메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 38, Issue 1, 2000, Pages 57-77

The value of facts in Boyle's experimental philosophy

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0002135696     PISSN: 00732753     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/007327530003800103     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (8)

References (146)
  • 1
    • 0346542303 scopus 로고
    • Boyle as a theoretical scientist
    • M. Boas Hall, "Boyle as a theoretical scientist", Isis, xli (1950), 261-8, and "The establishment of the mechanical philosophy", Osiris, x (1952), 412-541; R. S. Westfall, "Unpublished Boyle papers relating to scientific method", Annals of science, xii (1956), 63-73, 103-17; and idem, The construction of modern science: Mechanisms and mechanics (Cambridge, 1971), esp. pp. 41, 49-50, 75-81.
    • (1950) Isis , vol.41 , pp. 261-268
    • Boas Hall, M.1
  • 2
    • 0346542303 scopus 로고
    • The establishment of the mechanical philosophy
    • M. Boas Hall, "Boyle as a theoretical scientist", Isis, xli (1950), 261-8, and "The establishment of the mechanical philosophy", Osiris, x (1952), 412-541; R. S. Westfall, "Unpublished Boyle papers relating to scientific method", Annals of science, xii (1956), 63-73, 103-17; and idem, The construction of modern science: Mechanisms and mechanics (Cambridge, 1971), esp. pp. 41, 49-50, 75-81.
    • (1952) Osiris , vol.10 , pp. 412-541
  • 3
    • 84945596532 scopus 로고
    • Unpublished Boyle papers relating to scientific method
    • M. Boas Hall, "Boyle as a theoretical scientist", Isis, xli (1950), 261-8, and "The establishment of the mechanical philosophy", Osiris, x (1952), 412-541; R. S. Westfall, "Unpublished Boyle papers relating to scientific method", Annals of science, xii (1956), 63-73, 103-17; and idem, The construction of modern science: Mechanisms and mechanics (Cambridge, 1971), esp. pp. 41, 49-50, 75-81.
    • (1956) Annals of Science , vol.12 , pp. 63-73
    • Westfall, R.S.1
  • 4
    • 0346542303 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • M. Boas Hall, "Boyle as a theoretical scientist", Isis, xli (1950), 261-8, and "The establishment of the mechanical philosophy", Osiris, x (1952), 412-541; R. S. Westfall, "Unpublished Boyle papers relating to scientific method", Annals of science, xii (1956), 63-73, 103-17; and idem, The construction of modern science: Mechanisms and mechanics (Cambridge, 1971), esp. pp. 41, 49-50, 75-81.
    • (1971) The Construction of Modern Science: Mechanisms and Mechanics , pp. 41
    • Westfall, R.S.1
  • 5
    • 80054250776 scopus 로고
    • Princeton
    • S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life (Princeton, 1985). Their conclusions concerning the dictinctive character of Boyle's experimental programme were affirmed, in a broader context of the changing methodologies in seventeenth-century natural philosophy, by P. Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the scientific revolution (Chicago, 1995), esp. pp. 227-32. For the recent emphasis in science studies on the relative autonomy, with respect to theory, of experimental research, see, for example, I. Hacking, Representing and intervening (Cambridge, 1983); P. Galison, How experiments end (Chicago, 1987); D. Gooding, T. Pinch and S. Schaffer (eds), The uses of experiment: Studies in the natural sciences (Cambridge, 1989); T. Lenoir, "Practice, reason, context: The dialogue between theory and experiment", Science in context, ii (1989), 3-22; A. Pickering (ed.), Science as practice and culture (Chicago, 1992); J. Z. Buchwald (ed.), Scientific practice: Theories and stories of doing physics (Chicago, 1995).
    • (1985) Leviathan and the Air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life
    • Shapin, S.1    Schaffer, S.2
  • 6
    • 0004065718 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life (Princeton, 1985). Their conclusions concerning the dictinctive character of Boyle's experimental programme were affirmed, in a broader context of the changing methodologies in seventeenth-century natural philosophy, by P. Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the scientific revolution (Chicago, 1995), esp. pp. 227-32. For the recent emphasis in science studies on the relative autonomy, with respect to theory, of experimental research, see, for example, I. Hacking, Representing and intervening (Cambridge, 1983); P. Galison, How experiments end (Chicago, 1987); D. Gooding, T. Pinch and S. Schaffer (eds), The uses of experiment: Studies in the natural sciences (Cambridge, 1989); T. Lenoir, "Practice, reason, context: The dialogue between theory and experiment", Science in context, ii (1989), 3-22; A. Pickering (ed.), Science as practice and culture (Chicago, 1992); J. Z. Buchwald (ed.), Scientific practice: Theories and stories of doing physics (Chicago, 1995).
    • (1995) Discipline and Experience: The Mathematical Way in the Scientific Revolution , pp. 227-232
    • Dear, P.1
  • 7
    • 0003837238 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life (Princeton, 1985). Their conclusions concerning the dictinctive character of Boyle's experimental programme were affirmed, in a broader context of the changing methodologies in seventeenth-century natural philosophy, by P. Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the scientific revolution (Chicago, 1995), esp. pp. 227-32. For the recent emphasis in science studies on the relative autonomy, with respect to theory, of experimental research, see, for example, I. Hacking, Representing and intervening (Cambridge, 1983); P. Galison, How experiments end (Chicago, 1987); D. Gooding, T. Pinch and S. Schaffer (eds), The uses of experiment: Studies in the natural sciences (Cambridge, 1989); T. Lenoir, "Practice, reason, context: The dialogue between theory and experiment", Science in context, ii (1989), 3-22; A. Pickering (ed.), Science as practice and culture (Chicago, 1992); J. Z. Buchwald (ed.), Scientific practice: Theories and stories of doing physics (Chicago, 1995).
    • (1983) Representing and Intervening
    • Hacking, I.1
  • 8
    • 0003875877 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life (Princeton, 1985). Their conclusions concerning the dictinctive character of Boyle's experimental programme were affirmed, in a broader context of the changing methodologies in seventeenth-century natural philosophy, by P. Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the scientific revolution (Chicago, 1995), esp. pp. 227-32. For the recent emphasis in science studies on the relative autonomy, with respect to theory, of experimental research, see, for example, I. Hacking, Representing and intervening (Cambridge, 1983); P. Galison, How experiments end (Chicago, 1987); D. Gooding, T. Pinch and S. Schaffer (eds), The uses of experiment: Studies in the natural sciences (Cambridge, 1989); T. Lenoir, "Practice, reason, context: The dialogue between theory and experiment", Science in context, ii (1989), 3-22; A. Pickering (ed.), Science as practice and culture (Chicago, 1992); J. Z. Buchwald (ed.), Scientific practice: Theories and stories of doing physics (Chicago, 1995).
    • (1987) How Experiments End
    • Galison, P.1
  • 9
    • 0003406022 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life (Princeton, 1985). Their conclusions concerning the dictinctive character of Boyle's experimental programme were affirmed, in a broader context of the changing methodologies in seventeenth-century natural philosophy, by P. Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the scientific revolution (Chicago, 1995), esp. pp. 227-32. For the recent emphasis in science studies on the relative autonomy, with respect to theory, of experimental research, see, for example, I. Hacking, Representing and intervening (Cambridge, 1983); P. Galison, How experiments end (Chicago, 1987); D. Gooding, T. Pinch and S. Schaffer (eds), The uses of experiment: Studies in the natural sciences (Cambridge, 1989); T. Lenoir, "Practice, reason, context: The dialogue between theory and experiment", Science in context, ii (1989), 3-22; A. Pickering (ed.), Science as practice and culture (Chicago, 1992); J. Z. Buchwald (ed.), Scientific practice: Theories and stories of doing physics (Chicago, 1995).
    • (1989) The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences
    • Gooding, D.1    Pinch, T.2    Schaffer, S.3
  • 10
    • 84918247617 scopus 로고
    • Practice, reason, context: The dialogue between theory and experiment
    • S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life (Princeton, 1985). Their conclusions concerning the dictinctive character of Boyle's experimental programme were affirmed, in a broader context of the changing methodologies in seventeenth-century natural philosophy, by P. Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the scientific revolution (Chicago, 1995), esp. pp. 227-32. For the recent emphasis in science studies on the relative autonomy, with respect to theory, of experimental research, see, for example, I. Hacking, Representing and intervening (Cambridge, 1983); P. Galison, How experiments end (Chicago, 1987); D. Gooding, T. Pinch and S. Schaffer (eds), The uses of experiment: Studies in the natural sciences (Cambridge, 1989); T. Lenoir, "Practice, reason, context: The dialogue between theory and experiment", Science in context, ii (1989), 3-22; A. Pickering (ed.), Science as practice and culture (Chicago, 1992); J. Z. Buchwald (ed.), Scientific practice: Theories and stories of doing physics (Chicago, 1995).
    • (1989) Science in Context , vol.2 , pp. 3-22
    • Lenoir, T.1
  • 11
    • 0003410567 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life (Princeton, 1985). Their conclusions concerning the dictinctive character of Boyle's experimental programme were affirmed, in a broader context of the changing methodologies in seventeenth-century natural philosophy, by P. Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the scientific revolution (Chicago, 1995), esp. pp. 227-32. For the recent emphasis in science studies on the relative autonomy, with respect to theory, of experimental research, see, for example, I. Hacking, Representing and intervening (Cambridge, 1983); P. Galison, How experiments end (Chicago, 1987); D. Gooding, T. Pinch and S. Schaffer (eds), The uses of experiment: Studies in the natural sciences (Cambridge, 1989); T. Lenoir, "Practice, reason, context: The dialogue between theory and experiment", Science in context, ii (1989), 3-22; A. Pickering (ed.), Science as practice and culture (Chicago, 1992); J. Z. Buchwald (ed.), Scientific practice: Theories and stories of doing physics (Chicago, 1995).
    • (1992) Science as Practice and Culture
    • Pickering, A.1
  • 12
    • 0012818709 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • S. Shapin and S. Schaffer, Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life (Princeton, 1985). Their conclusions concerning the dictinctive character of Boyle's experimental programme were affirmed, in a broader context of the changing methodologies in seventeenth-century natural philosophy, by P. Dear, Discipline and experience: The mathematical way in the scientific revolution (Chicago, 1995), esp. pp. 227-32. For the recent emphasis in science studies on the relative autonomy, with respect to theory, of experimental research, see, for example, I. Hacking, Representing and intervening (Cambridge, 1983); P. Galison, How experiments end (Chicago, 1987); D. Gooding, T. Pinch and S. Schaffer (eds), The uses of experiment: Studies in the natural sciences (Cambridge, 1989); T. Lenoir, "Practice, reason, context: The dialogue between theory and experiment", Science in context, ii (1989), 3-22; A. Pickering (ed.), Science as practice and culture (Chicago, 1992); J. Z. Buchwald (ed.), Scientific practice: Theories and stories of doing physics (Chicago, 1995).
    • (1995) Scientific Practice: Theories and Stories of Doing Physics
    • Buchwald, J.Z.1
  • 13
    • 0001248479 scopus 로고
    • The lack of excellency of Boyle's mechanical philosophy
    • A. Chalmers, "The lack of excellency of Boyle's mechanical philosophy", Studies in history and philosophy of science, xxiv (1993), 541-64, p. 563.
    • (1993) Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , vol.24 , pp. 541-564
    • Chalmers, A.1
  • 15
    • 0009830591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert Boyle (1627-91): A suitable case for treatment?
    • M. Hunter, "Robert Boyle (1627-91): A suitable case for treatment?", The British journal for the history of science, xxx (1999), 261-75, p. 263.
    • (1999) The British Journal for the History of Science , vol.30 , pp. 261-275
    • Hunter, M.1
  • 18
    • 0345897083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 2
    • Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), esp. pp. 22-24; Sargent, The diffident naturalist (ref. 6). esp. pp. 5-20. For Popkin's thesis and its impact on historical studies of English methodological thought, see R. H. Popkin, The history of scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza (Berkeley, 1979); Henry G. van Leeuwen, The problem of certainty in English thought (The Hague, 1963); Barbara Shapiro, "Latitudinarianism and science in seventeenth-century England", in C. Webster (ed.), The intellectual revolution of the seventeenth century (London, 1974), 286-316, and Probability and certainty in seventeenth-century England: A study of the relationship between natural science, religion, history, law, and literature (Princeton, 1983); J. Henry, "The scientific revolution in England", in R. Porter and M. Teich (eds), The scientific revolution in national context (Cambridge, 1992), 178-209.
    • Leviathan , pp. 22-24
    • Shapin1    Schaffer2
  • 19
    • 39049138619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 6
    • Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), esp. pp. 22-24; Sargent, The diffident naturalist (ref. 6). esp. pp. 5-20. For Popkin's thesis and its impact on historical studies of English methodological thought, see R. H. Popkin, The history of scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza (Berkeley, 1979); Henry G. van Leeuwen, The problem of certainty in English thought (The Hague, 1963); Barbara Shapiro, "Latitudinarianism and science in seventeenth-century England", in C. Webster (ed.), The intellectual revolution of the seventeenth century (London, 1974), 286-316, and Probability and certainty in seventeenth-century England: A study of the relationship between natural science, religion, history, law, and literature (Princeton, 1983); J. Henry, "The scientific revolution in England", in R. Porter and M. Teich (eds), The scientific revolution in national context (Cambridge, 1992), 178-209.
    • The Diffident Naturalist , pp. 5-20
    • Sargent1
  • 20
    • 0004208466 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley
    • Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), esp. pp. 22-24; Sargent, The diffident naturalist (ref. 6). esp. pp. 5-20. For Popkin's thesis and its impact on historical studies of English methodological thought, see R. H. Popkin, The history of scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza (Berkeley, 1979); Henry G. van Leeuwen, The problem of certainty in English thought (The Hague, 1963); Barbara Shapiro, "Latitudinarianism and science in seventeenth-century England", in C. Webster (ed.), The intellectual revolution of the seventeenth century (London, 1974), 286-316, and Probability and certainty in seventeenth-century England: A study of the relationship between natural science, religion, history, law, and literature (Princeton, 1983); J. Henry, "The scientific revolution in England", in R. Porter and M. Teich (eds), The scientific revolution in national context (Cambridge, 1992), 178-209.
    • (1979) The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza
    • Popkin, R.H.1
  • 21
    • 84968139592 scopus 로고
    • The Hague
    • Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), esp. pp. 22-24; Sargent, The diffident naturalist (ref. 6). esp. pp. 5-20. For Popkin's thesis and its impact on historical studies of English methodological thought, see R. H. Popkin, The history of scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza (Berkeley, 1979); Henry G. van Leeuwen, The problem of certainty in English thought (The Hague, 1963); Barbara Shapiro, "Latitudinarianism and science in seventeenth-century England", in C. Webster (ed.), The intellectual revolution of the seventeenth century (London, 1974), 286-316, and Probability and certainty in seventeenth-century England: A study of the relationship between natural science, religion, history, law, and literature (Princeton, 1983); J. Henry, "The scientific revolution in England", in R. Porter and M. Teich (eds), The scientific revolution in national context (Cambridge, 1992), 178-209.
    • (1963) The Problem of Certainty in English Thought
    • Van Leeuwen, H.G.1
  • 22
    • 85069176837 scopus 로고
    • Latitudinarianism and science in seventeenth-century England
    • C. Webster (ed.), London
    • Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), esp. pp. 22-24; Sargent, The diffident naturalist (ref. 6). esp. pp. 5-20. For Popkin's thesis and its impact on historical studies of English methodological thought, see R. H. Popkin, The history of scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza (Berkeley, 1979); Henry G. van Leeuwen, The problem of certainty in English thought (The Hague, 1963); Barbara Shapiro, "Latitudinarianism and science in seventeenth-century England", in C. Webster (ed.), The intellectual revolution of the seventeenth century (London, 1974), 286-316, and Probability and certainty in seventeenth-century England: A study of the relationship between natural science, religion, history, law, and literature (Princeton, 1983); J. Henry, "The scientific revolution in England", in R. Porter and M. Teich (eds), The scientific revolution in national context (Cambridge, 1992), 178-209.
    • (1974) The Intellectual Revolution of the Seventeenth Century , pp. 286-316
    • Shapiro, B.1
  • 23
    • 0003876280 scopus 로고
    • Princeton
    • Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), esp. pp. 22-24; Sargent, The diffident naturalist (ref. 6). esp. pp. 5-20. For Popkin's thesis and its impact on historical studies of English methodological thought, see R. H. Popkin, The history of scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza (Berkeley, 1979); Henry G. van Leeuwen, The problem of certainty in English thought (The Hague, 1963); Barbara Shapiro, "Latitudinarianism and science in seventeenth-century England", in C. Webster (ed.), The intellectual revolution of the seventeenth century (London, 1974), 286-316, and Probability and certainty in seventeenth-century England: A study of the relationship between natural science, religion, history, law, and literature (Princeton, 1983); J. Henry, "The scientific revolution in England", in R. Porter and M. Teich (eds), The scientific revolution in national context (Cambridge, 1992), 178-209.
    • (1983) Probability and Certainty in Seventeenth-century England: A Study of the Relationship between Natural Science, Religion, History, Law, and Literature
  • 24
    • 0002830765 scopus 로고
    • The scientific revolution in England
    • R. Porter and M. Teich (eds), Cambridge
    • Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), esp. pp. 22-24; Sargent, The diffident naturalist (ref. 6). esp. pp. 5-20. For Popkin's thesis and its impact on historical studies of English methodological thought, see R. H. Popkin, The history of scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza (Berkeley, 1979); Henry G. van Leeuwen, The problem of certainty in English thought (The Hague, 1963); Barbara Shapiro, "Latitudinarianism and science in seventeenth-century England", in C. Webster (ed.), The intellectual revolution of the seventeenth century (London, 1974), 286-316, and Probability and certainty in seventeenth-century England: A study of the relationship between natural science, religion, history, law, and literature (Princeton, 1983); J. Henry, "The scientific revolution in England", in R. Porter and M. Teich (eds), The scientific revolution in national context (Cambridge, 1992), 178-209.
    • (1992) The Scientific Revolution in National Context , pp. 178-209
    • Henry, J.1
  • 25
    • 0002669339 scopus 로고
    • Discourse on the method
    • transl. by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff and D. Murdoch 2 vols, Cambridge
    • René Descartes, "Discourse on the method", in The philosophical writings of Descartes, transl. by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff and D. Murdoch (2 vols, Cambridge, 1985), i, 142-3; D. Garber, "Descartes and experiment in the Discourse and Essays", in S. Voss (ed.), Essays on the philosophy and science of René Descartes (Oxford, 1993), 288-323; T. Hobbes, "Physical dialogue", transl. by S. Schaffer, in Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), 345-91; Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), esp. pp. 115-25.
    • (1985) The Philosophical Writings of Descartes , vol.1 , pp. 142-143
    • Descartes, R.1
  • 26
    • 0009830590 scopus 로고
    • Descartes and experiment in the Discourse and Essays
    • S. Voss (ed.), Oxford
    • René Descartes, "Discourse on the method", in The philosophical writings of Descartes, transl. by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff and D. Murdoch (2 vols, Cambridge, 1985), i, 142-3; D. Garber, "Descartes and experiment in the Discourse and Essays", in S. Voss (ed.), Essays on the philosophy and science of René Descartes (Oxford, 1993), 288-323; T. Hobbes, "Physical dialogue", transl. by S. Schaffer, in Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), 345-91; Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), esp. pp. 115-25.
    • (1993) Essays on the Philosophy and Science of René Descartes , pp. 288-323
    • Garber, D.1
  • 27
    • 0009837101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Physical dialogue
    • transl. by S. Schaffer, in Shapin and Schaffer, ref. 2
    • René Descartes, "Discourse on the method", in The philosophical writings of Descartes, transl. by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff and D. Murdoch (2 vols, Cambridge, 1985), i, 142-3; D. Garber, "Descartes and experiment in the Discourse and Essays", in S. Voss (ed.), Essays on the philosophy and science of René Descartes (Oxford, 1993), 288-323; T. Hobbes, "Physical dialogue", transl. by S. Schaffer, in Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), 345-91; Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), esp. pp. 115-25.
    • Leviathan , pp. 345-391
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 28
    • 0345897083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 2
    • René Descartes, "Discourse on the method", in The philosophical writings of Descartes, transl. by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff and D. Murdoch (2 vols, Cambridge, 1985), i, 142-3; D. Garber, "Descartes and experiment in the Discourse and Essays", in S. Voss (ed.), Essays on the philosophy and science of René Descartes (Oxford, 1993), 288-323; T. Hobbes, "Physical dialogue", transl. by S. Schaffer, in Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), 345-91; Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), esp. pp. 115-25.
    • Leviathan , pp. 115-125
    • Shapin1    Schaffer2
  • 29
    • 0003771927 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • The distinction between active and passive entitlement was commonly drawn by scholars of legal aspects of ownership, and it often pertained to theological discussions of economic conduct. See, for example, R. Tuck, Natural rights theories: Their origin and development (Cambridge, 1979), esp. pp. 5-7.
    • (1979) Natural Rights Theories: Their Origin and Development , pp. 5-7
    • Tuck, R.1
  • 30
    • 0015412213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boyle's conception of nature
    • The Royal Society of London, MS 195, f. 192. For studies of Boyle's theocentric conception of the natural order, see J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; E. M. Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science: Belief in creation in seventeenth-century thought (Grand Rapids, 1977). For a detailed study of Boyle's views and recomendations for accommodating human reasoning to divine rule, see Jan W. Wojcik, Robert Boyle and the limits of reason (Cambridge, 1997).
    • (1972) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.33 , pp. 523-542
    • McGuire, J.E.1
  • 31
    • 0015412213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grand Rapids
    • The Royal Society of London, MS 195, f. 192. For studies of Boyle's theocentric conception of the natural order, see J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; E. M. Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science: Belief in creation in seventeenth-century thought (Grand Rapids, 1977). For a detailed study of Boyle's views and recomendations for accommodating human reasoning to divine rule, see Jan W. Wojcik, Robert Boyle and the limits of reason (Cambridge, 1997).
    • (1977) Religious Origins of Modern Science: Belief in Creation in Seventeenth-century Thought
    • Klaaren, E.M.1
  • 32
    • 0015412213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • The Royal Society of London, MS 195, f. 192. For studies of Boyle's theocentric conception of the natural order, see J. E. McGuire, "Boyle's conception of nature", Journal of the history of ideas, xxxiii (1972), 523-42; E. M. Klaaren, Religious origins of modern science: Belief in creation in seventeenth-century thought (Grand Rapids, 1977). For a detailed study of Boyle's views and recomendations for accommodating human reasoning to divine rule, see Jan W. Wojcik, Robert Boyle and the limits of reason (Cambridge, 1997).
    • (1997) Robert Boyle and the Limits of Reason
    • Wojcik, J.W.1
  • 33
    • 0347172538 scopus 로고
    • Some considerations touching the usefulness of experimental natural philosophy
    • ed. by T. Birch 6 vols, London, 1772; reprinted Hildesheim
    • R. Boyle, "Some considerations touching the usefulness of experimental natural philosophy", in The works of the Honourable Robert Boyle, ed. by T. Birch (6 vols, London, 1772; reprinted Hildesheim, 1965-66), i, 433.
    • (1965) The Works of the Honourable Robert Boyle , vol.1 , pp. 433
    • Boyle, R.1
  • 34
    • 0010503041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), ii, 53.
    • Works , vol.2 , pp. 53
    • Boyle1
  • 35
    • 0347172545 scopus 로고
    • An account of Philaretus
    • M. Hunter (ed.), London
    • R. Boyle, "An account of Philaretus", in M. Hunter (ed.), Robert Boyle by himself and his friends (London, 1994), 4, 7.
    • (1994) Robert Boyle by Himself and his Friends , vol.4 , pp. 7
    • Boyle, R.1
  • 36
    • 0020146035 scopus 로고
    • Greatrakes the stroker: The interpretations of historians
    • N. H. Steneck, "Greatrakes the stroker: The interpretations of historians", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 161-77; B. B. Kaplan, "Greatrakes the stroker: The interpretations of his contemporaries", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 178-85.
    • (1982) Isis , vol.73 , pp. 161-177
    • Steneck, N.H.1
  • 37
    • 0020144282 scopus 로고
    • Greatrakes the stroker: The interpretations of his contemporaries
    • N. H. Steneck, "Greatrakes the stroker: The interpretations of historians", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 161-77; B. B. Kaplan, "Greatrakes the stroker: The interpretations of his contemporaries", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 178-85.
    • (1982) Isis , vol.73 , pp. 178-185
    • Kaplan, B.B.1
  • 38
    • 0347802550 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), ii, 51.
    • Works , vol.2 , pp. 51
    • Boyle1
  • 39
    • 85013334182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 442-3.
    • Works , pp. 442-443
  • 40
    • 84965802234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'In the warehouse': Privacy, property and priority in the early Royal Society
    • This view explains in part Boyle's objection to intellectual secrecy and proprietary, but it did not abrogate the legitimate claim, in his view, to ownership rights with respect to inventions. See R. Iliffe, "'In the warehouse': Privacy, property and priority in the early Royal Society", History of science, xxx (1992), 29-68; L. M. Principe, "Boyle's alchemical pursuits", in Hunter (ed.). op. cit. (ref. 14), 91-105.
    • (1992) History of Science , vol.30 , pp. 29-68
    • Iliffe, R.1
  • 41
    • 84965802234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boyle's alchemical pursuits
    • Hunter (ed.). ref. 14
    • This view explains in part Boyle's objection to intellectual secrecy and proprietary, but it did not abrogate the legitimate claim, in his view, to ownership rights with respect to inventions. See R. Iliffe, "'In the warehouse': Privacy, property and priority in the early Royal Society", History of science, xxx (1992), 29-68; L. M. Principe, "Boyle's alchemical pursuits", in Hunter (ed.). op. cit. (ref. 14), 91-105.
    • History of Science , pp. 91-105
    • Principe, L.M.1
  • 42
    • 0002511344 scopus 로고
    • The intellectual sources of Boyle's philosophy of nature: Gassendi's voluntarism and Boyle's physico-theological project
    • R. Kroll, R. Ashcraft and P. Zagorin (eds), Cambridge
    • See, for example, M. Osler, "The intellectual sources of Boyle's philosophy of nature: Gassendi's voluntarism and Boyle's physico-theological project", in R. Kroll, R. Ashcraft and P. Zagorin (eds), Philosophy, science and religion in England 1640-1700 (Cambridge, 1992), 178-98; J. T. Harwood, The early essays and ethics of Robert Boyle (Carbondale and Edwardsville, 1991) (for a review of Harwood's demonstration of the conventional character of Boyle's ethical writings, see Steven Shapin, "Personal development and intellectual biography: The case of Robert Boyle", The British journal for the history of science, xxvi (1993), 335-45; M. Oster, "Biography, culture, and science: The formative years of Robert Boyle", History of science, xxi (1993), 177-226, and "Virtue, providence and political neutralism: Boyle and Interregnum politics", in M. Hunter (ed.), Robert Boyle reconsidered (Cambridge, 1994), 19-36; Lawrence M. Principe, "Style and thought of the early Boyle: Discovery of the 1648 manuscript of Seraphic love", Isis, lxxxv (1994), 247-60.
    • (1992) Philosophy, Science and Religion in England 1640-1700 , pp. 178-198
    • Osler, M.1
  • 43
    • 0004145687 scopus 로고
    • Carbondale and Edwardsville
    • See, for example, M. Osler, "The intellectual sources of Boyle's philosophy of nature: Gassendi's voluntarism and Boyle's physico-theological project", in R. Kroll, R. Ashcraft and P. Zagorin (eds), Philosophy, science and religion in England 1640-1700 (Cambridge, 1992), 178-98; J. T. Harwood, The early essays and ethics of Robert Boyle (Carbondale and Edwardsville, 1991) (for a review of Harwood's demonstration of the conventional character of Boyle's ethical writings, see Steven Shapin, "Personal development and intellectual biography: The case of Robert Boyle", The British journal for the history of science, xxvi (1993), 335-45; M. Oster, "Biography, culture, and science: The formative years of Robert Boyle", History of science, xxi (1993), 177-226, and "Virtue, providence and political neutralism: Boyle and Interregnum politics", in M. Hunter (ed.), Robert Boyle reconsidered (Cambridge, 1994), 19-36; Lawrence M. Principe, "Style and thought of the early Boyle: Discovery of the 1648 manuscript of Seraphic love", Isis, lxxxv (1994), 247-60.
    • (1991) The Early Essays and Ethics of Robert Boyle
    • Harwood, J.T.1
  • 44
    • 0002253063 scopus 로고
    • Personal development and intellectual biography: The case of Robert Boyle
    • See, for example, M. Osler, "The intellectual sources of Boyle's philosophy of nature: Gassendi's voluntarism and Boyle's physico-theological project", in R. Kroll, R. Ashcraft and P. Zagorin (eds), Philosophy, science and religion in England 1640-1700 (Cambridge, 1992), 178-98; J. T. Harwood, The early essays and ethics of Robert Boyle (Carbondale and Edwardsville, 1991) (for a review of Harwood's demonstration of the conventional character of Boyle's ethical writings, see Steven Shapin, "Personal development and intellectual biography: The case of Robert Boyle", The British journal for the history of science, xxvi (1993), 335-45; M. Oster, "Biography, culture, and science: The formative years of Robert Boyle", History of science, xxi (1993), 177-226, and "Virtue, providence and political neutralism: Boyle and Interregnum politics", in M. Hunter (ed.), Robert Boyle reconsidered (Cambridge, 1994), 19-36; Lawrence M. Principe, "Style and thought of the early Boyle: Discovery of the 1648 manuscript of Seraphic love", Isis, lxxxv (1994), 247-60.
    • (1993) The British Journal for the History of Science , vol.26 , pp. 335-345
    • Shapin, S.1
  • 45
    • 0027606214 scopus 로고
    • Biography, culture, and science: The formative years of Robert Boyle
    • See, for example, M. Osler, "The intellectual sources of Boyle's philosophy of nature: Gassendi's voluntarism and Boyle's physico-theological project", in R. Kroll, R. Ashcraft and P. Zagorin (eds), Philosophy, science and religion in England 1640-1700 (Cambridge, 1992), 178-98; J. T. Harwood, The early essays and ethics of Robert Boyle (Carbondale and Edwardsville, 1991) (for a review of Harwood's demonstration of the conventional character of Boyle's ethical writings, see Steven Shapin, "Personal development and intellectual biography: The case of Robert Boyle", The British journal for the history of science, xxvi (1993), 335-45; M. Oster, "Biography, culture, and science: The formative years of Robert Boyle", History of science, xxi (1993), 177-226, and "Virtue, providence and political neutralism: Boyle and Interregnum politics", in M. Hunter (ed.), Robert Boyle reconsidered (Cambridge, 1994), 19-36; Lawrence M. Principe, "Style and thought of the early Boyle: Discovery of the 1648 manuscript of Seraphic love", Isis, lxxxv (1994), 247-60.
    • (1993) History of Science , vol.21 , pp. 177-226
    • Oster, M.1
  • 46
    • 0001954411 scopus 로고
    • Virtue, providence and political neutralism: Boyle and Interregnum politics
    • Cambridge
    • See, for example, M. Osler, "The intellectual sources of Boyle's philosophy of nature: Gassendi's voluntarism and Boyle's physico-theological project", in R. Kroll, R. Ashcraft and P. Zagorin (eds), Philosophy, science and religion in England 1640-1700 (Cambridge, 1992), 178-98; J. T. Harwood, The early essays and ethics of Robert Boyle (Carbondale and Edwardsville, 1991) (for a review of Harwood's demonstration of the conventional character of Boyle's ethical writings, see Steven Shapin, "Personal development and intellectual biography: The case of Robert Boyle", The British journal for the history of science, xxvi (1993), 335-45; M. Oster, "Biography, culture, and science: The formative years of Robert Boyle", History of science, xxi (1993), 177-226, and "Virtue, providence and political neutralism: Boyle and Interregnum politics", in M. Hunter (ed.), Robert Boyle reconsidered (Cambridge, 1994), 19-36; Lawrence M. Principe, "Style and thought of the early Boyle: Discovery of the 1648 manuscript of Seraphic love", Isis, lxxxv (1994), 247-60.
    • (1994) Robert Boyle Reconsidered , pp. 19-36
    • Hunter, M.1
  • 47
    • 0009873729 scopus 로고
    • Style and thought of the early Boyle: Discovery of the 1648 manuscript of Seraphic love
    • See, for example, M. Osler, "The intellectual sources of Boyle's philosophy of nature: Gassendi's voluntarism and Boyle's physico-theological project", in R. Kroll, R. Ashcraft and P. Zagorin (eds), Philosophy, science and religion in England 1640-1700 (Cambridge, 1992), 178-98; J. T. Harwood, The early essays and ethics of Robert Boyle (Carbondale and Edwardsville, 1991) (for a review of Harwood's demonstration of the conventional character of Boyle's ethical writings, see Steven Shapin, "Personal development and intellectual biography: The case of Robert Boyle", The British journal for the history of science, xxvi (1993), 335-45; M. Oster, "Biography, culture, and science: The formative years of Robert Boyle", History of science, xxi (1993), 177-226, and "Virtue, providence and political neutralism: Boyle and Interregnum politics", in M. Hunter (ed.), Robert Boyle reconsidered (Cambridge, 1994), 19-36; Lawrence M. Principe, "Style and thought of the early Boyle: Discovery of the 1648 manuscript of Seraphic love", Isis, lxxxv (1994), 247-60.
    • (1994) Isis , vol.85 , pp. 247-260
    • Principe, L.M.1
  • 48
    • 84972605680 scopus 로고
    • How Boyle became a scientist
    • M. Hunter, "How Boyle became a scientist", History of science, xxxiii (1995), 59-103. For a different reconstruction of the beginnings of Boyle's scientific career, see J. R. Jacob "The ideological origins of Robert Boyle's natural philosophy", Journal of European studies, ii (1972), 1-21.
    • (1995) History of Science , vol.33 , pp. 59-103
    • Hunter, M.1
  • 49
    • 84965756687 scopus 로고
    • The ideological origins of Robert Boyle's natural philosophy
    • M. Hunter, "How Boyle became a scientist", History of science, xxxiii (1995), 59-103. For a different reconstruction of the beginnings of Boyle's scientific career, see J. R. Jacob "The ideological origins of Robert Boyle's natural philosophy", Journal of European studies, ii (1972), 1-21.
    • (1972) Journal of European Studies , vol.2 , pp. 1-21
    • Jacob, J.R.1
  • 50
    • 0346542298 scopus 로고
    • ed. by J. Spedding, R. L. Ellis and D. D. Heath 15 vols, London
    • Bacon, The works of Francis Bacon, ed. by J. Spedding, R. L. Ellis and D. D. Heath (15 vols, London, 1864-74), iii, 479.
    • (1864) The Works of Francis Bacon , vol.3 , pp. 479
    • Bacon1
  • 54
    • 84958139654 scopus 로고
    • Francis Bacon and the reform of society
    • Theodore K. Rabb and Jerrold E. Seigel, Princeton, It is important to note, therefore, that, however important was Boyle's debt to Bacon, it clearly did not pertain to reforming the relationship between religion and the study of nature. In this respect, Shapin and Schaffer's interpretation of Boyle's problem-situation is consistent with its minor attention to Bacon's philosophical writings (especially in comparison with 'method'-centred studies of Boyle's science, notably Sargent's The diffident naturalist, in which Bacon's legacy plays a prominent role): in as much as Boyle's experimental philosophy directly addressed the crisis of religious authority, it could hardly find assistance in, nor could it be based on Bacon's teachings
    • Novum Organum, Book I, lxv. For a study of Bacon's conservative outlook on religious reform, see Theodore K. Rabb, "Francis Bacon and the reform of society", in Theodore K. Rabb and Jerrold E. Seigel, Action and conviction in early modern Europe: Essays in memory of E. H. Harbison (Princeton, 1969), 169-93. It is important to note, therefore, that, however important was Boyle's debt to Bacon, it clearly did not pertain to reforming the relationship between religion and the study of nature. In this respect, Shapin and Schaffer's interpretation of Boyle's problem-situation is consistent with its minor attention to Bacon's philosophical writings (especially in comparison with 'method'-centred studies of Boyle's science, notably Sargent's The diffident naturalist, in which Bacon's legacy plays a prominent role): in as much as Boyle's experimental philosophy directly addressed the crisis of religious authority, it could hardly find assistance in, nor could it be based on Bacon's teachings.
    • (1969) Action and Conviction in Early Modern Europe: Essays in Memory of E. H. Harbison , pp. 169-193
    • Rabb, T.K.1
  • 55
    • 0003678946 scopus 로고
    • Hassocks
    • Bernard Williams, Descartes: The project of pure enquiry (Hassocks, 1978), 61; T. Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. by C. B. Macpherson (Harmondsworth, 1975), 117, 132-3; Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), 92-109.
    • (1978) Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry , pp. 61
    • Williams, B.1
  • 56
    • 0347172540 scopus 로고
    • ed. by C. B. Macpherson Harmondsworth
    • Bernard Williams, Descartes: The project of pure enquiry (Hassocks, 1978), 61; T. Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. by C. B. Macpherson (Harmondsworth, 1975), 117, 132-3; Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), 92-109.
    • (1975) Leviathan , vol.117 , pp. 132-133
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 57
    • 0345897083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 2
    • Bernard Williams, Descartes: The project of pure enquiry (Hassocks, 1978), 61; T. Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. by C. B. Macpherson (Harmondsworth, 1975), 117, 132-3; Shapin and Schaffer, Leviathan (ref. 2), 92-109.
    • Leviathan , pp. 92-109
    • Shapin1    Schaffer2
  • 58
    • 0347172514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some considerations touching the usefulness of experimental natural philosophy
    • ref. 12
    • Robert Boyle, "Some considerations touching the usefulness of experimental natural philosophy", in Works (ref. 12), i, 441.
    • Works , vol.1 , pp. 441
    • Boyle, R.1
  • 59
    • 85013289966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 439.
    • Works , pp. 439
  • 61
    • 0345911146 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), ii, 55.
    • Works , vol.2 , pp. 55
    • Boyle1
  • 62
    • 0345911151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), v, 162.
    • Works , vol.5 , pp. 162
    • Boyle1
  • 63
    • 85013271452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 170.
    • Works , pp. 170
  • 65
    • 0010856401 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Newton seems to have followed Boyle in renouncing the common assumption among philosophers that God's dominion could be understood by a methodical reflection upon created nature
    • Several years later, the objection to this common philosophical "error" was reiterated by Newton in a draft of the "General Scholium" of the Principia, where he explained that the proper use of reason was not confined to the assumption that nature was created by God: "He who shall demonstrate that there is a Perfect Being, and does not at the same lime demonstrate that he is Lord of the Universe or Pantokrator, will not yet have demonstrated that God exists. A Being eternal, infinite, allwise and most perfect without dominion is not God, but only Nature" (quoted from A. R. Hall and M. Boas Hall (eds), Unpublished scientific papers of Isaac Newton (Cambridge, 1978), 363). Newton seems to have followed Boyle in renouncing the common assumption among philosophers that God's dominion could be understood by a methodical reflection upon created nature.
    • (1978) Unpublished Scientific Papers of Isaac Newton , pp. 363
    • Hall, A.R.1    Boas Hall, M.2
  • 66
    • 0346542296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), v, 35.
    • Works , vol.5 , pp. 35
    • Boyle1
  • 67
    • 85013284754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • my emphasis
    • Ibid., 18, 21, my emphasis.
    • Works , pp. 18
  • 68
    • 85013264403 scopus 로고
    • Boyle
    • ref. 1 Bloomington
    • Early historical studies tended to attribute to Boyle a coherent "matter theory" whose underlying principles were mechanistic. See, for example, M. Boas Hall, "Boyle" (ref. 1), and Robert Boyle on natural philosophy: An essay with selections from his writings (Bloomington, 1965); R. S. Westfall, The construction of modern science (Cambridge, 1977), 49-50. Other studies demonstrated that Boyle's theological views rendered his mechanistic philosophy more complex. See, for example, McGuire, op. cit. (ref. 11); K. Hutchison, "What happened to occult qualities in the scientific revolution?", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 233-53, and "Supernaturalism and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxi (1983), 297-333. More recently, historians have highlighted the central place of non-mechanical qualities in his theory of matter. See, for example, John Henry, "Occult qualities and the experimental philosophy: Active principles in pre-Newtonian matter theory", History of science, xxiv (1986), 335-81; Simon Schaffer, "Occultism and reason", in A. J. Holland (ed.), Philosophy, its history and historiography (Dordrecht, 1985), 117-43, and "Godly men and mechanical philosophers: Souls and spirits in restoration natural philosophy", Science in context, i (1987), 55-85; A. Clericuzio, "A redefinition of Boyle's chemistry and corpuscular philosophy", Annals of science, xlvii (1990), 561-89. For a more philosophically analytic examination of Boyle's causal notion of the relational qualities of physical bodies, see R. J. O'Toole, "Qualities and powers in the corpuscular philosophy of Robert Boyle", Journal of the history of philosophy, xii (1974), 295-315.
    • (1965) Robert Boyle on Natural Philosophy: An Essay with Selections from His Writings
    • Boas Hall, M.1
  • 69
    • 0004304123 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • Early historical studies tended to attribute to Boyle a coherent "matter theory" whose underlying principles were mechanistic. See, for example, M. Boas Hall, "Boyle" (ref. 1), and Robert Boyle on natural philosophy: An essay with selections from his writings (Bloomington, 1965); R. S. Westfall, The construction of modern science (Cambridge, 1977), 49-50. Other studies demonstrated that Boyle's theological views rendered his mechanistic philosophy more complex. See, for example, McGuire, op. cit. (ref. 11); K. Hutchison, "What happened to occult qualities in the scientific revolution?", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 233-53, and "Supernaturalism and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxi (1983), 297-333. More recently, historians have highlighted the central place of non-mechanical qualities in his theory of matter. See, for example, John Henry, "Occult qualities and the experimental philosophy: Active principles in pre-Newtonian matter theory", History of science, xxiv (1986), 335-81; Simon Schaffer, "Occultism and reason", in A. J. Holland (ed.), Philosophy, its history and historiography (Dordrecht, 1985), 117-43, and "Godly men and mechanical philosophers: Souls and spirits in restoration natural philosophy", Science in context, i (1987), 55-85; A. Clericuzio, "A redefinition of Boyle's chemistry and corpuscular philosophy", Annals of science, xlvii (1990), 561-89. For a more philosophically analytic examination of Boyle's causal notion of the relational qualities of physical bodies, see R. J. O'Toole, "Qualities and powers in the corpuscular philosophy of Robert Boyle", Journal of the history of philosophy, xii (1974), 295-315.
    • (1977) The Construction of Modern Science , pp. 49-50
    • Westfall, R.S.1
  • 70
    • 0346542290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 11
    • Early historical studies tended to attribute to Boyle a coherent "matter theory" whose underlying principles were mechanistic. See, for example, M. Boas Hall, "Boyle" (ref. 1), and Robert Boyle on natural philosophy: An essay with selections from his writings (Bloomington, 1965); R. S. Westfall, The construction of modern science (Cambridge, 1977), 49-50. Other studies demonstrated that Boyle's theological views rendered his mechanistic philosophy more complex. See, for example, McGuire, op. cit. (ref. 11); K. Hutchison, "What happened to occult qualities in the scientific revolution?", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 233-53, and "Supernaturalism and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxi (1983), 297-333. More recently, historians have highlighted the central place of non-mechanical qualities in his theory of matter. See, for example, John Henry, "Occult qualities and the experimental philosophy: Active principles in pre-Newtonian matter theory", History of science, xxiv (1986), 335-81; Simon Schaffer, "Occultism and reason", in A. J. Holland (ed.), Philosophy, its history and historiography (Dordrecht, 1985), 117-43, and "Godly men and mechanical philosophers: Souls and spirits in restoration natural philosophy", Science in context, i (1987), 55-85; A. Clericuzio, "A redefinition of Boyle's chemistry and corpuscular philosophy", Annals of science, xlvii (1990), 561-89. For a more philosophically analytic examination of Boyle's causal notion of the relational qualities of physical bodies, see R. J. O'Toole, "Qualities and powers in the corpuscular philosophy of Robert Boyle", Journal of the history of philosophy, xii (1974), 295-315.
    • The Construction of Modern Science
    • McGuire1
  • 71
    • 0002496032 scopus 로고
    • What happened to occult qualities in the scientific revolution?
    • Early historical studies tended to attribute to Boyle a coherent "matter theory" whose underlying principles were mechanistic. See, for example, M. Boas Hall, "Boyle" (ref. 1), and Robert Boyle on natural philosophy: An essay with selections from his writings (Bloomington, 1965); R. S. Westfall, The construction of modern science (Cambridge, 1977), 49-50. Other studies demonstrated that Boyle's theological views rendered his mechanistic philosophy more complex. See, for example, McGuire, op. cit. (ref. 11); K. Hutchison, "What happened to occult qualities in the scientific revolution?", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 233-53, and "Supernaturalism and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxi (1983), 297-333. More recently, historians have highlighted the central place of non-mechanical qualities in his theory of matter. See, for example, John Henry, "Occult qualities and the experimental philosophy: Active principles in pre-Newtonian matter theory", History of science, xxiv (1986), 335-81; Simon Schaffer, "Occultism and reason", in A. J. Holland (ed.), Philosophy, its history and historiography (Dordrecht, 1985), 117-43, and "Godly men and mechanical philosophers: Souls and spirits in restoration natural philosophy", Science in context, i (1987), 55-85; A. Clericuzio, "A redefinition of Boyle's chemistry and corpuscular philosophy", Annals of science, xlvii (1990), 561-89. For a more philosophically analytic examination of Boyle's causal notion of the relational qualities of physical bodies, see R. J. O'Toole, "Qualities and powers in the corpuscular philosophy of Robert Boyle", Journal of the history of philosophy, xii (1974), 295-315.
    • (1982) Isis , vol.73 , pp. 233-253
    • Hutchison, K.1
  • 72
    • 84970479356 scopus 로고
    • Supernaturalism and the mechanical philosophy
    • Early historical studies tended to attribute to Boyle a coherent "matter theory" whose underlying principles were mechanistic. See, for example, M. Boas Hall, "Boyle" (ref. 1), and Robert Boyle on natural philosophy: An essay with selections from his writings (Bloomington, 1965); R. S. Westfall, The construction of modern science (Cambridge, 1977), 49-50. Other studies demonstrated that Boyle's theological views rendered his mechanistic philosophy more complex. See, for example, McGuire, op. cit. (ref. 11); K. Hutchison, "What happened to occult qualities in the scientific revolution?", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 233-53, and "Supernaturalism and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxi (1983), 297-333. More recently, historians have highlighted the central place of non-mechanical qualities in his theory of matter. See, for example, John Henry, "Occult qualities and the experimental philosophy: Active principles in pre-Newtonian matter theory", History of science, xxiv (1986), 335-81; Simon Schaffer, "Occultism and reason", in A. J. Holland (ed.), Philosophy, its history and historiography (Dordrecht, 1985), 117-43, and "Godly men and mechanical philosophers: Souls and spirits in restoration natural philosophy", Science in context, i (1987), 55-85; A. Clericuzio, "A redefinition of Boyle's chemistry and corpuscular philosophy", Annals of science, xlvii (1990), 561-89. For a more philosophically analytic examination of Boyle's causal notion of the relational qualities of physical bodies, see R. J. O'Toole, "Qualities and powers in the corpuscular philosophy of Robert Boyle", Journal of the history of philosophy, xii (1974), 295-315.
    • (1983) History of Science , vol.21 , pp. 297-333
  • 73
    • 84965737247 scopus 로고
    • Occult qualities and the experimental philosophy: Active principles in pre-Newtonian matter theory
    • Early historical studies tended to attribute to Boyle a coherent "matter theory" whose underlying principles were mechanistic. See, for example, M. Boas Hall, "Boyle" (ref. 1), and Robert Boyle on natural philosophy: An essay with selections from his writings (Bloomington, 1965); R. S. Westfall, The construction of modern science (Cambridge, 1977), 49-50. Other studies demonstrated that Boyle's theological views rendered his mechanistic philosophy more complex. See, for example, McGuire, op. cit. (ref. 11); K. Hutchison, "What happened to occult qualities in the scientific revolution?", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 233-53, and "Supernaturalism and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxi (1983), 297-333. More recently, historians have highlighted the central place of non-mechanical qualities in his theory of matter. See, for example, John Henry, "Occult qualities and the experimental philosophy: Active principles in pre-Newtonian matter theory", History of science, xxiv (1986), 335-81; Simon Schaffer, "Occultism and reason", in A. J. Holland (ed.), Philosophy, its history and historiography (Dordrecht, 1985), 117-43, and "Godly men and mechanical philosophers: Souls and spirits in restoration natural philosophy", Science in context, i (1987), 55-85; A. Clericuzio, "A redefinition of Boyle's chemistry and corpuscular philosophy", Annals of science, xlvii (1990), 561-89. For a more philosophically analytic examination of Boyle's causal notion of the relational qualities of physical bodies, see R. J. O'Toole, "Qualities and powers in the corpuscular philosophy of Robert Boyle", Journal of the history of philosophy, xii (1974), 295-315.
    • (1986) History of Science , vol.24 , pp. 335-381
    • Henry, J.1
  • 74
    • 0002160185 scopus 로고
    • Occultism and reason
    • A. J. Holland (ed.), Dordrecht
    • Early historical studies tended to attribute to Boyle a coherent "matter theory" whose underlying principles were mechanistic. See, for example, M. Boas Hall, "Boyle" (ref. 1), and Robert Boyle on natural philosophy: An essay with selections from his writings (Bloomington, 1965); R. S. Westfall, The construction of modern science (Cambridge, 1977), 49-50. Other studies demonstrated that Boyle's theological views rendered his mechanistic philosophy more complex. See, for example, McGuire, op. cit. (ref. 11); K. Hutchison, "What happened to occult qualities in the scientific revolution?", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 233-53, and "Supernaturalism and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxi (1983), 297-333. More recently, historians have highlighted the central place of non-mechanical qualities in his theory of matter. See, for example, John Henry, "Occult qualities and the experimental philosophy: Active principles in pre-Newtonian matter theory", History of science, xxiv (1986), 335-81; Simon Schaffer, "Occultism and reason", in A. J. Holland (ed.), Philosophy, its history and historiography (Dordrecht, 1985), 117-43, and "Godly men and mechanical philosophers: Souls and spirits in restoration natural philosophy", Science in context, i (1987), 55-85; A. Clericuzio, "A redefinition of Boyle's chemistry and corpuscular philosophy", Annals of science, xlvii (1990), 561-89. For a more philosophically analytic examination of Boyle's causal notion of the relational qualities of physical bodies, see R. J. O'Toole, "Qualities and powers in the corpuscular philosophy of Robert Boyle", Journal of the history of philosophy, xii (1974), 295-315.
    • (1985) Philosophy, Its History and Historiography , pp. 117-143
    • Schaffer, S.1
  • 75
    • 84976069326 scopus 로고
    • Godly men and mechanical philosophers: Souls and spirits in restoration natural philosophy
    • Early historical studies tended to attribute to Boyle a coherent "matter theory" whose underlying principles were mechanistic. See, for example, M. Boas Hall, "Boyle" (ref. 1), and Robert Boyle on natural philosophy: An essay with selections from his writings (Bloomington, 1965); R. S. Westfall, The construction of modern science (Cambridge, 1977), 49-50. Other studies demonstrated that Boyle's theological views rendered his mechanistic philosophy more complex. See, for example, McGuire, op. cit. (ref. 11); K. Hutchison, "What happened to occult qualities in the scientific revolution?", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 233-53, and "Supernaturalism and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxi (1983), 297-333. More recently, historians have highlighted the central place of non-mechanical qualities in his theory of matter. See, for example, John Henry, "Occult qualities and the experimental philosophy: Active principles in pre-Newtonian matter theory", History of science, xxiv (1986), 335-81; Simon Schaffer, "Occultism and reason", in A. J. Holland (ed.), Philosophy, its history and historiography (Dordrecht, 1985), 117-43, and "Godly men and mechanical philosophers: Souls and spirits in restoration natural philosophy", Science in context, i (1987), 55-85; A. Clericuzio, "A redefinition of Boyle's chemistry and corpuscular philosophy", Annals of science, xlvii (1990), 561-89. For a more philosophically analytic examination of Boyle's causal notion of the relational qualities of physical bodies, see R. J. O'Toole, "Qualities and powers in the corpuscular philosophy of Robert Boyle", Journal of the history of philosophy, xii (1974), 295-315.
    • (1987) Science in Context , vol.1 , pp. 55-85
  • 76
    • 0025519169 scopus 로고
    • A redefinition of Boyle's chemistry and corpuscular philosophy
    • Early historical studies tended to attribute to Boyle a coherent "matter theory" whose underlying principles were mechanistic. See, for example, M. Boas Hall, "Boyle" (ref. 1), and Robert Boyle on natural philosophy: An essay with selections from his writings (Bloomington, 1965); R. S. Westfall, The construction of modern science (Cambridge, 1977), 49-50. Other studies demonstrated that Boyle's theological views rendered his mechanistic philosophy more complex. See, for example, McGuire, op. cit. (ref. 11); K. Hutchison, "What happened to occult qualities in the scientific revolution?", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 233-53, and "Supernaturalism and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxi (1983), 297-333. More recently, historians have highlighted the central place of non-mechanical qualities in his theory of matter. See, for example, John Henry, "Occult qualities and the experimental philosophy: Active principles in pre-Newtonian matter theory", History of science, xxiv (1986), 335-81; Simon Schaffer, "Occultism and reason", in A. J. Holland (ed.), Philosophy, its history and historiography (Dordrecht, 1985), 117-43, and "Godly men and mechanical philosophers: Souls and spirits in restoration natural philosophy", Science in context, i (1987), 55-85; A. Clericuzio, "A redefinition of Boyle's chemistry and corpuscular philosophy", Annals of science, xlvii (1990), 561-89. For a more philosophically analytic examination of Boyle's causal notion of the relational qualities of physical bodies, see R. J. O'Toole, "Qualities and powers in the corpuscular philosophy of Robert Boyle", Journal of the history of philosophy, xii (1974), 295-315.
    • (1990) Annals of Science , vol.47 , pp. 561-589
    • Clericuzio, A.1
  • 77
    • 0009881158 scopus 로고
    • Qualities and powers in the corpuscular philosophy of Robert Boyle
    • Early historical studies tended to attribute to Boyle a coherent "matter theory" whose underlying principles were mechanistic. See, for example, M. Boas Hall, "Boyle" (ref. 1), and Robert Boyle on natural philosophy: An essay with selections from his writings (Bloomington, 1965); R. S. Westfall, The construction of modern science (Cambridge, 1977), 49-50. Other studies demonstrated that Boyle's theological views rendered his mechanistic philosophy more complex. See, for example, McGuire, op. cit. (ref. 11); K. Hutchison, "What happened to occult qualities in the scientific revolution?", Isis, lxxiii (1982), 233-53, and "Supernaturalism and the mechanical philosophy", History of science, xxi (1983), 297-333. More recently, historians have highlighted the central place of non-mechanical qualities in his theory of matter. See, for example, John Henry, "Occult qualities and the experimental philosophy: Active principles in pre-Newtonian matter theory", History of science, xxiv (1986), 335-81; Simon Schaffer, "Occultism and reason", in A. J. Holland (ed.), Philosophy, its history and historiography (Dordrecht, 1985), 117-43, and "Godly men and mechanical philosophers: Souls and spirits in restoration natural philosophy", Science in context, i (1987), 55-85; A. Clericuzio, "A redefinition of Boyle's chemistry and corpuscular philosophy", Annals of science, xlvii (1990), 561-89. For a more philosophically analytic examination of Boyle's causal notion of the relational qualities of physical bodies, see R. J. O'Toole, "Qualities and powers in the corpuscular philosophy of Robert Boyle", Journal of the history of philosophy, xii (1974), 295-315.
    • (1974) Journal of the History of Philosophy , vol.12 , pp. 295-315
    • O'Toole, R.J.1
  • 78
    • 0347802525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), v, 524.
    • Works , vol.5 , pp. 524
    • Boyle1
  • 79
    • 85013229552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 540.
    • Works , pp. 540
  • 80
    • 84882415489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 2
    • Dear, Discipline (ref. 2), 48-50, 101-5, 227-32. See also L. Daston, "Baconian facts, academic civility, and the prehistory of objectivity", Annals of scholarship, viii (1991), 337-63. Dear and Daston explained Boyle's conception of experience in accordance with Shapin and Schaffer's thesis, but, in accordance with Popkin's thesis, they claimed that the social crisis of authority was confined to neither England nor the Restoration era. Daston accordingly emphasized Boyle's debt to Bacon, in this respect, as against Shapin and Schaffer's thesis, which minimized its significance. Her view seems to have been later endorsed by S. Shapin, in his A Social history of truth: Civility and science in seventeenth-century England (Chicago, 1994).
    • Discipline , pp. 48-50
    • Dear1
  • 81
    • 0000231183 scopus 로고
    • Baconian facts, academic civility, and the prehistory of objectivity
    • Dear, Discipline (ref. 2), 48-50, 101-5, 227-32. See also L. Daston, "Baconian facts, academic civility, and the prehistory of objectivity", Annals of scholarship, viii (1991), 337-63. Dear and Daston explained Boyle's conception of experience in accordance with Shapin and Schaffer's thesis, but, in accordance with Popkin's thesis, they claimed that the social crisis of authority was confined to neither England nor the Restoration era. Daston accordingly emphasized Boyle's debt to Bacon, in this respect, as against Shapin and Schaffer's thesis, which minimized its significance. Her view seems to have been later endorsed by S. Shapin, in his A Social history of truth: Civility and science in seventeenth-century England (Chicago, 1994).
    • (1991) Annals of Scholarship , vol.8 , pp. 337-363
    • Daston, L.1
  • 82
    • 0003757606 scopus 로고
    • Chicago
    • Dear, Discipline (ref. 2), 48-50, 101-5, 227-32. See also L. Daston, "Baconian facts, academic civility, and the prehistory of objectivity", Annals of scholarship, viii (1991), 337-63. Dear and Daston explained Boyle's conception of experience in accordance with Shapin and Schaffer's thesis, but, in accordance with Popkin's thesis, they claimed that the social crisis of authority was confined to neither England nor the Restoration era. Daston accordingly emphasized Boyle's debt to Bacon, in this respect, as against Shapin and Schaffer's thesis, which minimized its significance. Her view seems to have been later endorsed by S. Shapin, in his A Social history of truth: Civility and science in seventeenth-century England (Chicago, 1994).
    • (1994) A Social History of Truth: Civility and Science in Seventeenth-century England
    • Shapin, S.1
  • 83
    • 0346542267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), ii, 29.
    • Works , vol.2 , pp. 29
    • Boyle1
  • 85
    • 0004033932 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • W. Haller, in his The rise of Puritanism (New York, 1957), esp. pp. 83-127, demonstrated that the propagation of popular piety by preachers was in part the result of the political inability of Puritan leaders to establish a Reformation from above. Thus, religious conduct in everyday life became the most important domain of Puritan reform. Haller's thesis is further elaborated in Peter Lake, Moderate Puritans and the Elizabethan Church (Cambridge, 1982). For studies of Puritan piety in everyday life, see also Christopher Hill, Society and Puritanism in pre-Revolutionary England (New York, 1964); O. C. Watkins, The Puritan experience (London, 1972); John Morgan, Godly learning: Puritan attitudes towards reason, learning, and education, 1560-1640 (Cambridge, 1986), esp. pp. 142-71; Margo Todd, Christian humanism and the puritan social order (Cambridge, 1987).
    • (1957) The Rise of Puritanism , pp. 83-127
    • Haller, W.1
  • 86
    • 0040547250 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • W. Haller, in his The rise of Puritanism (New York, 1957), esp. pp. 83-127, demonstrated that the propagation of popular piety by preachers was in part the result of the political inability of Puritan leaders to establish a Reformation from above. Thus, religious conduct in everyday life became the most important domain of Puritan reform. Haller's thesis is further elaborated in Peter Lake, Moderate Puritans and the Elizabethan Church (Cambridge, 1982). For studies of Puritan piety in everyday life, see also Christopher Hill, Society and Puritanism in pre-Revolutionary England (New York, 1964); O. C. Watkins, The Puritan experience (London, 1972); John Morgan, Godly learning: Puritan attitudes towards reason, learning, and education, 1560-1640 (Cambridge, 1986), esp. pp. 142-71; Margo Todd, Christian humanism and the puritan social order (Cambridge, 1987).
    • (1982) Moderate Puritans and the Elizabethan Church
    • Lake, P.1
  • 87
    • 0039034960 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • W. Haller, in his The rise of Puritanism (New York, 1957), esp. pp. 83-127, demonstrated that the propagation of popular piety by preachers was in part the result of the political inability of Puritan leaders to establish a Reformation from above. Thus, religious conduct in everyday life became the most important domain of Puritan reform. Haller's thesis is further elaborated in Peter Lake, Moderate Puritans and the Elizabethan Church (Cambridge, 1982). For studies of Puritan piety in everyday life, see also Christopher Hill, Society and Puritanism in pre-Revolutionary England (New York, 1964); O. C. Watkins, The Puritan experience (London, 1972); John Morgan, Godly learning: Puritan attitudes towards reason, learning, and education, 1560-1640 (Cambridge, 1986), esp. pp. 142-71; Margo Todd, Christian humanism and the puritan social order (Cambridge, 1987).
    • (1964) Society and Puritanism in Pre-Revolutionary England
    • Hill, C.1
  • 88
    • 0011158529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London
    • W. Haller, in his The rise of Puritanism (New York, 1957), esp. pp. 83-127, demonstrated that the propagation of popular piety by preachers was in part the result of the political inability of Puritan leaders to establish a Reformation from above. Thus, religious conduct in everyday life became the most important domain of Puritan reform. Haller's thesis is further elaborated in
    • (1972) The Puritan Experience
    • Watkins, O.C.1
  • 89
    • 0003674256 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • W. Haller, in his The rise of Puritanism (New York, 1957), esp. pp. 83-127, demonstrated that the propagation of popular piety by preachers was in part the result of the political inability of Puritan leaders to establish a Reformation from above. Thus, religious conduct in everyday life became the most important domain of Puritan reform. Haller's thesis is further elaborated in Peter Lake, Moderate Puritans and the Elizabethan Church (Cambridge, 1982). For studies of Puritan piety in everyday life, see also Christopher Hill, Society and Puritanism in pre-Revolutionary England (New York, 1964); O. C. Watkins, The Puritan experience (London, 1972); John Morgan, Godly learning: Puritan attitudes towards reason, learning, and education, 1560-1640 (Cambridge, 1986), esp. pp. 142-71; Margo Todd, Christian humanism and the puritan social order (Cambridge, 1987).
    • (1986) Godly Learning: Puritan Attitudes Towards Reason, Learning, and Education, 1560-1640 , pp. 142-171
    • Morgan, J.1
  • 90
    • 0009855873 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • W. Haller, in his The rise of Puritanism (New York, 1957), esp. pp. 83-127, demonstrated that the propagation of popular piety by preachers was in part the result of the political inability of Puritan leaders to establish a Reformation from above. Thus, religious conduct in everyday life became the most important domain of Puritan reform. Haller's thesis is further elaborated in Peter Lake, Moderate Puritans and the Elizabethan Church (Cambridge, 1982). For studies of Puritan piety in everyday life, see also Christopher Hill, Society and Puritanism in pre-Revolutionary England (New York, 1964); O. C. Watkins, The Puritan experience (London, 1972); John Morgan, Godly learning: Puritan attitudes towards reason, learning, and education, 1560-1640 (Cambridge, 1986), esp. pp. 142-71; Margo Todd, Christian humanism and the puritan social order (Cambridge, 1987).
    • (1987) Christian Humanism and the Puritan Social Order
    • Todd, M.1
  • 93
    • 0011158529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 43
    • John Rogers, Ohel or Beth-Shemesh: A tabernacle for the sun (London, 1653), 354. Quoted from Watkins, The Puritan experience (ref. 43), 29.
    • The Puritan Experience , pp. 29
    • Watkins1
  • 94
    • 0346542262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12, Note, however, that Boyle's statement, in this context, does not show that he was a Puritan, and the Puritans' discussion about the religious experiment does not mean that such an experiment was only relevant to Puritanism. By virtue of its internal organization during the first decades of the seventeenth century, Puritanism was a very effective vehicle of reform, especially of religious practices of relatively educated people, and the historical evidence shows, at least, a similarity between Boyle's view and the common view among Puritans. The similarity is indirectly supported by the aforementioned studies on Puritanism which show how Puritans propagated views that were very often accepted by other clergymen with a humanist background in England and other Protestant communities
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), vi, 717. Note, however, that Boyle's statement, in this context, does not show that he was a Puritan, and the Puritans' discussion about the religious experiment does not mean that such an experiment was only relevant to Puritanism. By virtue of its internal organization during the first decades of the seventeenth century, Puritanism was a very effective vehicle of reform, especially of religious practices of relatively educated people, and the historical evidence shows, at least, a similarity between Boyle's view and the common view among Puritans. The similarity is indirectly supported by the aforementioned studies on Puritanism which show how Puritans propagated views that were very often accepted by other clergymen with a humanist background in England and other Protestant communities.
    • Works , vol.6 , pp. 717
    • Boyle1
  • 95
    • 0347172523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), vi, 715.
    • Works , vol.6 , pp. 715
    • Boyle1
  • 96
    • 84870789968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 26
    • Hobbes, Leviathan (ref. 26), 147-8.
    • Leviathan , pp. 147-148
    • Hobbes1
  • 97
    • 0346542271 scopus 로고
    • ed. by C. Adam and P. Tannery 12 vols, Paris
    • René Descartes, Oeuvres de Descartes, ed. by C. Adam and P. Tannery (12 vols, Paris, 1897-1910), iii, 39. Quoted from Ralph M. Blake, Curt J. Ducasse and Edward H. Madden, Theories of scientific method: The Renaissance through the nineteenth century (New York, 1989), 76. See also Garber, "Descartes" (ref. 9).
    • (1897) Oeuvres de Descartes , vol.3 , pp. 39
    • Descartes, R.1
  • 99
    • 0347802538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 9
    • René Descartes, Oeuvres de Descartes, ed. by C. Adam and P. Tannery (12 vols, Paris, 1897-1910), iii, 39. Quoted from Ralph M. Blake, Curt J. Ducasse and Edward H. Madden, Theories of scientific method: The Renaissance through the nineteenth century (New York, 1989), 76. See also Garber, "Descartes" (ref. 9).
    • Descartes
    • Garber1
  • 100
    • 0347172524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), i, 262.
    • Works , vol.1 , pp. 262
    • Boyle1
  • 101
    • 0347172525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), v, 539.
    • Works , vol.5 , pp. 539
    • Boyle1
  • 102
    • 0346542291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), iv, 597.
    • Works , vol.4 , pp. 597
    • Boyle1
  • 103
    • 0004206497 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • The intellectual value of signs had always been recognized by philosophers, but it was often construed in terms of the methodology of empirical inference rather than the explication of the fundamental principles of natural causality. Gassendi and Bacon, for example, pointed out that the interpretation of signs could establish true empirical correlations. Thus, Gassendi argued that the proof of pores in the skin was valid because it was indubitably inferred from the appearance of sweat over the skin, while Bacon noted that natural history could similarly demonstrate the correlation between heat and friction. For the inferior status of these correlations compared to the philosophical explication of natural causality, see Ian Hacking, The emergence of probability (Cambridge, 1975), 39-48; Howard T. Egan, Gassendi's view of knowledge: A study of the epistemological basis of his logic (New York, 1984), esp. pp. 77-84; Lisa T. Sarasohn, Gassendi's ethics: Freedom in a mechanistic universe (Ithaca, 1996), esp. pp. 39-48; Bacon, Works (ref. 21), i, 236-56, 261-8; iv, 127-55; Lisa Jardine, Francis Bacon: Discovery and the art of discourse (Cambridge, 1974), esp. pp. 109-32; Antonio Perez-Ramos, Francis Bacon's idea of science and the maker's knowledge tradition (Oxford, 1988), esp. pp. 243-54.
    • (1975) The Emergence of Probability , pp. 39-48
    • Hacking, I.1
  • 104
    • 0345911168 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • The intellectual value of signs had always been recognized by philosophers, but it was often construed in terms of the methodology of empirical inference rather than the explication of the fundamental principles of natural causality. Gassendi and Bacon, for example, pointed out that the interpretation of signs could establish true empirical correlations. Thus, Gassendi argued that the proof of pores in the skin was valid because it was indubitably inferred from the appearance of sweat over the skin, while Bacon noted that natural history could similarly demonstrate the correlation between heat and friction. For the inferior status of these correlations compared to the philosophical explication of natural causality, see Ian Hacking, The emergence of probability (Cambridge, 1975), 39-48; Howard T. Egan, Gassendi's view of knowledge: A study of the epistemological basis of his logic (New York, 1984), esp. pp. 77-84; Lisa T. Sarasohn, Gassendi's ethics: Freedom in a mechanistic universe (Ithaca, 1996), esp. pp. 39-48; Bacon, Works (ref. 21), i, 236-56, 261-8; iv, 127-55; Lisa Jardine, Francis Bacon: Discovery and the art of discourse (Cambridge, 1974), esp. pp. 109-32; Antonio Perez-Ramos, Francis Bacon's idea of science and the maker's knowledge tradition (Oxford, 1988), esp. pp. 243-54.
    • (1984) Gassendi's View of Knowledge: A Study of the Epistemological Basis of his Logic , pp. 77-84
    • Egan, H.T.1
  • 105
    • 0002240381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca
    • The intellectual value of signs had always been recognized by philosophers, but it was often construed in terms of the methodology of empirical inference rather than the explication of the fundamental principles of natural causality. Gassendi and Bacon, for example, pointed out that the interpretation of signs could establish true empirical correlations. Thus, Gassendi argued that the proof of pores in the skin was valid because it was indubitably inferred from the appearance of sweat over the skin, while Bacon noted that natural history could similarly demonstrate the correlation between heat and friction. For the inferior status of these correlations compared to the philosophical explication of natural causality, see Ian Hacking, The emergence of probability (Cambridge, 1975), 39-48; Howard T. Egan, Gassendi's view of knowledge: A study of the epistemological basis of his logic (New York, 1984), esp. pp. 77-84; Lisa T. Sarasohn, Gassendi's ethics: Freedom in a mechanistic universe (Ithaca, 1996), esp. pp. 39-48; Bacon, Works (ref. 21), i, 236-56, 261-8; iv, 127-55; Lisa Jardine, Francis Bacon: Discovery and the art of discourse (Cambridge, 1974), esp. pp. 109-32; Antonio Perez-Ramos, Francis Bacon's idea of science and the maker's knowledge tradition (Oxford, 1988), esp. pp. 243-54.
    • (1996) Gassendi's Ethics: Freedom in a Mechanistic Universe , pp. 39-48
    • Sarasohn, L.T.1
  • 106
    • 0347802543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 21
    • The intellectual value of signs had always been recognized by philosophers, but it was often construed in terms of the methodology of empirical inference rather than the explication of the fundamental principles of natural causality. Gassendi and Bacon, for example, pointed out that the interpretation of signs could establish true empirical correlations. Thus, Gassendi argued that the proof of pores in the skin was valid because it was indubitably inferred from the appearance of sweat over the skin, while Bacon noted that natural history could similarly demonstrate the correlation between heat and friction. For the inferior status of these correlations compared to the philosophical explication of natural causality, see Ian Hacking, The emergence of probability (Cambridge, 1975), 39-48; Howard T. Egan, Gassendi's view of knowledge: A study of the epistemological basis of his logic (New York, 1984), esp. pp. 77-84; Lisa T. Sarasohn, Gassendi's ethics: Freedom in a mechanistic universe (Ithaca, 1996), esp. pp. 39-48; Bacon, Works (ref. 21), i, 236-56, 261-8; iv, 127-55; Lisa Jardine, Francis Bacon: Discovery and the art of discourse (Cambridge, 1974), esp. pp. 109-32; Antonio Perez-Ramos, Francis Bacon's idea of science and the maker's knowledge tradition (Oxford, 1988), esp. pp. 243-54.
    • Works , vol.1 , pp. 236-256
    • Bacon1
  • 107
    • 33749442544 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The intellectual value of signs had always been recognized by philosophers, but it was often construed in terms of the methodology of empirical inference rather than the explication of the fundamental principles of natural causality. Gassendi and Bacon, for example, pointed out that the interpretation of signs could establish true empirical correlations. Thus, Gassendi argued that the proof of pores in the skin was valid because it was indubitably inferred from the appearance of sweat over the skin, while Bacon noted that natural history could similarly demonstrate the correlation between heat and friction. For the inferior status of these correlations compared to the philosophical explication of natural causality, see Ian Hacking, The emergence of probability (Cambridge, 1975), 39-48; Howard T. Egan, Gassendi's view of knowledge: A study of the epistemological basis of his logic (New York, 1984), esp. pp. 77-84; Lisa T. Sarasohn, Gassendi's ethics: Freedom in a mechanistic universe (Ithaca, 1996), esp. pp. 39-48; Bacon, Works (ref. 21), i, 236-56, 261-8; iv, 127-55; Lisa Jardine, Francis Bacon: Discovery and the art of discourse (Cambridge, 1974), esp. pp. 109-32; Antonio Perez-Ramos, Francis Bacon's idea of science and the maker's knowledge tradition (Oxford, 1988), esp. pp. 243-54.
    • Works , vol.4 , pp. 127-155
  • 108
    • 0004065294 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • The intellectual value of signs had always been recognized by philosophers, but it was often construed in terms of the methodology of empirical inference rather than the explication of the fundamental principles of natural causality. Gassendi and Bacon, for example, pointed out that the interpretation of signs could establish true empirical correlations. Thus, Gassendi argued that the proof of pores in the skin was valid because it was indubitably inferred from the appearance of sweat over the skin, while Bacon noted that natural history could similarly demonstrate the correlation between heat and friction. For the inferior status of these correlations compared to the philosophical explication of natural causality, see Ian Hacking, The emergence of probability (Cambridge, 1975), 39-48; Howard T. Egan, Gassendi's view of knowledge: A study of the epistemological basis of his logic (New York, 1984), esp. pp. 77-84; Lisa T. Sarasohn, Gassendi's ethics: Freedom in a mechanistic universe (Ithaca, 1996), esp. pp. 39-48; Bacon, Works (ref. 21), i, 236-56, 261-8; iv, 127-55; Lisa Jardine, Francis Bacon: Discovery and the art of discourse (Cambridge, 1974), esp. pp. 109-32; Antonio Perez-Ramos, Francis Bacon's idea of science and the maker's knowledge tradition (Oxford, 1988), esp. pp. 243-54.
    • (1974) Francis Bacon: Discovery and the Art of Discourse , pp. 109-132
    • Jardine, L.1
  • 109
    • 0003849390 scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • The intellectual value of signs had always been recognized by philosophers, but it was often construed in terms of the methodology of empirical inference rather than the explication of the fundamental principles of natural causality. Gassendi and Bacon, for example, pointed out that the interpretation of signs could establish true empirical correlations. Thus, Gassendi argued that the proof of pores in the skin was valid because it was indubitably inferred from the appearance of sweat over the skin, while Bacon noted that natural history could similarly demonstrate the correlation between heat and friction. For the inferior status of these correlations compared to the philosophical explication of natural causality, see Ian Hacking, The emergence of probability (Cambridge, 1975), 39-48; Howard T. Egan, Gassendi's view of knowledge: A study of the epistemological basis of his logic (New York, 1984), esp. pp. 77-84; Lisa T. Sarasohn, Gassendi's ethics: Freedom in a mechanistic universe (Ithaca, 1996), esp. pp. 39-48; Bacon, Works (ref. 21), i, 236-56, 261-8; iv, 127-55; Lisa Jardine, Francis Bacon: Discovery and the art of discourse (Cambridge, 1974), esp. pp. 109-32; Antonio Perez-Ramos, Francis Bacon's idea of science and the maker's knowledge tradition (Oxford, 1988), esp. pp. 243-54.
    • (1988) Francis Bacon's Idea of Science and the Maker's Knowledge Tradition , pp. 243-254
    • Perez-Ramos, A.1
  • 110
    • 0346542273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), v, 3, 6, 17.
    • Works , vol.5 , pp. 3
    • Boyle1
  • 111
    • 0346542274 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), ii, 170.
    • Works , vol.2 , pp. 170
    • Boyle1
  • 112
    • 0345911169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), iii, 47.
    • Works , vol.3 , pp. 47
    • Boyle1
  • 113
    • 0028412807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), iv, 416. For detailed studies of Boyle's religious views on the limits of human reasoning, see Lotte Mulligan, "Robert Boyle, 'Right reason', and the meaning of metaphor", Journal of the history of ideas, lv (1994), 235-57; Wojcik, Boyle (ref. 11).
    • Works , vol.4 , pp. 416
    • Boyle1
  • 114
    • 0028412807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert Boyle, 'Right reason', and the meaning of metaphor
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), iv, 416. For detailed studies of Boyle's religious views on the limits of human reasoning, see Lotte Mulligan, "Robert Boyle, 'Right reason', and the meaning of metaphor", Journal of the history of ideas, lv (1994), 235-57; Wojcik, Boyle (ref. 11).
    • (1994) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.55 , pp. 235-257
    • Mulligan, L.1
  • 115
    • 0028412807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 11
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), iv, 416. For detailed studies of Boyle's religious views on the limits of human reasoning, see Lotte Mulligan, "Robert Boyle, 'Right reason', and the meaning of metaphor", Journal of the history of ideas, lv (1994), 235-57; Wojcik, Boyle (ref. 11).
    • Boyle
    • Wojcik1
  • 116
    • 0347172534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), ii, 45. For Boyle's critique of the language of chemical explanation, see A. Clericuzio, "Carneades and the chemists: A study of The sceptical chymist and its impact on seventeenth-century chemistry", in Hunter (ed.), Robert Boyle (ref. 19), 79-90.
    • Works , vol.2 , pp. 45
    • Boyle1
  • 117
    • 0001949205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carneades and the chemists: A study of the sceptical chymist and its impact on seventeenth-century chemistry
    • Hunter (ed.), ref. 19
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), ii, 45. For Boyle's critique of the language of chemical explanation, see A. Clericuzio, "Carneades and the chemists: A study of The sceptical chymist and its impact on seventeenth-century chemistry", in Hunter (ed.), Robert Boyle (ref. 19), 79-90.
    • Robert Boyle , pp. 79-90
    • Clericuzio, A.1
  • 118
    • 0347802542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), iv, 453.
    • Works , vol.4 , pp. 453
    • Boyle1
  • 119
    • 0347172526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), i, 404.
    • Works , vol.1 , pp. 404
    • Boyle1
  • 120
    • 85013297455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 309.
    • Works , pp. 309
  • 122
    • 0347802537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle often compared the spring of air to the elasticity of wool, an analogy he apparently borrowed from Pascal. In "The general history of the air" he listed several mechanical images, and noted his debt to Descartes. See Boyle, Works (ref. 12), v, 613-15; B. Pascal, Traité de la pesanteur de la masse d'air (Paris, 1956), 34-40.
    • Works , vol.5 , pp. 613-615
    • Boyle1
  • 123
    • 0345911167 scopus 로고
    • Paris
    • Boyle often compared the spring of air to the elasticity of wool, an analogy he apparently borrowed from Pascal. In "The general history of the air" he listed several mechanical images, and noted his debt to Descartes. See Boyle, Works (ref. 12), v, 613-15; B. Pascal, Traité de la pesanteur de la masse d'air (Paris, 1956), 34-40.
    • (1956) Traité de la Pesanteur de la Masse d'Air , pp. 34-40
    • Pascal, B.1
  • 124
    • 0347172537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), i, 33.
    • Works , vol.1 , pp. 33
    • Boyle1
  • 126
    • 0346542287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ref. 12
    • Boyle, Works (ref. 12), iii, 274-6.
    • Works , vol.3 , pp. 274-276
    • Boyle1
  • 127
    • 85013313682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 274.
    • Works , pp. 274
  • 128
    • 84996254603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Doctrine and use: Newton's 'gift of preaching'
    • which highlights the analogy between Newton's research in optics and Boyle's experimental pneumatics
    • The explanatory value and rhetorical function of the experimental report as a presentation of an experimental technique is further discussed in M. Ben-Chaim, "Doctrine and use: Newton's 'gift of preaching'", History of science, xxxvi (1998), 269-98, which highlights the analogy between Newton's research in optics and Boyle's experimental pneumatics.
    • (1998) History of Science , vol.36 , pp. 269-298
    • Ben-Chaim, M.1
  • 130
  • 131
    • 0000266280 scopus 로고
    • Totius in verba: Rhetoric and authority in the early Royal Society
    • As the title of his paper suggests, Dear claimed that the Society's emphasis on the practical value of experimental philosophy was predominantly a rhetorical gesture whose intention was to warrant the authority of experimental records. Following Popkin, Dear construed the experimental programme as a response to the crisis of scepticism, and for this reason his interpretation focused on the rhetoric of valid inference. The discipline of divine service and the mission of the gifted experimenter discussed in this paper explain, from a different perspective, how practice became the crucial dimension of the programme, at least as it was presented in Boyle's career. According to this interpretation, rhetoric accompanied the practice of transmitting God's gift but did not and, arguably, could not replace it
    • For a different interpretation of the Society's motto, see P. Dear, "Totius in verba: Rhetoric and authority in the early Royal Society", Isis, lxxvi (1985), 145-61. As the title of his paper suggests, Dear claimed that the Society's emphasis on the practical value of experimental philosophy was predominantly a rhetorical gesture whose intention was to warrant the authority of experimental records. Following Popkin, Dear construed the experimental programme as a response to the crisis of scepticism, and for this reason his interpretation focused on the rhetoric of valid inference. The discipline of divine service and the mission of the gifted experimenter discussed in this paper explain, from a different perspective, how practice became the crucial dimension of the programme, at least as it was presented in Boyle's career. According to this interpretation, rhetoric accompanied the practice of transmitting God's gift but did not and, arguably, could not replace it.
    • (1985) Isis , vol.76 , pp. 145-161
    • Dear, P.1
  • 133
    • 77950041748 scopus 로고
    • ed. by Peter H. Nidditch Oxford
    • J. Locke, An essay concerning human understanding, ed. by Peter H. Nidditch (Oxford, 1975), 9; J. Marshall, John Locke: Resistance, religion and responsibility (Cambridge, 1994), 9-11, 30-31.
    • (1975) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding , pp. 9
    • Locke, J.1
  • 135
    • 0004206947 scopus 로고
    • New York
    • I. Newton, Opticks (New York, 1952), 405.
    • (1952) Opticks , pp. 405
    • Newton, I.1
  • 136
    • 0009877256 scopus 로고
    • Treatise on revelation
    • Frank E. Manuel, Oxford
    • I. Newton, "Treatise on revelation", in Frank E. Manuel, The religion of Isaac Newton (Oxford, 1974), 113.
    • (1974) The Religion of Isaac Newton , pp. 113
    • Newton, I.1
  • 137
    • 34247943652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • transl. by W. D. Halls London, published originally in French in 1935
    • There are numerous anthropological studies on the reciprocation of gifts which are based on ethnographic evidence linking the collective satisfaction of human needs to benevolent deities. The classical statement on this subject is M. Mauss, The gift: The form and reason for exchange in archaic societies, transl. by W. D. Halls (London, 1990), published originally in French in 1935. For more recent studies, see for example, E. P. Thompson, "The moral economy of the English crowd in the eighteenth century", Past and present, 1 (1971), 76-136; C. Campbell, The Romantic ethic and the spirit of modern consumerism (Oxford, 1987); D. Cheal, The gift economy (London, 1988); J. Carrier, "Gifts, commodities, and social relations: A Maussian view of exchange", Sociological forum, vi (1991), 119-36; Alan D. Schrift (ed.), The logic of the gift: Toward an ethic of generosity (New York, 1997).
    • (1990) The Gift: the Form and Reason for Exchange in Archaic Societies
    • Mauss, M.1
  • 138
    • 34247943652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The moral economy of the English crowd in the eighteenth century
    • There are numerous anthropological studies on the reciprocation of gifts which are based on ethnographic evidence linking the collective satisfaction of human needs to benevolent deities. The classical statement on this subject is M. Mauss, The gift: The form and reason for exchange in archaic societies, transl. by W. D. Halls (London, 1990), published originally in French in 1935. For more recent studies, see for example, E. P. Thompson, "The moral economy of the English crowd in the eighteenth century", Past and present, 1 (1971), 76-136; C. Campbell, The Romantic ethic and the spirit of modern consumerism (Oxford, 1987); D. Cheal, The gift economy (London, 1988); J. Carrier, "Gifts, commodities, and social relations: A Maussian view of exchange", Sociological forum, vi (1991), 119-36; Alan D. Schrift (ed.), The logic of the gift: Toward an ethic of generosity (New York, 1997).
    • (1971) Past and Present , vol.1 , pp. 76-136
    • Thompson, E.P.1
  • 139
    • 34247943652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford
    • There are numerous anthropological studies on the reciprocation of gifts which are based on ethnographic evidence linking the collective satisfaction of human needs to benevolent deities. The classical statement on this subject is M. Mauss, The gift: The form and reason for exchange in archaic societies, transl. by W. D. Halls (London, 1990), published originally in French in 1935. For more recent studies, see for example, E. P. Thompson, "The moral economy of the English crowd in the eighteenth century", Past and present, 1 (1971), 76-136; C. Campbell, The Romantic ethic and the spirit of modern consumerism (Oxford, 1987); D. Cheal, The gift economy (London, 1988); J. Carrier, "Gifts, commodities, and social relations: A Maussian view of exchange", Sociological forum, vi (1991), 119-36; Alan D. Schrift (ed.), The logic of the gift: Toward an ethic of generosity (New York, 1997).
    • (1987) The Romantic Ethic and the Spirit of Modern Consumerism
    • Campbell, C.1
  • 140
    • 34247943652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London
    • There are numerous anthropological studies on the reciprocation of gifts which are based on ethnographic evidence linking the collective satisfaction of human needs to benevolent deities. The classical statement on this subject is M. Mauss, The gift: The form and reason for exchange in archaic societies, transl. by W. D. Halls (London, 1990), published originally in French in 1935. For more recent studies, see for example, E. P. Thompson, "The moral economy of the English crowd in the eighteenth century", Past and present, 1 (1971), 76-136; C. Campbell, The Romantic ethic and the spirit of modern consumerism (Oxford, 1987); D. Cheal, The gift economy (London, 1988); J. Carrier, "Gifts, commodities, and social relations: A Maussian view of exchange", Sociological forum, vi (1991), 119-36; Alan D. Schrift (ed.), The logic of the gift: Toward an ethic of generosity (New York, 1997).
    • (1988) The Gift Economy
    • Cheal, D.1
  • 141
    • 0000014293 scopus 로고
    • Gifts, commodities, and social relations: A Maussian view of exchange
    • There are numerous anthropological studies on the reciprocation of gifts which are based on ethnographic evidence linking the collective satisfaction of human needs to benevolent deities. The classical statement on this subject is M. Mauss, The gift: The form and reason for exchange in archaic societies, transl. by W. D. Halls (London, 1990), published originally in French in 1935. For more recent studies, see for example, E. P. Thompson, "The moral economy of the English crowd in the eighteenth century", Past and present, 1 (1971), 76-136; C. Campbell, The Romantic ethic and the spirit of modern consumerism (Oxford, 1987); D. Cheal, The gift economy (London, 1988); J. Carrier, "Gifts, commodities, and social relations: A Maussian view of exchange", Sociological forum, vi (1991), 119-36; Alan D. Schrift (ed.), The logic of the gift: Toward an ethic of generosity (New York, 1997).
    • (1991) Sociological Forum , vol.6 , pp. 119-136
    • Carrier, J.1
  • 142
    • 34247943652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York
    • There are numerous anthropological studies on the reciprocation of gifts which are based on ethnographic evidence linking the collective satisfaction of human needs to benevolent deities. The classical statement on this subject is M. Mauss, The gift: The form and reason for exchange in archaic societies, transl. by W. D. Halls (London, 1990), published originally in French in 1935. For more recent studies, see for example, E. P. Thompson, "The moral economy of the English crowd in the eighteenth century", Past and present, 1 (1971), 76-136; C. Campbell, The Romantic ethic and the spirit of modern consumerism (Oxford, 1987); D. Cheal, The gift economy (London, 1988); J. Carrier, "Gifts, commodities, and social relations: A Maussian view of exchange", Sociological forum, vi (1991), 119-36; Alan D. Schrift (ed.), The logic of the gift: Toward an ethic of generosity (New York, 1997).
    • (1997) The Logic of the Gift: Toward an Ethic of Generosity
    • Schrift, A.D.1
  • 144
    • 0004021580 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca
    • For the ascendance of science as a new social power in relation to the traditional cultural dominance of the Church in late seventeenth-century and eighteenth-century England, see M. C. Jacob, The Newtonians and the English Revolution, 1689-1720 (Ithaca, 1976); L. Stewart, The rise of public science: Rhetoric, technology, and natural philosophy in Newtonian Britain, 1660-1750 (Cambridge, 1992); P. Fara, Sympathetic attractions: Magnetic practices, beliefs and symbolism in eighteenth-century England (Princeton, 1996).
    • (1976) The Newtonians and the English Revolution, 1689-1720
    • Jacob, M.C.1
  • 145
    • 0003847984 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge
    • For the ascendance of science as a new social power in relation to the traditional cultural dominance of the Church in late seventeenth-century and eighteenth-century England, see M. C. Jacob, The Newtonians and the English Revolution, 1689-1720 (Ithaca, 1976); L. Stewart, The rise of public science: Rhetoric, technology, and natural philosophy in Newtonian Britain, 1660-1750 (Cambridge, 1992); P. Fara, Sympathetic attractions: Magnetic practices, beliefs and symbolism in eighteenth-century England (Princeton, 1996).
    • (1992) The Rise of Public Science: Rhetoric, Technology, and Natural Philosophy in Newtonian Britain, 1660-1750
    • Stewart, L.1
  • 146
    • 0003519115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton
    • For the ascendance of science as a new social power in relation to the traditional cultural dominance of the Church in late seventeenth-century and eighteenth-century England, see M. C. Jacob, The Newtonians and the English Revolution, 1689-1720 (Ithaca, 1976); L. Stewart, The rise of public science: Rhetoric, technology, and natural philosophy in Newtonian Britain, 1660-1750 (Cambridge, 1992); P. Fara, Sympathetic attractions: Magnetic practices, beliefs and symbolism in eighteenth-century England (Princeton, 1996).
    • (1996) Sympathetic Attractions: Magnetic Practices, Beliefs and Symbolism in Eighteenth-century England
    • Fara, P.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.