메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 108, Issue 2, 1998, Pages 367-385

Philosophical intuitions and psychological theory

(1)  Horowitz, Tamara a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0000400416     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/233809     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (45)

References (20)
  • 1
    • 0009404476 scopus 로고
    • Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Warren Quinn, "Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing," in his Morality and Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 149.
    • (1993) Morality and Action , pp. 149
    • Quinn, W.1
  • 2
    • 0013602838 scopus 로고
    • Killing and Letting Die
    • ed. Jay Garfield Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press
    • The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing and this thought experiment are orginally the work of Professor P. Foote. See P. Foote, "Killing and Letting Die," in Abortion: Moral and Legal Perspectives, ed. Jay Garfield (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1984), pp. 178-85.
    • (1984) Abortion: Moral and Legal Perspectives , pp. 178-185
    • Foote, P.1
  • 3
    • 85034200324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Quinn, p. 152
    • Quinn, p. 152.
  • 4
    • 85034188004 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 167
    • Ibid., p. 167.
  • 5
    • 0000125532 scopus 로고
    • Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk
    • For an account of prospect theory, see D. Kahneman and A. Tversky, "Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk," Econometrica 47 (1979): 263-91.
    • (1979) Econometrica , vol.47 , pp. 263-291
    • Kahneman, D.1    Tversky, A.2
  • 8
    • 85034192586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Problem 2 is obtained from problem 1 by increasing the original amount by $200 and subtracting this amount from both options.
  • 9
    • 85034202187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • An expected-utility maximizer would not exhibit this pattern, since any person who is maximizing expected utility would choose the first option in each problem or the second option in each problem.
  • 10
    • 85034168945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The other operations include combining probabilities associated with identical outcomes, segregating risky from riskless components of prospects, discarding components that are shared by all of the available prospects, rounding off probabilities or outcomes, and rejecting dominated alternatives. For a full discussion of these processes, see Kahneman and Tversky, p. 274.
  • 11
    • 85034157680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Positive and negative prospects are evaluated in the following way. In the editing phase, they are segregated into two components, a riskless component which is the minimum loss or gain certain to be received and a risky component comprised of the additional gain or loss at stake. These prospects are then evaluated in the following way: if p + q = 1 and either x > y > 0 or x < y < 0, then D(x, p; y, q) = v(y) + w(p)[v(x) - v(y)]. This value equals the value of the riskless component, plus the difference between the two outcomes multiplied by the weight associated with the outcome with the greater absolute value. See Kahneman and Tversky, p. 276.
  • 12
    • 85034199998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kahneman and Tversky, p. 279
    • Kahneman and Tversky, p. 279.
  • 13
    • 85034169724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Notice that no such hypothesis is needed for the analysis of the experiments reported by Kahneman and Tversky. They are concerned to explain the order in which subjects prefer certain possible actions in different decision problems. To do this, they must hypothesize that, in each decision problem, a subject arrives at a D value for various alternative actions, but they are never required to hypothesize that these D values can be compared from one decision problem to the other.
  • 14
    • 85034174498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Nevertheless, I suspect prospect theory does explain most of these intuitions, although I will not try to survey them here.
  • 15
    • 85034186933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is a version of an objection offered by one of the editors of Ethics.
  • 16
    • 85034174221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am especially indebted to Joseph Camp for many helpful discussions of the issues treated in this section.
  • 17
    • 85034194203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Assume that I am at a gym and that I am wearing my glasses. A thief to my left steals my pocketbook off a chair. Fortunately, there is a police officer in uniform to my right. Then, (a) the thief to my left stealing my pocketbook is a reason for (b) my calling to the police officer to my right. If my glasses are off, I will not be so lucky because (c) the dark figure to my left holding a dark object is not a reason for (d) my calling to the dark figure to my right. One can argue that (a) and (c) are strictly identical states and that (b) and (d) are strictly identical states. 'Is a reason for' resembles 'implies' in its logic.
  • 18
    • 0039570950 scopus 로고
    • Empirical Foundations of Linguistic Theory
    • ed. R. Austerlitz Ghent: Peter De Ridder
    • See W. Labov, "Empirical Foundations of Linguistic Theory," in The Scope of American Linguistics, ed. R. Austerlitz (Ghent: Peter De Ridder, 1975), pp. 77-133;
    • (1975) The Scope of American Linguistics , pp. 77-133
    • Labov, W.1
  • 19
    • 0010058754 scopus 로고
    • Differences between Linguists and Nonlinguists in Intuitions of Grammaticality-Acceptability
    • cited in Labov
    • and N. Spencer, "Differences between Linguists and Nonlinguists in Intuitions of Grammaticality-Acceptability," Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 2 (1973): 83-98 (cited in Labov).
    • (1973) Journal of Psycholinguistic Research , vol.2 , pp. 83-98
    • Spencer, N.1
  • 20
    • 0004083939 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press
    • It was called to my attention after this article was written that Robert Nozick points to the "strong similarity" between the doing and allowing distinction and framing effects in R. Nozick, The Nature of Rationality (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995), p. 60.
    • (1995) The Nature of Rationality , pp. 60
    • Nozick, R.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.