "man regarded as a person . . . is exalted above any price . . . he possesses . . . a dignity (an absolute inner worth) by which he exacts respect for himself from all other rational beings in the world: he can measure himself with every other being in the world and value himself on a footing of equality with them"; Doctrine of Virtue: Part II of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1964), p. 99. See also Hill, "Servility and Self-Respect"; Laurence Thomas, "Self-Respect: Theory and Practice," in Philosophy Born of Struggle: Anthology of Afro-American Philosophy from 1917, ed. Leonard Harris (Dubuque, Iowa: Kendall/Hunt, 1983), pp. 174-89; and Bernard R. Boxill, "Self-Respect and Protest," Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (1976): 58-69. The latter three are reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1976) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.6 , pp. 58-69
    • Boxill, B.R.1
  • 22
    • 85033121967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The latter three are reprinted
    • The locus classicus for this view is, of course, Kant: "man regarded as a person . . . is exalted above any price . . . he possesses . . . a dignity (an absolute inner worth) by which he exacts respect for himself from all other rational beings in the world: he can measure himself with every other being in the world and value himself on a footing of equality with them"; Doctrine of Virtue: Part II of the Metaphysic of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1964), p. 99. See also Hill, "Servility and Self-Respect"; Laurence Thomas, "Self-Respect: Theory and Practice," in Philosophy Born of Struggle: Anthology of Afro-American Philosophy from 1917, ed. Leonard Harris (Dubuque, Iowa: Kendall/Hunt, 1983), pp. 174-89; and Bernard R. Boxill, "Self-Respect and Protest," Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (1976): 58-69. The latter three are reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • Dignity, Character, and Self-respect
  • 23
    • 0009234636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, chap. 5
    • For discussions of resentment and self-respect, see, e.g., Michael Pritchard, On Becoming Responsible (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1989), chap. 5, which draws on Joseph Butler's Sermon 8, "Upon Resentment" (in Fifteen Sermons, ed. T. A. Roberts [1722; reprint, London: S.P.C.K., 1970] and on Peter Strawson's "Freedom and Resentment" (in Freedom, Resentment, and Other Essays [London: Methuen, 1974]); and Laurence Thomas, Living Morally (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1989), chap. 6.
    • (1989) On Becoming Responsible
    • Pritchard, M.1
  • 24
    • 0039195518 scopus 로고
    • Upon resentment
    • ed. T. A. Roberts
    • For discussions of resentment and self-respect, see, e.g., Michael Pritchard, On Becoming Responsible (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1989), chap. 5, which draws on Joseph Butler's Sermon 8, "Upon Resentment" (in Fifteen Sermons, ed. T. A. Roberts [1722; reprint, London: S.P.C.K., 1970] and on Peter Strawson's "Freedom and Resentment" (in Freedom, Resentment, and Other Essays [London: Methuen, 1974]); and Laurence Thomas, Living Morally (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1989), chap. 6.
    • (1722) Fifteen Sermons
    • Butler, J.1
  • 25
    • 0003363646 scopus 로고
    • Freedom and resentment
    • London: Methuen
    • For discussions of resentment and self-respect, see, e.g., Michael Pritchard, On Becoming Responsible (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1989), chap. 5, which draws on Joseph Butler's Sermon 8, "Upon Resentment" (in Fifteen Sermons, ed. T. A. Roberts [1722; reprint, London: S.P.C.K., 1970] and on Peter Strawson's "Freedom and Resentment" (in Freedom, Resentment, and Other Essays [London: Methuen, 1974]); and Laurence Thomas, Living Morally (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1989), chap. 6.
    • (1970) Freedom, Resentment, and Other Essays
    • Strawson, P.1
  • 26
    • 0039787874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philadelphia: Temple University Press, chap. 6
    • For discussions of resentment and self-respect, see, e.g., Michael Pritchard, On Becoming Responsible (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1989), chap. 5, which draws on Joseph Butler's Sermon 8, "Upon Resentment" (in Fifteen Sermons, ed. T. A. Roberts [1722; reprint, London: S.P.C.K., 1970] and on Peter Strawson's "Freedom and Resentment" (in Freedom, Resentment, and Other Essays [London: Methuen, 1974]); and Laurence Thomas, Living Morally (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1989), chap. 6.
    • (1989) Living Morally
    • Thomas, L.1
  • 27
    • 85033099536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I discuss this more fully in "How to Lose Your Self-Respect." Note that it is possible for someone to have a mistaken view of her place in the moral world or care little about how others treat her and yet to have a keen sense of her other responsibilities and fulfill them out of respect for herself. That is, it is possible to respect oneself as an agent without respecting oneself as an equal. Massey describes such an individual in "Is Self-Respect a Moral or a Psychological Concept?"
  • 28
    • 0004031730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, chap. 3
    • See Gabriele Taylor, Pride, Shame, and Guilt: Emotions of Self-Assessment (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985), chap. 3; and John Deigh, "Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique," Ethics 93 (1983): 225-45, reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1985) Pride, Shame, and Guilt: Emotions of Self-Assessment
    • Taylor, G.1
  • 29
    • 0039195508 scopus 로고
    • Shame and self-esteem: A critique
    • See Gabriele Taylor, Pride, Shame, and Guilt: Emotions of Self-Assessment (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985), chap. 3; and John Deigh, "Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique," Ethics 93 (1983): 225-45, reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1983) Ethics , vol.93 , pp. 225-245
    • Deigh, J.1
  • 30
    • 85033103961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reprinted
    • See Gabriele Taylor, Pride, Shame, and Guilt: Emotions of Self-Assessment (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985), chap. 3; and John Deigh, "Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique," Ethics 93 (1983): 225-45, reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • Dignity, Character, and Self-respect
  • 31
    • 0039195513 scopus 로고
    • ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge Oxford: Clarendon
    • David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford: Clarendon, 1971), p. 620.
    • (1971) A Treatise of Human Nature , pp. 620
    • Hume, D.1
  • 32
    • 84970095958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, pt. 1
    • See, e.g., ibid., bk. 2, pt. 1; Arnold Isenberg, "Natural Pride and Natural Shame," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 10 (1949): 1-24; and Taylor, Pride, Shame, and Guilt, chap. 2. Taylor in fact denies a connection between self-respect and emotional pride, arguing that the connection actually holds between self-esteem and pride. However, while Taylor is right that there is a conceptual difference between self-respect and self-esteem, it is also the case that there is no agreement about precisely what the difference is. I discuss some differences in "Introduction," in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • A Treatise of Human Nature
  • 33
    • 0040974355 scopus 로고
    • Natural pride and natural shame
    • See, e.g., ibid., bk. 2, pt. 1; Arnold Isenberg, "Natural Pride and Natural Shame," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 10 (1949): 1-24; and Taylor, Pride, Shame, and Guilt, chap. 2. Taylor in fact denies a connection between self-respect and emotional pride, arguing that the connection actually holds between self-esteem and pride. However, while Taylor is right that there is a conceptual difference between self-respect and self-esteem, it is also the case that there is no agreement about precisely what the difference is. I discuss some differences in "Introduction," in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1949) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.10 , pp. 1-24
    • Isenberg, A.1
  • 34
    • 0004031730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 2
    • See, e.g., ibid., bk. 2, pt. 1; Arnold Isenberg, "Natural Pride and Natural Shame," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 10 (1949): 1-24; and Taylor, Pride, Shame, and Guilt, chap. 2. Taylor in fact denies a connection between self-respect and emotional pride, arguing that the connection actually holds between self-esteem and pride. However, while Taylor is right that there is a conceptual difference between self-respect and self-esteem, it is also the case that there is no agreement about precisely what the difference is. I discuss some differences in "Introduction," in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • Pride, Shame, and Guilt
    • Taylor1
  • 35
    • 85033106436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • See, e.g., ibid., bk. 2, pt. 1; Arnold Isenberg, "Natural Pride and Natural Shame," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 10 (1949): 1-24; and Taylor, Pride, Shame, and Guilt, chap. 2. Taylor in fact denies a connection between self-respect and emotional pride, arguing that the connection actually holds between self-esteem and pride. However, while Taylor is right that there is a conceptual difference between self-respect and self-esteem, it is also the case that there is no agreement about precisely what the difference is. I discuss some differences in "Introduction," in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • Dignity, Character, and Self-respect
    • Taylor1
  • 36
    • 85033116709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that pride does not always enact evaluative self-respect, for it can be unjustified, nor does it enact only evaluative self-respect, since its possible grounds are wider than quality of character and conduct. Note, too, that normative self-conceptions typically also include criteria of minimum acceptability and that to behave a certain way may not be an achievement but the least one expects of oneself. A positive self-evaluation here yields not pride but contentment or self-acceptance.
  • 37
    • 85033106542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Isenberg; Taylor; Hill, "Self-Respect Reconsidered"; John Deigh, "Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique," and "Guilt and Shame," in Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker (New York: Garland, 1992), pp. 426-28; Sandra Lee Bartky, "Shame and Gender," in her Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression (New York: Routledge, 1990), pp. 83-98; John Kekes, "Shame and Moral Progress," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 13, ed. Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, and Howard K. Wettstein (Notre Dame, Ind.: Notre Dame University Press, 1988); Susan Miller, The Shame Experience (Hillsdale, N.J.: Analytic Press, 1985); and John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 440-46, which is reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • Self-respect Reconsidered
    • Isenberg1    Taylor2    Hill3
  • 38
    • 0039195488 scopus 로고
    • Shame and self-esteem: A critique," and "guilt and shame
    • ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker New York: Garland
    • See Isenberg; Taylor; Hill, "Self-Respect Reconsidered"; John Deigh, "Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique," and "Guilt and Shame," in Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker (New York: Garland, 1992), pp. 426-28; Sandra Lee Bartky, "Shame and Gender," in her Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression (New York: Routledge, 1990), pp. 83-98; John Kekes, "Shame and Moral Progress," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 13, ed. Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, and Howard K. Wettstein (Notre Dame, Ind.: Notre Dame University Press, 1988); Susan Miller, The Shame Experience (Hillsdale, N.J.: Analytic Press, 1985); and John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 440-46, which is reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1992) Encyclopedia of Ethics , pp. 426-428
    • Deigh, J.1
  • 39
    • 0040380104 scopus 로고
    • Shame and gender
    • New York: Routledge
    • See Isenberg; Taylor; Hill, "Self-Respect Reconsidered"; John Deigh, "Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique," and "Guilt and Shame," in Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker (New York: Garland, 1992), pp. 426-28; Sandra Lee Bartky, "Shame and Gender," in her Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression (New York: Routledge, 1990), pp. 83-98; John Kekes, "Shame and Moral Progress," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 13, ed. Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, and Howard K. Wettstein (Notre Dame, Ind.: Notre Dame University Press, 1988); Susan Miller, The Shame Experience (Hillsdale, N.J.: Analytic Press, 1985); and John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 440-46, which is reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1990) Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression , pp. 83-98
    • Bartky, S.L.1
  • 40
    • 84985383264 scopus 로고
    • Shame and moral progress
    • ed. Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, and Howard K. Wettstein Notre Dame, Ind.: Notre Dame University Press
    • See Isenberg; Taylor; Hill, "Self-Respect Reconsidered"; John Deigh, "Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique," and "Guilt and Shame," in Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker (New York: Garland, 1992), pp. 426-28; Sandra Lee Bartky, "Shame and Gender," in her Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression (New York: Routledge, 1990), pp. 83-98; John Kekes, "Shame and Moral Progress," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 13, ed. Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, and Howard K. Wettstein (Notre Dame, Ind.: Notre Dame University Press, 1988); Susan Miller, The Shame Experience (Hillsdale, N.J.: Analytic Press, 1985); and John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 440-46, which is reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1988) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.13
    • Kekes, J.1
  • 41
    • 0004084434 scopus 로고
    • Hillsdale, N.J.: Analytic Press
    • See Isenberg; Taylor; Hill, "Self-Respect Reconsidered"; John Deigh, "Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique," and "Guilt and Shame," in Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker (New York: Garland, 1992), pp. 426-28; Sandra Lee Bartky, "Shame and Gender," in her Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression (New York: Routledge, 1990), pp. 83-98; John Kekes, "Shame and Moral Progress," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 13, ed. Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, and Howard K. Wettstein (Notre Dame, Ind.: Notre Dame University Press, 1988); Susan Miller, The Shame Experience (Hillsdale, N.J.: Analytic Press, 1985); and John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 440-46, which is reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1985) The Shame Experience
    • Miller, S.1
  • 42
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
    • See Isenberg; Taylor; Hill, "Self-Respect Reconsidered"; John Deigh, "Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique," and "Guilt and Shame," in Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker (New York: Garland, 1992), pp. 426-28; Sandra Lee Bartky, "Shame and Gender," in her Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression (New York: Routledge, 1990), pp. 83-98; John Kekes, "Shame and Moral Progress," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 13, ed. Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, and Howard K. Wettstein (Notre Dame, Ind.: Notre Dame University Press, 1988); Susan Miller, The Shame Experience (Hillsdale, N.J.: Analytic Press, 1985); and John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 440-46, which is reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 440-446
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 43
    • 85033103961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reprinted
    • See Isenberg; Taylor; Hill, "Self-Respect Reconsidered"; John Deigh, "Shame and Self-Esteem: A Critique," and "Guilt and Shame," in Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker (New York: Garland, 1992), pp. 426-28; Sandra Lee Bartky, "Shame and Gender," in her Femininity and Domination: Studies in the Phenomenology of Oppression (New York: Routledge, 1990), pp. 83-98; John Kekes, "Shame and Moral Progress," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 13, ed. Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, and Howard K. Wettstein (Notre Dame, Ind.: Notre Dame University Press, 1988); Susan Miller, The Shame Experience (Hillsdale, N.J.: Analytic Press, 1985); and John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 440-46, which is reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • Dignity, Character, and Self-respect
  • 44
    • 85033118578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Isenberg, p. 16. Rawls and Kekes are among those who share this view; Bartky is among those who challenge it.
    • Isenberg1
  • 45
    • 85033116362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I owe this case to Claudia Murphy
    • I owe this case to Claudia Murphy.
  • 46
    • 0040380108 scopus 로고
    • The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence
    • done by the American Association of University Women Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women
    • To be more accurate, damaged self-respect is integrally connected with oppression. The claim that damaged self-respect is a gendered phenomenon requires, of course, more than anecdotal support. There are, however, some difficulties with empirical support. The first is that empirical research is carried on by psychologists, whose term of use is "self-esteem" rather than self-respect. I have argued elsewhere that the two are distinct; however, there is no agreement among psychologists or philosophers about whether there is a distinction and if so what it is. Still, many of the psychological studies I've looked at define "self-esteem" in ways that overlap with self-respect, so it is reasonable to look at that evidence. However, there is reason to worry about gender bias in psychological studies of self-esteem, since the standard definitions and measures (Coopersmith's and Rosenberg's, for example) omit gender considerations and are predicated on a model of the healthy self that is clearly male-biased (Kaschak). Further, empirical research relevant to damaged self-esteem is indirect, through work on shame and on psychopathologies such as depression and eating disorders, both of which are typically analyzed as involving damaged self-worth. There is, however, reason to suspect gender bias (and race bias) in diagnosis of psychopathology. Finally, much empirical work on gender and self-esteem is racially biased, omitting women of color. These methodological concerns are somewhat addressed by looking at studies which are explicitly sensitive to gender and race considerations, and there the evidence is clear. Women with traditionally feminine gender identification are more likely to have low self-esteem than men (Travis). Women are more likely to exceed men on reports of shame (Brody and Hall, Lewis). Women suffer depression at rates two to three times higher than men; the gender difference is consistently confirmed in epidemiological and clinical studies, is not an artifact of reporting, genetics, or hormones, and holds across racial and ethnic lines and cross-culturally (Jack, Russo and Green, Ritter, Matlin, Unger and Crawford, Travis). Ninety to ninety-five percent of those suffering from eating disorders are women. Two-thirds of teen self-mutilators are girls; the etiology is the same as for eating disorders (Orenstein). The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence, done by the American Association of University Women (Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action [Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women, 1991]), found that during adolescence the self-regard of girls drops further than boys' and never catches up; teen girls are much more likely than boys to say they are "not good enough" to achieve their dreams; although girls consistently report lower self-esteem than boys, Latina girls' self-esteem drops much lower than that of Caucasian girls, while the self-esteem of African American girls is higher than that of Caucasian girls though still lower than that of African American boys. All of these studies agree that the best explanation for the findings is that they are the effects on women of living in a sexist society. See Leslie Brody and Judith A. Hall, "Gender and Emotions," in Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland (New York: Guilford, 1993); Dana Jack, "Silencing the Self: The Power of Social Imperatives in Female Depression," in Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective, ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian (New York: Springer, 1987); Ellyn Kaschak, Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience (New York: Basic, 1992); Helen Block Lewis, "The Role of Shame in Depression in Women," in Formanek and Gurian, eds.; Margaret W. Matlin, The Psychology of Women, 2d ed. (Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987); Peggy Orenstein, SchoolGirls: Young Women, Self-Esteem, and the Confidence Gap (New York: Anchor, 1994); Kathleen Y. Ritter, "Depression in Women," in Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling, ed. Ellen Piel Cook (Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association, 1993); Nancy Felipe Russo and Beth L. Green, "Women and Mental Health," in Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories, ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1993); Karen W. Saakvitne and Laurie Anne Pearlman, "The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence against Women on Feminine Identity," in Cook, ed.; Linda Tschirhart Sanford and Mary Ellen Donovan, Women and Self-Esteem (New York: Anchor, 1984); Cheryl Brown Travis, Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1988); and Rhoda Unger and Mary Crawford, Women and Gender: A Feminist Psychology (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • (1991) Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action
    • Jack, R.1    Green, R.2    Matlin, U.3    Crawford, T.4
  • 47
    • 0002436525 scopus 로고
    • Gender and emotions
    • Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland New York: Guilford
    • To be more accurate, damaged self-respect is integrally connected with oppression. The claim that damaged self-respect is a gendered phenomenon requires, of course, more than anecdotal support. There are, however, some difficulties with empirical support. The first is that empirical research is carried on by psychologists, whose term of use is "self-esteem" rather than self-respect. I have argued elsewhere that the two are distinct; however, there is no agreement among psychologists or philosophers about whether there is a distinction and if so what it is. Still, many of the psychological studies I've looked at define "self-esteem" in ways that overlap with self-respect, so it is reasonable to look at that evidence. However, there is reason to worry about gender bias in psychological studies of self-esteem, since the standard definitions and measures (Coopersmith's and Rosenberg's, for example) omit gender considerations and are predicated on a model of the healthy self that is clearly male-biased (Kaschak). Further, empirical research relevant to damaged self-esteem is indirect, through work on shame and on psychopathologies such as depression and eating disorders, both of which are typically analyzed as involving damaged self-worth. There is, however, reason to suspect gender bias (and race bias) in diagnosis of psychopathology. Finally, much empirical work on gender and self-esteem is racially biased, omitting women of color. These methodological concerns are somewhat addressed by looking at studies which are explicitly sensitive to gender and race considerations, and there the evidence is clear. Women with traditionally feminine gender identification are more likely to have low self-esteem than men (Travis). Women are more likely to exceed men on reports of shame (Brody and Hall, Lewis). Women suffer depression at rates two to three times higher than men; the gender difference is consistently confirmed in epidemiological and clinical studies, is not an artifact of reporting, genetics, or hormones, and holds across racial and ethnic lines and cross-culturally (Jack, Russo and Green, Ritter, Matlin, Unger and Crawford, Travis). Ninety to ninety-five percent of those suffering from eating disorders are women. Two-thirds of teen self-mutilators are girls; the etiology is the same as for eating disorders (Orenstein). The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence, done by the American Association of University Women (Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action [Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women, 1991]), found that during adolescence the self-regard of girls drops further than boys' and never catches up; teen girls are much more likely than boys to say they are "not good enough" to achieve their dreams; although girls consistently report lower self-esteem than boys, Latina girls' self-esteem drops much lower than that of Caucasian girls, while the self-esteem of African American girls is higher than that of Caucasian girls though still lower than that of African American boys. All of these studies agree that the best explanation for the findings is that they are the effects on women of living in a sexist society. See Leslie Brody and Judith A. Hall, "Gender and Emotions," in Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland (New York: Guilford, 1993); Dana Jack, "Silencing the Self: The Power of Social Imperatives in Female Depression," in Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective, ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian (New York: Springer, 1987); Ellyn Kaschak, Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience (New York: Basic, 1992); Helen Block Lewis, "The Role of Shame in Depression in Women," in Formanek and Gurian, eds.; Margaret W. Matlin, The Psychology of Women, 2d ed. (Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987); Peggy Orenstein, SchoolGirls: Young Women, Self-Esteem, and the Confidence Gap (New York: Anchor, 1994); Kathleen Y. Ritter, "Depression in Women," in Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling, ed. Ellen Piel Cook (Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association, 1993); Nancy Felipe Russo and Beth L. Green, "Women and Mental Health," in Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories, ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1993); Karen W. Saakvitne and Laurie Anne Pearlman, "The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence against Women on Feminine Identity," in Cook, ed.; Linda Tschirhart Sanford and Mary Ellen Donovan, Women and Self-Esteem (New York: Anchor, 1984); Cheryl Brown Travis, Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1988); and Rhoda Unger and Mary Crawford, Women and Gender: A Feminist Psychology (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • (1993) Handbook of Emotions
    • Brody, L.1    Hall, J.A.2
  • 48
    • 0003026459 scopus 로고
    • Silencing the self: The power of social imperatives in female depression
    • ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian New York: Springer
    • To be more accurate, damaged self-respect is integrally connected with oppression. The claim that damaged self-respect is a gendered phenomenon requires, of course, more than anecdotal support. There are, however, some difficulties with empirical support. The first is that empirical research is carried on by psychologists, whose term of use is "self-esteem" rather than self-respect. I have argued elsewhere that the two are distinct; however, there is no agreement among psychologists or philosophers about whether there is a distinction and if so what it is. Still, many of the psychological studies I've looked at define "self-esteem" in ways that overlap with self-respect, so it is reasonable to look at that evidence. However, there is reason to worry about gender bias in psychological studies of self-esteem, since the standard definitions and measures (Coopersmith's and Rosenberg's, for example) omit gender considerations and are predicated on a model of the healthy self that is clearly male-biased (Kaschak). Further, empirical research relevant to damaged self-esteem is indirect, through work on shame and on psychopathologies such as depression and eating disorders, both of which are typically analyzed as involving damaged self-worth. There is, however, reason to suspect gender bias (and race bias) in diagnosis of psychopathology. Finally, much empirical work on gender and self-esteem is racially biased, omitting women of color. These methodological concerns are somewhat addressed by looking at studies which are explicitly sensitive to gender and race considerations, and there the evidence is clear. Women with traditionally feminine gender identification are more likely to have low self-esteem than men (Travis). Women are more likely to exceed men on reports of shame (Brody and Hall, Lewis). Women suffer depression at rates two to three times higher than men; the gender difference is consistently confirmed in epidemiological and clinical studies, is not an artifact of reporting, genetics, or hormones, and holds across racial and ethnic lines and cross-culturally (Jack, Russo and Green, Ritter, Matlin, Unger and Crawford, Travis). Ninety to ninety-five percent of those suffering from eating disorders are women. Two-thirds of teen self-mutilators are girls; the etiology is the same as for eating disorders (Orenstein). The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence, done by the American Association of University Women (Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action [Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women, 1991]), found that during adolescence the self-regard of girls drops further than boys' and never catches up; teen girls are much more likely than boys to say they are "not good enough" to achieve their dreams; although girls consistently report lower self-esteem than boys, Latina girls' self-esteem drops much lower than that of Caucasian girls, while the self-esteem of African American girls is higher than that of Caucasian girls though still lower than that of African American boys. All of these studies agree that the best explanation for the findings is that they are the effects on women of living in a sexist society. See Leslie Brody and Judith A. Hall, "Gender and Emotions," in Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland (New York: Guilford, 1993); Dana Jack, "Silencing the Self: The Power of Social Imperatives in Female Depression," in Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective, ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian (New York: Springer, 1987); Ellyn Kaschak, Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience (New York: Basic, 1992); Helen Block Lewis, "The Role of Shame in Depression in Women," in Formanek and Gurian, eds.; Margaret W. Matlin, The Psychology of Women, 2d ed. (Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987); Peggy Orenstein, SchoolGirls: Young Women, Self-Esteem, and the Confidence Gap (New York: Anchor, 1994); Kathleen Y. Ritter, "Depression in Women," in Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling, ed. Ellen Piel Cook (Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association, 1993); Nancy Felipe Russo and Beth L. Green, "Women and Mental Health," in Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories, ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1993); Karen W. Saakvitne and Laurie Anne Pearlman, "The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence against Women on Feminine Identity," in Cook, ed.; Linda Tschirhart Sanford and Mary Ellen Donovan, Women and Self-Esteem (New York: Anchor, 1984); Cheryl Brown Travis, Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1988); and Rhoda Unger and Mary Crawford, Women and Gender: A Feminist Psychology (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • (1987) Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective
    • Jack, D.1
  • 49
    • 0004250387 scopus 로고
    • New York: Basic
    • To be more accurate, damaged self-respect is integrally connected with oppression. The claim that damaged self-respect is a gendered phenomenon requires, of course, more than anecdotal support. There are, however, some difficulties with empirical support. The first is that empirical research is carried on by psychologists, whose term of use is "self-esteem" rather than self-respect. I have argued elsewhere that the two are distinct; however, there is no agreement among psychologists or philosophers about whether there is a distinction and if so what it is. Still, many of the psychological studies I've looked at define "self-esteem" in ways that overlap with self-respect, so it is reasonable to look at that evidence. However, there is reason to worry about gender bias in psychological studies of self-esteem, since the standard definitions and measures (Coopersmith's and Rosenberg's, for example) omit gender considerations and are predicated on a model of the healthy self that is clearly male-biased (Kaschak). Further, empirical research relevant to damaged self-esteem is indirect, through work on shame and on psychopathologies such as depression and eating disorders, both of which are typically analyzed as involving damaged self-worth. There is, however, reason to suspect gender bias (and race bias) in diagnosis of psychopathology. Finally, much empirical work on gender and self-esteem is racially biased, omitting women of color. These methodological concerns are somewhat addressed by looking at studies which are explicitly sensitive to gender and race considerations, and there the evidence is clear. Women with traditionally feminine gender identification are more likely to have low self-esteem than men (Travis). Women are more likely to exceed men on reports of shame (Brody and Hall, Lewis). Women suffer depression at rates two to three times higher than men; the gender difference is consistently confirmed in epidemiological and clinical studies, is not an artifact of reporting, genetics, or hormones, and holds across racial and ethnic lines and cross-culturally (Jack, Russo and Green, Ritter, Matlin, Unger and Crawford, Travis). Ninety to ninety-five percent of those suffering from eating disorders are women. Two-thirds of teen self-mutilators are girls; the etiology is the same as for eating disorders (Orenstein). The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence, done by the American Association of University Women (Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action [Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women, 1991]), found that during adolescence the self-regard of girls drops further than boys' and never catches up; teen girls are much more likely than boys to say they are "not good enough" to achieve their dreams; although girls consistently report lower self-esteem than boys, Latina girls' self-esteem drops much lower than that of Caucasian girls, while the self-esteem of African American girls is higher than that of Caucasian girls though still lower than that of African American boys. All of these studies agree that the best explanation for the findings is that they are the effects on women of living in a sexist society. See Leslie Brody and Judith A. Hall, "Gender and Emotions," in Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland (New York: Guilford, 1993); Dana Jack, "Silencing the Self: The Power of Social Imperatives in Female Depression," in Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective, ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian (New York: Springer, 1987); Ellyn Kaschak, Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience (New York: Basic, 1992); Helen Block Lewis, "The Role of Shame in Depression in Women," in Formanek and Gurian, eds.; Margaret W. Matlin, The Psychology of Women, 2d ed. (Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987); Peggy Orenstein, SchoolGirls: Young Women, Self-Esteem, and the Confidence Gap (New York: Anchor, 1994); Kathleen Y. Ritter, "Depression in Women," in Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling, ed. Ellen Piel Cook (Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association, 1993); Nancy Felipe Russo and Beth L. Green, "Women and Mental Health," in Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories, ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1993); Karen W. Saakvitne and Laurie Anne Pearlman, "The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence against Women on Feminine Identity," in Cook, ed.; Linda Tschirhart Sanford and Mary Ellen Donovan, Women and Self-Esteem (New York: Anchor, 1984); Cheryl Brown Travis, Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1988); and Rhoda Unger and Mary Crawford, Women and Gender: A Feminist Psychology (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • (1992) Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience
    • Kaschak, E.1
  • 50
    • 85033111815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Formanek and Gurian, eds.
    • To be more accurate, damaged self-respect is integrally connected with oppression. The claim that damaged self-respect is a gendered phenomenon requires, of course, more than anecdotal support. There are, however, some difficulties with empirical support. The first is that empirical research is carried on by psychologists, whose term of use is "self-esteem" rather than self-respect. I have argued elsewhere that the two are distinct; however, there is no agreement among psychologists or philosophers about whether there is a distinction and if so what it is. Still, many of the psychological studies I've looked at define "self-esteem" in ways that overlap with self-respect, so it is reasonable to look at that evidence. However, there is reason to worry about gender bias in psychological studies of self-esteem, since the standard definitions and measures (Coopersmith's and Rosenberg's, for example) omit gender considerations and are predicated on a model of the healthy self that is clearly male-biased (Kaschak). Further, empirical research relevant to damaged self-esteem is indirect, through work on shame and on psychopathologies such as depression and eating disorders, both of which are typically analyzed as involving damaged self-worth. There is, however, reason to suspect gender bias (and race bias) in diagnosis of psychopathology. Finally, much empirical work on gender and self-esteem is racially biased, omitting women of color. These methodological concerns are somewhat addressed by looking at studies which are explicitly sensitive to gender and race considerations, and there the evidence is clear. Women with traditionally feminine gender identification are more likely to have low self-esteem than men (Travis). Women are more likely to exceed men on reports of shame (Brody and Hall, Lewis). Women suffer depression at rates two to three times higher than men; the gender difference is consistently confirmed in epidemiological and clinical studies, is not an artifact of reporting, genetics, or hormones, and holds across racial and ethnic lines and cross-culturally (Jack, Russo and Green, Ritter, Matlin, Unger and Crawford, Travis). Ninety to ninety-five percent of those suffering from eating disorders are women. Two-thirds of teen self-mutilators are girls; the etiology is the same as for eating disorders (Orenstein). The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence, done by the American Association of University Women (Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action [Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women, 1991]), found that during adolescence the self-regard of girls drops further than boys' and never catches up; teen girls are much more likely than boys to say they are "not good enough" to achieve their dreams; although girls consistently report lower self-esteem than boys, Latina girls' self-esteem drops much lower than that of Caucasian girls, while the self-esteem of African American girls is higher than that of Caucasian girls though still lower than that of African American boys. All of these studies agree that the best explanation for the findings is that they are the effects on women of living in a sexist society. See Leslie Brody and Judith A. Hall, "Gender and Emotions," in Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland (New York: Guilford, 1993); Dana Jack, "Silencing the Self: The Power of Social Imperatives in Female Depression," in Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective, ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian (New York: Springer, 1987); Ellyn Kaschak, Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience (New York: Basic, 1992); Helen Block Lewis, "The Role of Shame in Depression in Women," in Formanek and Gurian, eds.; Margaret W. Matlin, The Psychology of Women, 2d ed. (Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987); Peggy Orenstein, SchoolGirls: Young Women, Self-Esteem, and the Confidence Gap (New York: Anchor, 1994); Kathleen Y. Ritter, "Depression in Women," in Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling, ed. Ellen Piel Cook (Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association, 1993); Nancy Felipe Russo and Beth L. Green, "Women and Mental Health," in Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories, ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1993); Karen W. Saakvitne and Laurie Anne Pearlman, "The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence against Women on Feminine Identity," in Cook, ed.; Linda Tschirhart Sanford and Mary Ellen Donovan, Women and Self-Esteem (New York: Anchor, 1984); Cheryl Brown Travis, Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1988); and Rhoda Unger and Mary Crawford, Women and Gender: A Feminist Psychology (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • The Role of Shame in Depression in Women
    • Lewis, H.B.1
  • 51
    • 0004231999 scopus 로고
    • Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich
    • To be more accurate, damaged self-respect is integrally connected with oppression. The claim that damaged self-respect is a gendered phenomenon requires, of course, more than anecdotal support. There are, however, some difficulties with empirical support. The first is that empirical research is carried on by psychologists, whose term of use is "self-esteem" rather than self-respect. I have argued elsewhere that the two are distinct; however, there is no agreement among psychologists or philosophers about whether there is a distinction and if so what it is. Still, many of the psychological studies I've looked at define "self-esteem" in ways that overlap with self-respect, so it is reasonable to look at that evidence. However, there is reason to worry about gender bias in psychological studies of self-esteem, since the standard definitions and measures (Coopersmith's and Rosenberg's, for example) omit gender considerations and are predicated on a model of the healthy self that is clearly male-biased (Kaschak). Further, empirical research relevant to damaged self-esteem is indirect, through work on shame and on psychopathologies such as depression and eating disorders, both of which are typically analyzed as involving damaged self-worth. There is, however, reason to suspect gender bias (and race bias) in diagnosis of psychopathology. Finally, much empirical work on gender and self-esteem is racially biased, omitting women of color. These methodological concerns are somewhat addressed by looking at studies which are explicitly sensitive to gender and race considerations, and there the evidence is clear. Women with traditionally feminine gender identification are more likely to have low self-esteem than men (Travis). Women are more likely to exceed men on reports of shame (Brody and Hall, Lewis). Women suffer depression at rates two to three times higher than men; the gender difference is consistently confirmed in epidemiological and clinical studies, is not an artifact of reporting, genetics, or hormones, and holds across racial and ethnic lines and cross-culturally (Jack, Russo and Green, Ritter, Matlin, Unger and Crawford, Travis). Ninety to ninety-five percent of those suffering from eating disorders are women. Two-thirds of teen self-mutilators are girls; the etiology is the same as for eating disorders (Orenstein). The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence, done by the American Association of University Women (Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action [Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women, 1991]), found that during adolescence the self-regard of girls drops further than boys' and never catches up; teen girls are much more likely than boys to say they are "not good enough" to achieve their dreams; although girls consistently report lower self-esteem than boys, Latina girls' self-esteem drops much lower than that of Caucasian girls, while the self-esteem of African American girls is higher than that of Caucasian girls though still lower than that of African American boys. All of these studies agree that the best explanation for the findings is that they are the effects on women of living in a sexist society. See Leslie Brody and Judith A. Hall, "Gender and Emotions," in Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland (New York: Guilford, 1993); Dana Jack, "Silencing the Self: The Power of Social Imperatives in Female Depression," in Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective, ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian (New York: Springer, 1987); Ellyn Kaschak, Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience (New York: Basic, 1992); Helen Block Lewis, "The Role of Shame in Depression in Women," in Formanek and Gurian, eds.; Margaret W. Matlin, The Psychology of Women, 2d ed. (Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987); Peggy Orenstein, SchoolGirls: Young Women, Self-Esteem, and the Confidence Gap (New York: Anchor, 1994); Kathleen Y. Ritter, "Depression in Women," in Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling, ed. Ellen Piel Cook (Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association, 1993); Nancy Felipe Russo and Beth L. Green, "Women and Mental Health," in Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories, ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1993); Karen W. Saakvitne and Laurie Anne Pearlman, "The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence against Women on Feminine Identity," in Cook, ed.; Linda Tschirhart Sanford and Mary Ellen Donovan, Women and Self-Esteem (New York: Anchor, 1984); Cheryl Brown Travis, Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1988); and Rhoda Unger and Mary Crawford, Women and Gender: A Feminist Psychology (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • (1987) The Psychology of Women, 2d Ed.
    • Matlin, M.W.1
  • 52
    • 0003477618 scopus 로고
    • New York: Anchor
    • To be more accurate, damaged self-respect is integrally connected with oppression. The claim that damaged self-respect is a gendered phenomenon requires, of course, more than anecdotal support. There are, however, some difficulties with empirical support. The first is that empirical research is carried on by psychologists, whose term of use is "self-esteem" rather than self-respect. I have argued elsewhere that the two are distinct; however, there is no agreement among psychologists or philosophers about whether there is a distinction and if so what it is. Still, many of the psychological studies I've looked at define "self-esteem" in ways that overlap with self-respect, so it is reasonable to look at that evidence. However, there is reason to worry about gender bias in psychological studies of self-esteem, since the standard definitions and measures (Coopersmith's and Rosenberg's, for example) omit gender considerations and are predicated on a model of the healthy self that is clearly male-biased (Kaschak). Further, empirical research relevant to damaged self-esteem is indirect, through work on shame and on psychopathologies such as depression and eating disorders, both of which are typically analyzed as involving damaged self-worth. There is, however, reason to suspect gender bias (and race bias) in diagnosis of psychopathology. Finally, much empirical work on gender and self-esteem is racially biased, omitting women of color. These methodological concerns are somewhat addressed by looking at studies which are explicitly sensitive to gender and race considerations, and there the evidence is clear. Women with traditionally feminine gender identification are more likely to have low self-esteem than men (Travis). Women are more likely to exceed men on reports of shame (Brody and Hall, Lewis). Women suffer depression at rates two to three times higher than men; the gender difference is consistently confirmed in epidemiological and clinical studies, is not an artifact of reporting, genetics, or hormones, and holds across racial and ethnic lines and cross-culturally (Jack, Russo and Green, Ritter, Matlin, Unger and Crawford, Travis). Ninety to ninety-five percent of those suffering from eating disorders are women. Two-thirds of teen self-mutilators are girls; the etiology is the same as for eating disorders (Orenstein). The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence, done by the American Association of University Women (Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action [Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women, 1991]), found that during adolescence the self-regard of girls drops further than boys' and never catches up; teen girls are much more likely than boys to say they are "not good enough" to achieve their dreams; although girls consistently report lower self-esteem than boys, Latina girls' self-esteem drops much lower than that of Caucasian girls, while the self-esteem of African American girls is higher than that of Caucasian girls though still lower than that of African American boys. All of these studies agree that the best explanation for the findings is that they are the effects on women of living in a sexist society. See Leslie Brody and Judith A. Hall, "Gender and Emotions," in Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland (New York: Guilford, 1993); Dana Jack, "Silencing the Self: The Power of Social Imperatives in Female Depression," in Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective, ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian (New York: Springer, 1987); Ellyn Kaschak, Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience (New York: Basic, 1992); Helen Block Lewis, "The Role of Shame in Depression in Women," in Formanek and Gurian, eds.; Margaret W. Matlin, The Psychology of Women, 2d ed. (Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987); Peggy Orenstein, SchoolGirls: Young Women, Self-Esteem, and the Confidence Gap (New York: Anchor, 1994); Kathleen Y. Ritter, "Depression in Women," in Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling, ed. Ellen Piel Cook (Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association, 1993); Nancy Felipe Russo and Beth L. Green, "Women and Mental Health," in Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories, ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1993); Karen W. Saakvitne and Laurie Anne Pearlman, "The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence against Women on Feminine Identity," in Cook, ed.; Linda Tschirhart Sanford and Mary Ellen Donovan, Women and Self-Esteem (New York: Anchor, 1984); Cheryl Brown Travis, Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues (Hillsdale, N.J.:
    • (1994) Schoolgirls: Young Women, Self-esteem, and the Confidence Gap
    • Orenstein, P.1
  • 53
    • 85033102206 scopus 로고
    • Depression in women
    • ed. Ellen Piel Cook Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association
    • To be more accurate, damaged self-respect is integrally connected with oppression. The claim that damaged self-respect is a gendered phenomenon requires, of course, more than anecdotal support. There are, however, some difficulties with empirical support. The first is that empirical research is carried on by psychologists, whose term of use is "self-esteem" rather than self-respect. I have argued elsewhere that the two are distinct; however, there is no agreement among psychologists or philosophers about whether there is a distinction and if so what it is. Still, many of the psychological studies I've looked at define "self-esteem" in ways that overlap with self-respect, so it is reasonable to look at that evidence. However, there is reason to worry about gender bias in psychological studies of self-esteem, since the standard definitions and measures (Coopersmith's and Rosenberg's, for example) omit gender considerations and are predicated on a model of the healthy self that is clearly male-biased (Kaschak). Further, empirical research relevant to damaged self-esteem is indirect, through work on shame and on psychopathologies such as depression and eating disorders, both of which are typically analyzed as involving damaged self-worth. There is, however, reason to suspect gender bias (and race bias) in diagnosis of psychopathology. Finally, much empirical work on gender and self-esteem is racially biased, omitting women of color. These methodological concerns are somewhat addressed by looking at studies which are explicitly sensitive to gender and race considerations, and there the evidence is clear. Women with traditionally feminine gender identification are more likely to have low self-esteem than men (Travis). Women are more likely to exceed men on reports of shame (Brody and Hall, Lewis). Women suffer depression at rates two to three times higher than men; the gender difference is consistently confirmed in epidemiological and clinical studies, is not an artifact of reporting, genetics, or hormones, and holds across racial and ethnic lines and cross-culturally (Jack, Russo and Green, Ritter, Matlin, Unger and Crawford, Travis). Ninety to ninety-five percent of those suffering from eating disorders are women. Two-thirds of teen self-mutilators are girls; the etiology is the same as for eating disorders (Orenstein). The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence, done by the American Association of University Women (Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action [Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women, 1991]), found that during adolescence the self-regard of girls drops further than boys' and never catches up; teen girls are much more likely than boys to say they are "not good enough" to achieve their dreams; although girls consistently report lower self-esteem than boys, Latina girls' self-esteem drops much lower than that of Caucasian girls, while the self-esteem of African American girls is higher than that of Caucasian girls though still lower than that of African American boys. All of these studies agree that the best explanation for the findings is that they are the effects on women of living in a sexist society. See Leslie Brody and Judith A. Hall, "Gender and Emotions," in Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland (New York: Guilford, 1993); Dana Jack, "Silencing the Self: The Power of Social Imperatives in Female Depression," in Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective, ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian (New York: Springer, 1987); Ellyn Kaschak, Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience (New York: Basic, 1992); Helen Block Lewis, "The Role of Shame in Depression in Women," in Formanek and Gurian, eds.; Margaret W. Matlin, The Psychology of Women, 2d ed. (Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987); Peggy Orenstein, SchoolGirls: Young Women, Self-Esteem, and the Confidence Gap (New York: Anchor, 1994); Kathleen Y. Ritter, "Depression in Women," in Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling, ed. Ellen Piel Cook (Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association, 1993); Nancy Felipe Russo and Beth L. Green, "Women and Mental Health," in Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories, ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1993); Karen W. Saakvitne and Laurie Anne Pearlman, "The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence against Women on Feminine Identity," in Cook, ed.; Linda Tschirhart Sanford and Mary Ellen Donovan, Women and Self-Esteem (New York: Anchor, 1984); Cheryl Brown Travis, Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1988); and Rhoda Unger and Mary Crawford, Women and Gender: A Feminist Psychology (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • (1993) Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling
    • Ritter, K.Y.1
  • 54
    • 0007171304 scopus 로고
    • Women and mental health
    • ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi Westport, Conn.: Greenwood
    • To be more accurate, damaged self-respect is integrally connected with oppression. The claim that damaged self-respect is a gendered phenomenon requires, of course, more than anecdotal support. There are, however, some difficulties with empirical support. The first is that empirical research is carried on by psychologists, whose term of use is "self-esteem" rather than self-respect. I have argued elsewhere that the two are distinct; however, there is no agreement among psychologists or philosophers about whether there is a distinction and if so what it is. Still, many of the psychological studies I've looked at define "self-esteem" in ways that overlap with self-respect, so it is reasonable to look at that evidence. However, there is reason to worry about gender bias in psychological studies of self-esteem, since the standard definitions and measures (Coopersmith's and Rosenberg's, for example) omit gender considerations and are predicated on a model of the healthy self that is clearly male-biased (Kaschak). Further, empirical research relevant to damaged self-esteem is indirect, through work on shame and on psychopathologies such as depression and eating disorders, both of which are typically analyzed as involving damaged self-worth. There is, however, reason to suspect gender bias (and race bias) in diagnosis of psychopathology. Finally, much empirical work on gender and self-esteem is racially biased, omitting women of color. These methodological concerns are somewhat addressed by looking at studies which are explicitly sensitive to gender and race considerations, and there the evidence is clear. Women with traditionally feminine gender identification are more likely to have low self-esteem than men (Travis). Women are more likely to exceed men on reports of shame (Brody and Hall, Lewis). Women suffer depression at rates two to three times higher than men; the gender difference is consistently confirmed in epidemiological and clinical studies, is not an artifact of reporting, genetics, or hormones, and holds across racial and ethnic lines and cross-culturally (Jack, Russo and Green, Ritter, Matlin, Unger and Crawford, Travis). Ninety to ninety-five percent of those suffering from eating disorders are women. Two-thirds of teen self-mutilators are girls; the etiology is the same as for eating disorders (Orenstein). The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence, done by the American Association of University Women (Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action [Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women, 1991]), found that during adolescence the self-regard of girls drops further than boys' and never catches up; teen girls are much more likely than boys to say they are "not good enough" to achieve their dreams; although girls consistently report lower self-esteem than boys, Latina girls' self-esteem drops much lower than that of Caucasian girls, while the self-esteem of African American girls is higher than that of Caucasian girls though still lower than that of African American boys. All of these studies agree that the best explanation for the findings is that they are the effects on women of living in a sexist society. See Leslie Brody and Judith A. Hall, "Gender and Emotions," in Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland (New York: Guilford, 1993); Dana Jack, "Silencing the Self: The Power of Social Imperatives in Female Depression," in Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective, ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian (New York: Springer, 1987); Ellyn Kaschak, Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience (New York: Basic, 1992); Helen Block Lewis, "The Role of Shame in Depression in Women," in Formanek and Gurian, eds.; Margaret W. Matlin, The Psychology of Women, 2d ed. (Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987); Peggy Orenstein, SchoolGirls: Young Women, Self-Esteem, and the Confidence Gap (New York: Anchor, 1994); Kathleen Y. Ritter, "Depression in Women," in Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling, ed. Ellen Piel Cook (Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association, 1993); Nancy Felipe Russo and Beth L. Green, "Women and Mental Health," in Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories, ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1993); Karen W. Saakvitne and Laurie Anne Pearlman, "The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence against Women on Feminine Identity," in Cook, ed.; Linda Tschirhart Sanford and Mary Ellen Donovan, Women and Self-Esteem (New York: Anchor, 1984); Cheryl Brown Travis, Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1988); and Rhoda Unger and Mary Crawford, Women and Gender: A Feminist Psychology (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • (1993) Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories
    • Russo, N.F.1    Green, B.L.2
  • 55
    • 85033119739 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cook, ed.
    • To be more accurate, damaged self-respect is integrally connected with oppression. The claim that damaged self-respect is a gendered phenomenon requires, of course, more than anecdotal support. There are, however, some difficulties with empirical support. The first is that empirical research is carried on by psychologists, whose term of use is "self-esteem" rather than self-respect. I have argued elsewhere that the two are distinct; however, there is no agreement among psychologists or philosophers about whether there is a distinction and if so what it is. Still, many of the psychological studies I've looked at define "self-esteem" in ways that overlap with self-respect, so it is reasonable to look at that evidence. However, there is reason to worry about gender bias in psychological studies of self-esteem, since the standard definitions and measures (Coopersmith's and Rosenberg's, for example) omit gender considerations and are predicated on a model of the healthy self that is clearly male-biased (Kaschak). Further, empirical research relevant to damaged self-esteem is indirect, through work on shame and on psychopathologies such as depression and eating disorders, both of which are typically analyzed as involving damaged self-worth. There is, however, reason to suspect gender bias (and race bias) in diagnosis of psychopathology. Finally, much empirical work on gender and self-esteem is racially biased, omitting women of color. These methodological concerns are somewhat addressed by looking at studies which are explicitly sensitive to gender and race considerations, and there the evidence is clear. Women with traditionally feminine gender identification are more likely to have low self-esteem than men (Travis). Women are more likely to exceed men on reports of shame (Brody and Hall, Lewis). Women suffer depression at rates two to three times higher than men; the gender difference is consistently confirmed in epidemiological and clinical studies, is not an artifact of reporting, genetics, or hormones, and holds across racial and ethnic lines and cross-culturally (Jack, Russo and Green, Ritter, Matlin, Unger and Crawford, Travis). Ninety to ninety-five percent of those suffering from eating disorders are women. Two-thirds of teen self-mutilators are girls; the etiology is the same as for eating disorders (Orenstein). The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence, done by the American Association of University Women (Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action [Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women, 1991]), found that during adolescence the self-regard of girls drops further than boys' and never catches up; teen girls are much more likely than boys to say they are "not good enough" to achieve their dreams; although girls consistently report lower self-esteem than boys, Latina girls' self-esteem drops much lower than that of Caucasian girls, while the self-esteem of African American girls is higher than that of Caucasian girls though still lower than that of African American boys. All of these studies agree that the best explanation for the findings is that they are the effects on women of living in a sexist society. See Leslie Brody and Judith A. Hall, "Gender and Emotions," in Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland (New York: Guilford, 1993); Dana Jack, "Silencing the Self: The Power of Social Imperatives in Female Depression," in Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective, ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian (New York: Springer, 1987); Ellyn Kaschak, Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience (New York: Basic, 1992); Helen Block Lewis, "The Role of Shame in Depression in Women," in Formanek and Gurian, eds.; Margaret W. Matlin, The Psychology of Women, 2d ed. (Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987); Peggy Orenstein, SchoolGirls: Young Women, Self-Esteem, and the Confidence Gap (New York: Anchor, 1994); Kathleen Y. Ritter, "Depression in Women," in Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling, ed. Ellen Piel Cook (Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association, 1993); Nancy Felipe Russo and Beth L. Green, "Women and Mental Health," in Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories, ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1993); Karen W. Saakvitne and Laurie Anne Pearlman, "The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence against Women on Feminine Identity," in Cook, ed.; Linda Tschirhart Sanford and Mary Ellen Donovan, Women and Self-Esteem (New York: Anchor, 1984); Cheryl Brown Travis, Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1988); and Rhoda Unger and Mary Crawford, Women and Gender: A Feminist Psychology (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence Against Women on Feminine Identity
    • Saakvitne, K.W.1    Pearlman, L.A.2
  • 56
    • 0004101149 scopus 로고
    • New York: Anchor
    • To be more accurate, damaged self-respect is integrally connected with oppression. The claim that damaged self-respect is a gendered phenomenon requires, of course, more than anecdotal support. There are, however, some difficulties with empirical support. The first is that empirical research is carried on by psychologists, whose term of use is "self-esteem" rather than self-respect. I have argued elsewhere that the two are distinct; however, there is no agreement among psychologists or philosophers about whether there is a distinction and if so what it is. Still, many of the psychological studies I've looked at define "self-esteem" in ways that overlap with self-respect, so it is reasonable to look at that evidence. However, there is reason to worry about gender bias in psychological studies of self-esteem, since the standard definitions and measures (Coopersmith's and Rosenberg's, for example) omit gender considerations and are predicated on a model of the healthy self that is clearly male-biased (Kaschak). Further, empirical research relevant to damaged self-esteem is indirect, through work on shame and on psychopathologies such as depression and eating disorders, both of which are typically analyzed as involving damaged self-worth. There is, however, reason to suspect gender bias (and race bias) in diagnosis of psychopathology. Finally, much empirical work on gender and self-esteem is racially biased, omitting women of color. These methodological concerns are somewhat addressed by looking at studies which are explicitly sensitive to gender and race considerations, and there the evidence is clear. Women with traditionally feminine gender identification are more likely to have low self-esteem than men (Travis). Women are more likely to exceed men on reports of shame (Brody and Hall, Lewis). Women suffer depression at rates two to three times higher than men; the gender difference is consistently confirmed in epidemiological and clinical studies, is not an artifact of reporting, genetics, or hormones, and holds across racial and ethnic lines and cross-culturally (Jack, Russo and Green, Ritter, Matlin, Unger and Crawford, Travis). Ninety to ninety-five percent of those suffering from eating disorders are women. Two-thirds of teen self-mutilators are girls; the etiology is the same as for eating disorders (Orenstein). The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence, done by the American Association of University Women (Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action [Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women, 1991]), found that during adolescence the self-regard of girls drops further than boys' and never catches up; teen girls are much more likely than boys to say they are "not good enough" to achieve their dreams; although girls consistently report lower self-esteem than boys, Latina girls' self-esteem drops much lower than that of Caucasian girls, while the self-esteem of African American girls is higher than that of Caucasian girls though still lower than that of African American boys. All of these studies agree that the best explanation for the findings is that they are the effects on women of living in a sexist society. See Leslie Brody and Judith A. Hall, "Gender and Emotions," in Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland (New York: Guilford, 1993); Dana Jack, "Silencing the Self: The Power of Social Imperatives in Female Depression," in Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective, ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian (New York: Springer, 1987); Ellyn Kaschak, Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience (New York: Basic, 1992); Helen Block Lewis, "The Role of Shame in Depression in Women," in Formanek and Gurian, eds.; Margaret W. Matlin, The Psychology of Women, 2d ed. (Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987); Peggy Orenstein, SchoolGirls: Young Women, Self-Esteem, and the Confidence Gap (New York: Anchor, 1994); Kathleen Y. Ritter, "Depression in Women," in Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling, ed. Ellen Piel Cook (Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association, 1993); Nancy Felipe Russo and Beth L. Green, "Women and Mental Health," in Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories, ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1993); Karen W. Saakvitne and Laurie Anne Pearlman, "The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence against Women on Feminine Identity," in Cook, ed.; Linda Tschirhart Sanford and Mary Ellen Donovan, Women and Self-Esteem (New York: Anchor, 1984); Cheryl Brown Travis, Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1988); and Rhoda Unger and Mary Crawford, Women and Gender: A Feminist Psychology (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • (1984) Women and Self-esteem
    • Sanford, L.T.1    Donovan, M.E.2
  • 57
    • 0003754185 scopus 로고
    • Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum
    • To be more accurate, damaged self-respect is integrally connected with oppression. The claim that damaged self-respect is a gendered phenomenon requires, of course, more than anecdotal support. There are, however, some difficulties with empirical support. The first is that empirical research is carried on by psychologists, whose term of use is "self-esteem" rather than self-respect. I have argued elsewhere that the two are distinct; however, there is no agreement among psychologists or philosophers about whether there is a distinction and if so what it is. Still, many of the psychological studies I've looked at define "self-esteem" in ways that overlap with self-respect, so it is reasonable to look at that evidence. However, there is reason to worry about gender bias in psychological studies of self-esteem, since the standard definitions and measures (Coopersmith's and Rosenberg's, for example) omit gender considerations and are predicated on a model of the healthy self that is clearly male-biased (Kaschak). Further, empirical research relevant to damaged self-esteem is indirect, through work on shame and on psychopathologies such as depression and eating disorders, both of which are typically analyzed as involving damaged self-worth. There is, however, reason to suspect gender bias (and race bias) in diagnosis of psychopathology. Finally, much empirical work on gender and self-esteem is racially biased, omitting women of color. These methodological concerns are somewhat addressed by looking at studies which are explicitly sensitive to gender and race considerations, and there the evidence is clear. Women with traditionally feminine gender identification are more likely to have low self-esteem than men (Travis). Women are more likely to exceed men on reports of shame (Brody and Hall, Lewis). Women suffer depression at rates two to three times higher than men; the gender difference is consistently confirmed in epidemiological and clinical studies, is not an artifact of reporting, genetics, or hormones, and holds across racial and ethnic lines and cross-culturally (Jack, Russo and Green, Ritter, Matlin, Unger and Crawford, Travis). Ninety to ninety-five percent of those suffering from eating disorders are women. Two-thirds of teen self-mutilators are girls; the etiology is the same as for eating disorders (Orenstein). The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence, done by the American Association of University Women (Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action [Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women, 1991]), found that during adolescence the self-regard of girls drops further than boys' and never catches up; teen girls are much more likely than boys to say they are "not good enough" to achieve their dreams; although girls consistently report lower self-esteem than boys, Latina girls' self-esteem drops much lower than that of Caucasian girls, while the self-esteem of African American girls is higher than that of Caucasian girls though still lower than that of African American boys. All of these studies agree that the best explanation for the findings is that they are the effects on women of living in a sexist society. See Leslie Brody and Judith A. Hall, "Gender and Emotions," in Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland (New York: Guilford, 1993); Dana Jack, "Silencing the Self: The Power of Social Imperatives in Female Depression," in Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective, ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian (New York: Springer, 1987); Ellyn Kaschak, Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience (New York: Basic, 1992); Helen Block Lewis, "The Role of Shame in Depression in Women," in Formanek and Gurian, eds.; Margaret W. Matlin, The Psychology of Women, 2d ed. (Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987); Peggy Orenstein, SchoolGirls: Young Women, Self-Esteem, and the Confidence Gap (New York: Anchor, 1994); Kathleen Y. Ritter, "Depression in Women," in Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling, ed. Ellen Piel Cook (Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association, 1993); Nancy Felipe Russo and Beth L. Green, "Women and Mental Health," in Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories, ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1993); Karen W. Saakvitne and Laurie Anne Pearlman, "The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence against Women on Feminine Identity," in Cook, ed.; Linda Tschirhart Sanford and Mary Ellen Donovan, Women and Self-Esteem (New York: Anchor, 1984); Cheryl Brown Travis, Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1988); and Rhoda Unger and Mary Crawford, Women and Gender: A Feminist Psychology (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • (1988) Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues
    • Travis, C.B.1
  • 58
    • 0003789750 scopus 로고
    • Philadelphia: Temple University Press
    • To be more accurate, damaged self-respect is integrally connected with oppression. The claim that damaged self-respect is a gendered phenomenon requires, of course, more than anecdotal support. There are, however, some difficulties with empirical support. The first is that empirical research is carried on by psychologists, whose term of use is "self-esteem" rather than self-respect. I have argued elsewhere that the two are distinct; however, there is no agreement among psychologists or philosophers about whether there is a distinction and if so what it is. Still, many of the psychological studies I've looked at define "self-esteem" in ways that overlap with self-respect, so it is reasonable to look at that evidence. However, there is reason to worry about gender bias in psychological studies of self-esteem, since the standard definitions and measures (Coopersmith's and Rosenberg's, for example) omit gender considerations and are predicated on a model of the healthy self that is clearly male-biased (Kaschak). Further, empirical research relevant to damaged self-esteem is indirect, through work on shame and on psychopathologies such as depression and eating disorders, both of which are typically analyzed as involving damaged self-worth. There is, however, reason to suspect gender bias (and race bias) in diagnosis of psychopathology. Finally, much empirical work on gender and self-esteem is racially biased, omitting women of color. These methodological concerns are somewhat addressed by looking at studies which are explicitly sensitive to gender and race considerations, and there the evidence is clear. Women with traditionally feminine gender identification are more likely to have low self-esteem than men (Travis). Women are more likely to exceed men on reports of shame (Brody and Hall, Lewis). Women suffer depression at rates two to three times higher than men; the gender difference is consistently confirmed in epidemiological and clinical studies, is not an artifact of reporting, genetics, or hormones, and holds across racial and ethnic lines and cross-culturally (Jack, Russo and Green, Ritter, Matlin, Unger and Crawford, Travis). Ninety to ninety-five percent of those suffering from eating disorders are women. Two-thirds of teen self-mutilators are girls; the etiology is the same as for eating disorders (Orenstein). The most extensive national survey on gender and self-esteem in adolescence, done by the American Association of University Women (Shortchanging Girls, Shortchanging America: A Call to Action [Washington, D.C.: American Association of University Women, 1991]), found that during adolescence the self-regard of girls drops further than boys' and never catches up; teen girls are much more likely than boys to say they are "not good enough" to achieve their dreams; although girls consistently report lower self-esteem than boys, Latina girls' self-esteem drops much lower than that of Caucasian girls, while the self-esteem of African American girls is higher than that of Caucasian girls though still lower than that of African American boys. All of these studies agree that the best explanation for the findings is that they are the effects on women of living in a sexist society. See Leslie Brody and Judith A. Hall, "Gender and Emotions," in Handbook of Emotions, ed. Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. Haviland (New York: Guilford, 1993); Dana Jack, "Silencing the Self: The Power of Social Imperatives in Female Depression," in Women and Depression: A Lifespan Perspective, ed. Ruth Formanek and Anita Gurian (New York: Springer, 1987); Ellyn Kaschak, Engendered Lives: A New Psychology of Women's Experience (New York: Basic, 1992); Helen Block Lewis, "The Role of Shame in Depression in Women," in Formanek and Gurian, eds.; Margaret W. Matlin, The Psychology of Women, 2d ed. (Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987); Peggy Orenstein, SchoolGirls: Young Women, Self-Esteem, and the Confidence Gap (New York: Anchor, 1994); Kathleen Y. Ritter, "Depression in Women," in Women, Relationships, and Power: Implications for Counseling, ed. Ellen Piel Cook (Alexandria, Va.: American Counseling Association, 1993); Nancy Felipe Russo and Beth L. Green, "Women and Mental Health," in Psychology of Women: A Handbook of Issues and Theories, ed. Florence L. Denmark and Michele A. Paludi (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood, 1993); Karen W. Saakvitne and Laurie Anne Pearlman, "The Impact of Internalized Misogyny and Violence against Women on Feminine Identity," in Cook, ed.; Linda Tschirhart Sanford and Mary Ellen Donovan, Women and Self-Esteem (New York: Anchor, 1984); Cheryl Brown Travis, Women and Health Psychology: Mental Health Issues (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1988); and Rhoda Unger and Mary Crawford, Women and Gender: A Feminist Psychology (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992).
    • (1992) Women and Gender: A Feminist Psychology
    • Unger, R.1    Crawford, M.2
  • 59
    • 0004289747 scopus 로고
    • Explaining emotions
    • ed. Amélie Oksenberg Rorty Berkeley: University of California Press
    • They might also be explained in terms of bad emotional habits, weakness of will, or bad faith, i.e., insufficient commitment to the standards these women claim to embrace. (Amélie Rorty discusses "akrasia of the emotions" [also known as "irrational conservation of emotions"] in "Explaining Emotions," in Explaining Emotions, ed. Amélie Oksenberg Rorty [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980]; Bartky discusses the bad faith charge in "Feminism and the Politics of Personal Transformation," in her Femininity and Domination.) I won't pursue these suggestions, however, since they don't really explain the divergence of emotions and beliefs in these cases, or its persistence in the face of distress and sincere efforts to change, or the power of the emotions to so profoundly shape the lives of these women.
    • (1980) Explaining Emotions
    • Rorty, A.1
  • 60
    • 80051673420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feminism and the politics of personal transformation
    • They might also be explained in terms of bad emotional habits, weakness of will, or bad faith, i.e., insufficient commitment to the standards these women claim to embrace. (Amélie Rorty discusses "akrasia of the emotions" [also known as "irrational conservation of emotions"] in "Explaining Emotions," in Explaining Emotions, ed. Amélie Oksenberg Rorty [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980]; Bartky discusses the bad faith charge in "Feminism and the Politics of Personal Transformation," in her Femininity and Domination.) I won't pursue these suggestions, however, since they don't really explain the divergence of emotions and beliefs in these cases, or its persistence in the face of distress and sincere efforts to change, or the power of the emotions to so profoundly shape the lives of these women.
    • Femininity and Domination
    • Bartky1
  • 61
    • 84875361980 scopus 로고
    • Cognitivism in the theory of emotions
    • For an illuminating discussion of cognitivism and emotion, see John Deigh, "Cognitivism in the Theory of Emotions," Ethics 104 (1994): 824-54. I draw on Deigh in what follows.
    • (1994) Ethics , vol.104 , pp. 824-854
    • Deigh, J.1
  • 62
    • 0007189615 scopus 로고
    • Love and knowledge: Emotion in feminist Epistemology
    • ed. Ann Garry and Marilyn Pearsall Boston: Unwin Hyman
    • Alison Jaggar, "Love and Knowledge: Emotion in Feminist Epistemology," in Women, Knowledge, and Reality: Explorations in Feminist Philosophy, ed. Ann Garry and Marilyn Pearsall (Boston: Unwin Hyman, 1989), pp. 144-45.
    • (1989) Women, Knowledge, and Reality: Explorations in Feminist Philosophy , pp. 144-145
    • Jaggar, A.1
  • 63
    • 0009318423 scopus 로고
    • Race, class, and the social construction of self-respect
    • For an illuminating discussion of the ways in which social institutions limit access to socially defined bases of self-respect, see Michele M. Moody-Adams, "Race, Class, and the Social Construction of Self-Respect," Philosophical Forum 24 (1992-93): 251-66, reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • (1992) Philosophical Forum , vol.24 , pp. 251-266
    • Moody-Adams, M.M.1
  • 64
    • 85033103961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reprinted
    • For an illuminating discussion of the ways in which social institutions limit access to socially defined bases of self-respect, see Michele M. Moody-Adams, "Race, Class, and the Social Construction of Self-Respect," Philosophical Forum 24 (1992-93): 251-66, reprinted in Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect.
    • Dignity, Character, and Self-respect
  • 66
    • 14544305794 scopus 로고
    • Cognitive emotions?
    • ed. Cheshire Calhoun and Robert C. Solomon New York: Oxford University Press
    • Cheshire Calhoun distinguishes "believing intellectually" and "believing evidentially," the latter being a matter of feeling or experiencing things in a certain way, in "Cognitive Emotions?" in What Is an Emotion? Classic Readings in Philosophical Psychology, ed. Cheshire Calhoun and Robert C. Solomon (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984), pp. 335-36. Michael Pritchard draws a similar distinction between "intellectual understanding" and "participant understanding," where the latter mode involves the engagement of one's sentiments, in On Becoming Responsible, chap. 3. Michael Stocker differentiates beliefs from "emotional thoughts," which can conflict with beliefs and in which something is emotionally present and taken seriously or felt to be the case, in "Emotional Thoughts," American Philosophical Quarterly 24 (1987): 59-69.
    • (1984) What Is An Emotion? Classic Readings in Philosophical Psychology , pp. 335-336
    • Calhoun, C.1
  • 67
    • 0009234636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 3
    • Cheshire Calhoun distinguishes "believing intellectually" and "believing evidentially," the latter being a matter of feeling or experiencing things in a certain way, in "Cognitive Emotions?" in What Is an Emotion? Classic Readings in Philosophical Psychology, ed. Cheshire Calhoun and Robert C. Solomon (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984), pp. 335-36. Michael Pritchard draws a similar distinction between "intellectual understanding" and "participant understanding," where the latter mode involves the engagement of one's sentiments, in On Becoming Responsible, chap. 3. Michael Stocker differentiates beliefs from "emotional thoughts," which can conflict with beliefs and in which something is emotionally present and taken seriously or felt to be the case, in "Emotional Thoughts," American Philosophical Quarterly 24 (1987): 59-69.
    • On Becoming Responsible
    • Pritchard, M.1
  • 68
    • 0010210685 scopus 로고
    • Emotional thoughts
    • Cheshire Calhoun distinguishes "believing intellectually" and "believing evidentially," the latter being a matter of feeling or experiencing things in a certain way, in "Cognitive Emotions?" in What Is an Emotion? Classic Readings in Philosophical Psychology, ed. Cheshire Calhoun and Robert C. Solomon (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984), pp. 335-36. Michael Pritchard draws a similar distinction between "intellectual understanding" and "participant understanding," where the latter mode involves the engagement of one's sentiments, in On Becoming Responsible, chap. 3. Michael Stocker differentiates beliefs from "emotional thoughts," which can conflict with beliefs and in which something is emotionally present and taken seriously or felt to be the case, in "Emotional Thoughts," American Philosophical Quarterly 24 (1987): 59-69.
    • (1987) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.24 , pp. 59-69
    • Stocker, M.1
  • 69
    • 0039787858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Deigh, "Cognitivism in the Theory of Emotions"; Calhoun; Susan E. Babbitt, Impossible Dreams: Rationality, Integrity, and Moral Imagination (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1996), chap. 2; and Richmond Campbell's critical notice of Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, by Allan Gibbard, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 32 (1993): 299-324.
    • Cognitivism in the Theory of Emotions
    • Deigh1
  • 70
    • 0008986576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boulder, Colo.: Westview, chap. 2
    • See Deigh, "Cognitivism in the Theory of Emotions"; Calhoun; Susan E. Babbitt, Impossible Dreams: Rationality, Integrity, and Moral Imagination (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1996), chap. 2; and Richmond Campbell's critical notice of Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, by Allan Gibbard, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 32 (1993): 299-324.
    • (1996) Impossible Dreams: Rationality, Integrity, and Moral Imagination
    • Calhoun1    Babbitt, S.E.2
  • 71
    • 84886844951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Deigh, "Cognitivism in the Theory of Emotions"; Calhoun; Susan E. Babbitt, Impossible Dreams: Rationality, Integrity, and Moral Imagination (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1996), chap. 2; and Richmond Campbell's critical notice of Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, by Allan Gibbard, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 32 (1993): 299-324.
    • Wise Choices, Apt Feelings
    • Campbell, R.1
  • 72
    • 0040974363 scopus 로고
    • See Deigh, "Cognitivism in the Theory of Emotions"; Calhoun; Susan E. Babbitt, Impossible Dreams: Rationality, Integrity, and Moral Imagination (Boulder, Colo.: Westview, 1996), chap. 2; and Richmond Campbell's critical notice of Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, by Allan Gibbard, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 32 (1993): 299-324.
    • (1993) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.32 , pp. 299-324
    • Gibbard, A.1
  • 73
    • 0000219825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The influence of early experience on personality development
    • See Mark H. Bickhard and John Chambers Christopher, "The Influence of Early Experience on Personality Development," New Ideas in Psychology 12 (1994): 229-52; V. F. Guidano and G. Liotti, Cognitive Processes and Emotional Disorders (New York: Guilford, 1993); Michael Polanyi, The Tacit Dimension (New York: Doubleday, 1966); and Calhoun.
    • (1994) New Ideas in Psychology , vol.12 , pp. 229-252
    • Bickhard, M.H.1    Christopher, J.C.2
  • 74
    • 0000219825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Guilford
    • See Mark H. Bickhard and John Chambers Christopher, "The Influence of Early Experience on Personality Development," New Ideas in Psychology 12 (1994): 229-52; V. F. Guidano and G. Liotti, Cognitive Processes and Emotional Disorders (New York: Guilford, 1993); Michael Polanyi, The Tacit Dimension (New York: Doubleday, 1966); and Calhoun.
    • (1993) Cognitive Processes and Emotional Disorders
    • Guidano, V.F.1    Liotti, G.2
  • 75
    • 0000219825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Doubleday
    • See Mark H. Bickhard and John Chambers Christopher, "The Influence of Early Experience on Personality Development," New Ideas in Psychology 12 (1994): 229-52; V. F. Guidano and G. Liotti, Cognitive Processes and Emotional Disorders (New York: Guilford, 1993); Michael Polanyi, The Tacit Dimension (New York: Doubleday, 1966); and Calhoun.
    • (1966) The Tacit Dimension
    • Polanyi, M.1
  • 76
    • 0000219825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Mark H. Bickhard and John Chambers Christopher, "The Influence of Early Experience on Personality Development," New Ideas in Psychology 12 (1994): 229-52; V. F. Guidano and G. Liotti, Cognitive Processes and Emotional Disorders (New York: Guilford, 1993); Michael Polanyi, The Tacit Dimension (New York: Doubleday, 1966); and Calhoun.
    • Calhoun1
  • 77
    • 85033118107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emotion and self-theory
    • Lewis and Haviland, eds.
    • Since developing this account, I have found it to be congruent with a number of analyses in psychology, most notably Guidano and Liotti; and Seymour Epstein, "Emotion and Self-Theory," in Lewis and Haviland, eds. What Thomas calls "basic psychological security" also points in the direction of basal self-respect (Living Morally, pp. 61, 242).
    • Living Morally , pp. 61
    • Guidano1    Liotti2    Epstein, S.3
  • 78
    • 0040380094 scopus 로고
    • On self-respect
    • New York: Washington Square
    • Joan Didion, "On Self-Respect," in Slouching toward Bethlehem (New York: Washington Square, 1968), pp. 124-25.
    • (1968) Slouching Toward Bethlehem , pp. 124-125
    • Didion, J.1
  • 79
    • 85033115606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • One might object here, as an Ethics editor did, "the fact that a source of self-respect is political will not settle the extent of the agent's responsibility, if any, for failed self-respect. In some cases where the excusing cause is political, still, all things considered, one may judge that the individual should have done more to preserve self-respect and is to a degree blameworthy." However, while this objection does hold for evaluative and recognition self-respect, it misses the point regarding basal self-respect. For the point is not that the excusing cause of damaged basal self-respect is a political one (and, suppressed premise, a political cause obviates responsibility), but rather that what is damaged (by political causes) is basal self-respect, which, as the fundamental interpretive medium, is what makes it possible or impossible for one to do anything to build, preserve, receive support for, etc., the other two kinds of self-respect. I return to this point in the last section.
  • 80
    • 0040974371 scopus 로고
    • Social construction in emotions
    • Lewis and Haviland, eds.; Doris Howard, ed., New York: Haworth
    • I draw here on the large body of work in philosophy and psychology on the social construction of emotion and personality, especially in connection with gender. In psychology, see, e.g., Kaschak; Travis; Brody and Hall; Unger and Crawford; Keith Oatley, "Social Construction in Emotions," in Lewis and Haviland, eds.; Doris Howard, ed., The Dynamics of Feminist Therapy (New York: Haworth, 1986); M. Butler, "Guidelines for Feminist Therapy," in Handbook of Feminist Therapy, ed. L. B. Rosewater and L. Walker (New York: Springer, 1985); Hannah Lerman, "The Limits of Phenomenology: A Feminist Critique of the Humanistic Personality Theories," in Personality and Psychopathology: Feminist Appraisals, ed. Laura S. Brown and Mary Ballou (New York: Guilford, 1992); Rom Harre, ed., The Social Construction of Emotions (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986). In philosophy, see, e.g., Bartky, "Shame and Gender"; Jaggar; Marilyn Frye, "A Note on Anger," in her The Politics of Reality: Essays in Feminist Theory (Freedom, Calif.: Crossing, 1983); Naomi Scheman, "Individualism and the Objects of Psychology," in Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, ed. Sandra Harding and Merrill Hintikka (Boston: Reidel, 1983).
    • (1986) The Dynamics of Feminist Therapy
    • Kaschak1    Travis2    Brody3    Hall4    Unger5    Crawford6    Oatley, K.7
  • 81
    • 0007126346 scopus 로고
    • Guidelines for feminist therapy
    • ed. L. B. Rosewater and L. Walker New York: Springer
    • I draw here on the large body of work in philosophy and psychology on the social construction of emotion and personality, especially in connection with gender. In psychology, see, e.g., Kaschak; Travis; Brody and Hall; Unger and Crawford; Keith Oatley, "Social Construction in Emotions," in Lewis and Haviland, eds.; Doris Howard, ed., The Dynamics of Feminist Therapy (New York: Haworth, 1986); M. Butler, "Guidelines for Feminist Therapy," in Handbook of Feminist Therapy, ed. L. B. Rosewater and L. Walker (New York: Springer, 1985); Hannah Lerman, "The Limits of Phenomenology: A Feminist Critique of the Humanistic Personality Theories," in Personality and Psychopathology: Feminist Appraisals, ed. Laura S. Brown and Mary Ballou (New York: Guilford, 1992); Rom Harre, ed., The Social Construction of Emotions (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986). In philosophy, see, e.g., Bartky, "Shame and Gender"; Jaggar; Marilyn Frye, "A Note on Anger," in her The Politics of Reality: Essays in Feminist Theory (Freedom, Calif.: Crossing, 1983); Naomi Scheman, "Individualism and the Objects of Psychology," in Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, ed. Sandra Harding and Merrill Hintikka (Boston: Reidel, 1983).
    • (1985) Handbook of Feminist Therapy
    • Butler, M.1
  • 82
    • 38149088910 scopus 로고
    • The limits of phenomenology: A feminist critique of the humanistic personality theories
    • ed. Laura S. Brown and Mary Ballou New York: Guilford
    • I draw here on the large body of work in philosophy and psychology on the social construction of emotion and personality, especially in connection with gender. In psychology, see, e.g., Kaschak; Travis; Brody and Hall; Unger and Crawford; Keith Oatley, "Social Construction in Emotions," in Lewis and Haviland, eds.; Doris Howard, ed., The Dynamics of Feminist Therapy (New York: Haworth, 1986); M. Butler, "Guidelines for Feminist Therapy," in Handbook of Feminist Therapy, ed. L. B. Rosewater and L. Walker (New York: Springer, 1985); Hannah Lerman, "The Limits of Phenomenology: A Feminist Critique of the Humanistic Personality Theories," in Personality and Psychopathology: Feminist Appraisals, ed. Laura S. Brown and Mary Ballou (New York: Guilford, 1992); Rom Harre, ed., The Social Construction of Emotions (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986). In philosophy, see, e.g., Bartky, "Shame and Gender"; Jaggar; Marilyn Frye, "A Note on Anger," in her The Politics of Reality: Essays in Feminist Theory (Freedom, Calif.: Crossing, 1983); Naomi Scheman, "Individualism and the Objects of Psychology," in Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, ed. Sandra Harding and Merrill Hintikka (Boston: Reidel, 1983).
    • (1992) Personality and Psychopathology: Feminist Appraisals
    • Lerman, H.1
  • 83
    • 0004209789 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • I draw here on the large body of work in philosophy and psychology on the social construction of emotion and personality, especially in connection with gender. In psychology, see, e.g., Kaschak; Travis; Brody and Hall; Unger and Crawford; Keith Oatley, "Social Construction in Emotions," in Lewis and Haviland, eds.; Doris Howard, ed., The Dynamics of Feminist Therapy (New York: Haworth, 1986); M. Butler, "Guidelines for Feminist Therapy," in Handbook of Feminist Therapy, ed. L. B. Rosewater and L. Walker (New York: Springer, 1985); Hannah Lerman, "The Limits of Phenomenology: A Feminist Critique of the Humanistic Personality Theories," in Personality and Psychopathology: Feminist Appraisals, ed. Laura S. Brown and Mary Ballou (New York: Guilford, 1992); Rom Harre, ed., The Social Construction of Emotions (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986). In philosophy, see, e.g., Bartky, "Shame and Gender"; Jaggar; Marilyn Frye, "A Note on Anger," in her The Politics of Reality: Essays in Feminist Theory (Freedom, Calif.: Crossing, 1983); Naomi Scheman, "Individualism and the Objects of Psychology," in Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, ed. Sandra Harding and Merrill Hintikka (Boston: Reidel, 1983).
    • (1986) The Social Construction of Emotions
    • Harre, R.1
  • 84
    • 85033114142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I draw here on the large body of work in philosophy and psychology on the social construction of emotion and personality, especially in connection with gender. In psychology, see, e.g., Kaschak; Travis; Brody and Hall; Unger and Crawford; Keith Oatley, "Social Construction in Emotions," in Lewis and Haviland, eds.; Doris Howard, ed., The Dynamics of Feminist Therapy (New York: Haworth, 1986); M. Butler, "Guidelines for Feminist Therapy," in Handbook of Feminist Therapy, ed. L. B. Rosewater and L. Walker (New York: Springer, 1985); Hannah Lerman, "The Limits of Phenomenology: A Feminist Critique of the Humanistic Personality Theories," in Personality and Psychopathology: Feminist Appraisals, ed. Laura S. Brown and Mary Ballou (New York: Guilford, 1992); Rom Harre, ed., The Social Construction of Emotions (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986). In philosophy, see, e.g., Bartky, "Shame and Gender"; Jaggar; Marilyn Frye, "A Note on Anger," in her The Politics of Reality: Essays in Feminist Theory (Freedom, Calif.: Crossing, 1983); Naomi Scheman, "Individualism and the Objects of Psychology," in Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, ed. Sandra Harding and Merrill Hintikka (Boston: Reidel, 1983).
    • Shame and Gender
    • Bartky1
  • 85
    • 0039787852 scopus 로고
    • A note on anger
    • Freedom, Calif.: Crossing
    • I draw here on the large body of work in philosophy and psychology on the social construction of emotion and personality, especially in connection with gender. In psychology, see, e.g., Kaschak; Travis; Brody and Hall; Unger and Crawford; Keith Oatley, "Social Construction in Emotions," in Lewis and Haviland, eds.; Doris Howard, ed., The Dynamics of Feminist Therapy (New York: Haworth, 1986); M. Butler, "Guidelines for Feminist Therapy," in Handbook of Feminist Therapy, ed. L. B. Rosewater and L. Walker (New York: Springer, 1985); Hannah Lerman, "The Limits of Phenomenology: A Feminist Critique of the Humanistic Personality Theories," in Personality and Psychopathology: Feminist Appraisals, ed. Laura S. Brown and Mary Ballou (New York: Guilford, 1992); Rom Harre, ed., The Social Construction of Emotions (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986). In philosophy, see, e.g., Bartky, "Shame and Gender"; Jaggar; Marilyn Frye, "A Note on Anger," in her The Politics of Reality: Essays in Feminist Theory (Freedom, Calif.: Crossing, 1983); Naomi Scheman, "Individualism and the Objects of Psychology," in Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, ed. Sandra Harding and Merrill Hintikka (Boston: Reidel, 1983).
    • (1983) The Politics of Reality: Essays in Feminist Theory
    • Jaggar1    Frye, M.2
  • 86
    • 0011469764 scopus 로고
    • Individualism and the objects of psychology
    • ed. Sandra Harding and Merrill Hintikka Boston: Reidel
    • I draw here on the large body of work in philosophy and psychology on the social construction of emotion and personality, especially in connection with gender. In psychology, see, e.g., Kaschak; Travis; Brody and Hall; Unger and Crawford; Keith Oatley, "Social Construction in Emotions," in Lewis and Haviland, eds.; Doris Howard, ed., The Dynamics of Feminist Therapy (New York: Haworth, 1986); M. Butler, "Guidelines for Feminist Therapy," in Handbook of Feminist Therapy, ed. L. B. Rosewater and L. Walker (New York: Springer, 1985); Hannah Lerman, "The Limits of Phenomenology: A Feminist Critique of the Humanistic Personality Theories," in Personality and Psychopathology: Feminist Appraisals, ed. Laura S. Brown and Mary Ballou (New York: Guilford, 1992); Rom Harre, ed., The Social Construction of Emotions (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986). In philosophy, see, e.g., Bartky, "Shame and Gender"; Jaggar; Marilyn Frye, "A Note on Anger," in her The Politics of Reality: Essays in Feminist Theory (Freedom, Calif.: Crossing, 1983); Naomi Scheman, "Individualism and the Objects of Psychology," in Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, ed. Sandra Harding and Merrill Hintikka (Boston: Reidel, 1983).
    • (1983) Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science
    • Scheman, N.1
  • 87
    • 85033109128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am indebted to Richmond Campbell for this point. The primordial human experience of being a valued and valuable person among valued and valuable persons is not only the experiential source for an individual's basal, recognition, and evaluation self-respect but is also the ground of the very concepts of recognition and evaluative self-respect, which are socially constructed out of that collective experience, in light of other socially constructed (hence historically, culturally, and ideologically variable) concepts, such as personhood, personal identity, agency, the good life, and so on.
  • 88
    • 0039787853 scopus 로고
    • Eye to eye: Black women, hatred, and anger
    • Trumansburg, N.Y.: Crossing
    • The term is Audre Lorde's, in "Eye to Eye: Black Women, Hatred, and Anger," in her Sister Outsider (Trumansburg, N.Y.: Crossing, 1984).
    • (1984) Sister Outsider
    • Lorde, A.1
  • 90
    • 85033103144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I owe this way of putting the point to Laurence Thomas.
  • 93
    • 85033114142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bartky, "Shame and Gender," p. 85. The phrase in single quotes she attributes to Husseen Abdilahi Bulhan, Frantz Fanon and the Psychology of Oppression (New York: Plenum, 1985), p. 122.
    • Shame and Gender , pp. 85
    • Bartky1
  • 94
  • 96
    • 0004222801 scopus 로고
    • New York: Guilford
    • It is important to note (as one reviewer did) that when gender works together with other factors - for example, race or ethnicity - being female might in fact make one less liable to damaged self-respect. With regard to race and ethnicity, however, I've found no evidence to support this hypothesis and much that suggests the opposite. See, e.g., the essays in Lillian Comas-Diaz and Beverly Greene, eds., Women of Color: Integrating Ethnic and Gender Identities in Psychotherapy (New York: Guilford, 1994).
    • (1994) Women of Color: Integrating Ethnic and Gender Identities in Psychotherapy
    • Comas-Diaz, L.1    Greene, B.2
  • 97
    • 85033121833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For two claims that one can and must love oneself into self-respect, see Lorde, pp. 172-75; and Collins, pp. 107-13.
    • Lorde1
  • 98
    • 85033105127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For two claims that one can and must love oneself into self-respect, see Lorde, pp. 172-75; and Collins, pp. 107-13.
    • Collins1
  • 99
    • 0040974286 scopus 로고
    • Feminism and objective interests: The role of transformation experiences in rational deliberation
    • ed. Linda Alcoff and Elizabeth Potter New York: Routledge
    • See Susan Babbitt, "Feminism and Objective Interests: The Role of Transformation Experiences in Rational Deliberation," in Feminist Epistemologies, ed. Linda Alcoff and Elizabeth Potter (New York: Routledge, 1993).
    • (1993) Feminist Epistemologies
    • Babbitt, S.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.